2.1 Metaphysical Emergence and Homeostatic Organization
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41
In the previous chapter, the attempt was made to show that the processes
in which the components of an organismic hierarchy are engaged produce
homeostasis through abilities to exchange data internally, selectively
convert data to information, integrate that information, and process information
from environments. Now, it will be argued that the components
and attending processes of an organism should be considered as emergent
phenomena because of the way in which the components are organized
to maintain the homeostasis of the organism at the various levels in the
organismic hierarchy (also see Arp, 2008a).
Near the end of the fi rst section of the previous chapter, the claim was
made that higher level subsystems are the phenomena that literally emerge
from lower level subsystems and processes of an organism conceived of as
a hierarchically organized living entity. With respect to organisms and the
descriptions of their components, processes, and properties, I endorse
certain forms of metaphysical and epistemological emergence. As Silberstein
(2002), Silberstein & McGreever (1999), and McLaughlin (1992, 1997)
have clarifi ed, there are metaphysical and epistemological forms of emergence.
In Kim’s (1995, p. 224) words, according to metaphysical emergentists,
“a property of a complex system is said to be ‘emergent’ just in case,
although it arises out of the properties and relations characterizing simpler
constituents, it is neither predictable from, nor reducible to, these lowerlevel
characteristics” (also see the discussions in Kim, 1999; Wimsatt, 1994,
1997; Emmeche, Køppe, & Stjernfelt, 2000; Craver, 2001; Lowe, 2000;
O’Connor, 1994; Rueger, 2000; Zylstra, 1992). According to epistemological
emergentists, the concepts, theories, models, or frameworks we utilize
to describe phenomena at a certain level are nonreducible to the concepts,
theories, and so forth at a lower level (see, e.g., the discussions in Batterman, 2001; Cartwright, 1999; Primas, 1998; Sklar, 1999; Dupré, 1993;
Crane, 2001; Van Gulick, 2001).
Further, as Silberstein (2002) and Silberstein & McGeever (1999) clarify,
within the genus of metaphysical emergence, four kinds have been distinguished,
namely, non-elimination, nonidentity, mereological emergence,
and nomological emergence. Also, within the genus of epistemological
emergence, at least two kinds of approaches have been distinguished,
namely, predictive/explanatory emergence and representational/cognitive
emergence. In light of the previous chapter, the metaphysical and epistemological
forms of emergence that will be explored and defended in this
chapter are the following: nomological emergence, understood by Silberstein
(2002, p. 91) as “cases in which higher-level entities, properties, etc., are
governed by higher-level laws that are not determined by or necessitated
by the fundamental laws of physics governing the structure and behavior
of their most basic physical parts,” and representational/cognitive emergence,
understood by Silberstein (2002, p. 92) as the thesis that “wholes (systems)
exhibit features, patterns or regularities that cannot be fully represented
(understood) using the theoretical and representational resources adequate
for describing and understanding the features and regularities of their more
basic parts and the relations between those more basic parts.”
From the metaphysical perspective, nomological emergentists deny the
general principle that the whole can be accounted for fully in terms of the
physical parts, and so their view is contrasted with nomological reductionism.
According to nomological reductionists, there are really no entities,
properties, or substances that arise out of more fundamental physical
ones, since, once the more fundamental ones have been described, that
is all there is to the reality of an entity, property, or substance. Thus, for
example, when people speak about water, they may take it to be a substance
in its own right. However, according to the nomological reductionist,
water just is hydrogen and oxygen—nothing new emerges when two
hydrogen molecules combine with one oxygen molecule. Conversely,
according to a nomological emergentist, there is something about water—
for example, its liquidity or liquid property—that emerges from the hydrogen
and oxygen molecules, making it such that this liquidity exists on a
separate metaphysical plane from the molecules on which it depends.
After all, reason nomological emergentists, liquidity appears to be something
distinct from hydrogen and oxygen molecules, as well as their
chemical bond.
From the epistemological perspective, representational emergentists are
contrasted with representational/theoretical reductionists, who attempt to reduce concepts, theories, and so forth to their lowest common
denominator, as it were, and this usually means a description in terms
of physicochemical entities, properties, or substances and their attending
laws or principles. Thus, if we took the cell as an example, according
to a representational reductionist, the cell can be described completely
within a physicochemical framework of concepts, theories, models, laws,
and so forth associated with vectors and physical substructures and
bonds (see the discussions in Churchland, 1995; Humphreys, 1997;
Primas, 1998).
Some emergentists maintain that chemical bonds or basic physical
structures—as well as our descriptions of them—are nonreducible to the
molecules and atoms of which they are composed. Thus, there is an
emergence–reduction divide even at the physicochemical level (see, e.g.,
the discussions in Hendry, 1999; Hellman, 1999; Belot & Earman, 1997).
This physicochemical debate is avoided here, and instead I want to maintain
that starting with the organelles that constitute a cell, and continuing
up the hierarchy of components in processes and subsystems of an organism—
including psychological phenomena—we have clear instances of
emergent phenomena. The fundamental reason why these components
and their attending processes must be considered as emergent phenomena
has to do with the way in which the components are organized to
function so as to maintain the homeostasis of the organism at the various
levels in the hierarchy. I will refer to this position as the homeostatic
organization view (HOV) of biological phenomena. Since homeostasis
is ubiquitous as both a concept and as a recognized reality in biological,
psychological, and philosophical communities (among many other disciplines),
it makes for a natural point of discussion in the emergence/reduction
debate.
In the fi rst section of the previous chapter, a distinction was drawn
between particularized homeostasis and generalized homeostasis. It was
shown that because the various processes and subsystems of an organism
are functioning properly in their internal environments (particularized
homeostasis), the organism is able to live its life effectively in some environment
external to it (generalized homeostasis). Here, the very existence
of components and their activities at various levels in the organism’s hierarchy
is linked to the coordination of such components so as ultimately
to produce generalized homeostasis. The components of an organism are
organized in such a way that the resultant outcome of their processes becomes
fi rst particularized homeostasis and then generalized homeostasis.
That components are organized to perform some function resulting in homeostasis is one feature that marks them out to be novel emergent
entities distinguishable from the very physicochemical processes of which
they are composed.
It was noted already that homeostasis fi rst occurs at the basic level of
the organized coordination of the activities of organelles in a cell. Researchers
like Audesirk et al. (2002), Kandel et al. (2000), Voet et al. (2002),
Campbell & Reece (1999), and Smolensky (1988) document cellular homeostasis.
At this basic level of organelle interaction within the cell, we also
would have the fi rst instances of salient emergent biological properties that
are distinct from the physicochemical properties upon which they depend.
Consider all of the information being exchanged between and among the
organelles of an animal cell. The nucleus is in constant communication
with each mitochondrion, centriole, golgi apparatus, ribosome, and endoplasmic
reticulum, each of which has its own function in maintaining the
overall homeostasis of the cell (see fi gure 2.1): the nucleus contains the
nucleolus and houses DNA, the mitochondrion supplies the cell with
energy, centrioles are important for cell division, the Golgi apparatus stores
Ribosomes
Endoplasmic
Reticulum
Nucleus
Nucleolus
Centriole
Golgi
Apparatus
Plasma
Membrane
Mitochondrion
Figure 2.1
The major organelles of the animal cell proteins, ribosomes are the sites for protein synthesis, the endoplasmic
reticulum expedites the transport of cellular material, and the plasma
membrane permits materials to move into and out of the cell.
In fact, components of organisms as they have been described—
organelles, cells, organs, and subsystems, as well as the organism itself—all
would be considered emergent entities. Referring to the schematization
of an organism as one huge triangle containing smaller triangles that was
used in fi gure 1.1 of the previous chapter, each one of those triangles—
from biggest to smallest—represents a biologically emergent phenomenon.
For example, although the organelles of a cell themselves are made up of
physicochemical entities, they engage in coordinated kinds of activities
that benefi t the overall homeostasis of the cell; so too, although kidney
cells are made up of organelles—which are made up of physicochemical
entities—the kidney cells themselves engage in coordinated activities that
benefi t the homeostasis of the kidney; and so on, up the hierarchy of the
mammal. This point was reiterated in my discussions with Jerry Morrissey
at his lab at Washington University in St. Louis, where Morrissey conducts
research on kidney cells (see the fi nal section of Kaneto, Morrissey,
McCracken, Reyes, & Klahr, 1998).
Now, in arguing for HOV, I am not advocating some “spooky stuff”
principle (this terminology is borrowed from Churchland, 1993) of internal
“vitalism” or external “design,” the likes of which might be put forward
by an organicist or a creationist (also see Arp, 1998, 1999, 2002). As was
mentioned in the last chapter, the property of internal–hierarchical data
exchange in an organism manifests upward causation, whereby the lower
levels of the hierarchy exhibit causal infl uence over the higher levels.
Likewise, the dual properties of data selectivity and informational integration
manifest downward causation, whereby the higher levels of the hierarchy
exhibit causal infl uence over the lower levels, in terms of control.
Consider that an organism like the human body is a complex multicllular
entity made up of levels of independently organized entities
that perform certain operations. These organized entities are hierarchically
arranged from organ systems (e.g., the nervous system), composed of
organs (brain, spinal cord, etc.), that are composed of tissues (nervous
tissue), which are composed of cells (neurons, glial cells), each of which is
composed of organelles (mitochondrion, nucleus, etc.), that are composed
of organic molecules (carbon, nitrogen, oxygen, DNA, etc.). Each of these
entities functions such that the operations at the lower levels contribute
to the emergence of entities and their operations at the higher levels.
Because of the activities of organic molecules, it is possible for organelles and their attending activities at a higher level to emerge, and because of
the activities of organelles, it is possible for cells and their attending activities
at a higher level to emerge, and so on.
Now, think of all of the complex upward and downward causal relations
taking place when the human body simply gets up out of bed. Put crudely,
the brain must exhibit downward causation, as a necessary condition,
upon its own neurochemical constituents in order to cause the body to get
up, while the neurochemical constituents must exhibit upward causation,
as a necessary condition, for movement to occur in the fi rst place. There
is no “spooky” vitalism or design in any of this upward and downward
causal interaction.
In fact, HOV provides an important addition to one standard interpretation
of a hierarchical mechanism. In philosophy of science and philosophy
of mind literature, it is now commonplace to fi nd references to Craver’s
(2001) Cummins-infl uenced description of a mechanism hierarchy as some
mechanism S, which is -ing, composed of smaller entity Xs, which are
-ing. These Xs are little mechanisms themselves consisting of smaller
entity Ps, which are -ing (also see Machamer, Darden, & Craver, 2000).
This view has the benefi t of describing some mechanism as a hierarchically
organized system, in a nonspooky fashion, consisting of entities engaging
in inter- and intraleveled causally effi cacious activities. Also, this view is
specifi cally supposed to account for living mechanisms, which classically
have resisted a mechanistic description. In fact, Craver’s view of a hierarchical
mechanism maps onto my schematization of a hierarchically organized
system schematized as nested triangles, and our two views have
much in common.
However, as I pointed out to Carl Craver at a conference at Washington
University in St. Louis, the problem with his view of mechanisms is that
it neglects the more specifi ed kinds of organized homeostatic activities in
which the processes of organismic hierarchies are engaged. It is arguable
that physicochemical entities—the so-called smaller entity Ps, which are
-ing, that make up the organelles, which are -ing—themselves are not
coordinated in such a way so as to produce homeostatic results; they are
not organized to do something, or achieve some result in this homeostatic
manner. Further, it is arguable that physicochemical entities are not
organized in hierarchical ways such that we could say they are engaged
in particularized homeostatic processes contributing to a generalized
homeostasis.
Organisms are responsive to their environments in such a way that they
can adapt to changes. A callous on your foot is a simple example of the integumentary subsystem of your body adapting to a change in its external
environment. Organisms, as well as the subsystems and processes of which
they are composed, exhibit a certain amount of fl exibility and malleability
in relation to their internal and external environments. In fact, as we have
already seen, the subsystems and processes of organisms produce particularized
and generalized homeostasis, namely, a relatively constant coordination
among the components of an organism, given the interaction
of these components with environments internal to and external to the
organism. Homeostasis and adaptability are two sides of the same coin. As
was intimated already, this property of adaptability in relation to environments
is yet another essential feature that distinguishes living entities,
properties, or substances from nonliving ones. Another way to say this is
that the adaptability of processes and subsystems in organisms can be
pointed to as a clear way in which to distinguish the biological from the
physicochemical realms.
Consider a rock. A rock would be classifi ed as a nonliving, physicochemical
entity because it does not have this ability to adapt to environments
and situations the way that living, biological entities do. If a rock
is hit by a hammer with a certain amount of force, it breaks up into
pieces, the pieces fall where they may according to physicochemical laws,
and that is the end of the story—this is its “response” to the environment.
Alternatively, if one’s forearm is hit by a hammer such that a bone
breaks, the various systems of the body go to work to repair the damage
so that some form of homeostasis can be reachieved. The body adaptively
responds to this environmental pressure, and the hierarchy goes to work
on fi xing the problem. Further, if the bone does not heal correctly or the
muscles surrounding it have atrophied because of the blow, the subsystems
and processes of the body can compensate for the injury. If the hierarchy
cannot fi x the problem, it adjusts or readjusts if necessary.
Homeostasis in an organism entails adaptability as a necessary condition,
for it is the organism’s response to its ever-changing environment that
will occasion the need for either particularized or generalized homeostasis.
Of course, biological entities are constructed of physicochemical components
and are subject to the same physicochemical laws as any other
piece of matter in the world; again, there is upward physicochemical causation
that acts as a necessary condition for biological functioning.
However, biological entities, as hierarchically organized living systems,
have this distinguishing property whereby the subsystems and processes
adaptively respond to their environments in ways that other physicochemical
entities do not.
In the previous chapter, the attempt was made to show that the processes
in which the components of an organismic hierarchy are engaged produce
homeostasis through abilities to exchange data internally, selectively
convert data to information, integrate that information, and process information
from environments. Now, it will be argued that the components
and attending processes of an organism should be considered as emergent
phenomena because of the way in which the components are organized
to maintain the homeostasis of the organism at the various levels in the
organismic hierarchy (also see Arp, 2008a).
Near the end of the fi rst section of the previous chapter, the claim was
made that higher level subsystems are the phenomena that literally emerge
from lower level subsystems and processes of an organism conceived of as
a hierarchically organized living entity. With respect to organisms and the
descriptions of their components, processes, and properties, I endorse
certain forms of metaphysical and epistemological emergence. As Silberstein
(2002), Silberstein & McGreever (1999), and McLaughlin (1992, 1997)
have clarifi ed, there are metaphysical and epistemological forms of emergence.
In Kim’s (1995, p. 224) words, according to metaphysical emergentists,
“a property of a complex system is said to be ‘emergent’ just in case,
although it arises out of the properties and relations characterizing simpler
constituents, it is neither predictable from, nor reducible to, these lowerlevel
characteristics” (also see the discussions in Kim, 1999; Wimsatt, 1994,
1997; Emmeche, Køppe, & Stjernfelt, 2000; Craver, 2001; Lowe, 2000;
O’Connor, 1994; Rueger, 2000; Zylstra, 1992). According to epistemological
emergentists, the concepts, theories, models, or frameworks we utilize
to describe phenomena at a certain level are nonreducible to the concepts,
theories, and so forth at a lower level (see, e.g., the discussions in Batterman, 2001; Cartwright, 1999; Primas, 1998; Sklar, 1999; Dupré, 1993;
Crane, 2001; Van Gulick, 2001).
Further, as Silberstein (2002) and Silberstein & McGeever (1999) clarify,
within the genus of metaphysical emergence, four kinds have been distinguished,
namely, non-elimination, nonidentity, mereological emergence,
and nomological emergence. Also, within the genus of epistemological
emergence, at least two kinds of approaches have been distinguished,
namely, predictive/explanatory emergence and representational/cognitive
emergence. In light of the previous chapter, the metaphysical and epistemological
forms of emergence that will be explored and defended in this
chapter are the following: nomological emergence, understood by Silberstein
(2002, p. 91) as “cases in which higher-level entities, properties, etc., are
governed by higher-level laws that are not determined by or necessitated
by the fundamental laws of physics governing the structure and behavior
of their most basic physical parts,” and representational/cognitive emergence,
understood by Silberstein (2002, p. 92) as the thesis that “wholes (systems)
exhibit features, patterns or regularities that cannot be fully represented
(understood) using the theoretical and representational resources adequate
for describing and understanding the features and regularities of their more
basic parts and the relations between those more basic parts.”
From the metaphysical perspective, nomological emergentists deny the
general principle that the whole can be accounted for fully in terms of the
physical parts, and so their view is contrasted with nomological reductionism.
According to nomological reductionists, there are really no entities,
properties, or substances that arise out of more fundamental physical
ones, since, once the more fundamental ones have been described, that
is all there is to the reality of an entity, property, or substance. Thus, for
example, when people speak about water, they may take it to be a substance
in its own right. However, according to the nomological reductionist,
water just is hydrogen and oxygen—nothing new emerges when two
hydrogen molecules combine with one oxygen molecule. Conversely,
according to a nomological emergentist, there is something about water—
for example, its liquidity or liquid property—that emerges from the hydrogen
and oxygen molecules, making it such that this liquidity exists on a
separate metaphysical plane from the molecules on which it depends.
After all, reason nomological emergentists, liquidity appears to be something
distinct from hydrogen and oxygen molecules, as well as their
chemical bond.
From the epistemological perspective, representational emergentists are
contrasted with representational/theoretical reductionists, who attempt to reduce concepts, theories, and so forth to their lowest common
denominator, as it were, and this usually means a description in terms
of physicochemical entities, properties, or substances and their attending
laws or principles. Thus, if we took the cell as an example, according
to a representational reductionist, the cell can be described completely
within a physicochemical framework of concepts, theories, models, laws,
and so forth associated with vectors and physical substructures and
bonds (see the discussions in Churchland, 1995; Humphreys, 1997;
Primas, 1998).
Some emergentists maintain that chemical bonds or basic physical
structures—as well as our descriptions of them—are nonreducible to the
molecules and atoms of which they are composed. Thus, there is an
emergence–reduction divide even at the physicochemical level (see, e.g.,
the discussions in Hendry, 1999; Hellman, 1999; Belot & Earman, 1997).
This physicochemical debate is avoided here, and instead I want to maintain
that starting with the organelles that constitute a cell, and continuing
up the hierarchy of components in processes and subsystems of an organism—
including psychological phenomena—we have clear instances of
emergent phenomena. The fundamental reason why these components
and their attending processes must be considered as emergent phenomena
has to do with the way in which the components are organized to
function so as to maintain the homeostasis of the organism at the various
levels in the hierarchy. I will refer to this position as the homeostatic
organization view (HOV) of biological phenomena. Since homeostasis
is ubiquitous as both a concept and as a recognized reality in biological,
psychological, and philosophical communities (among many other disciplines),
it makes for a natural point of discussion in the emergence/reduction
debate.
In the fi rst section of the previous chapter, a distinction was drawn
between particularized homeostasis and generalized homeostasis. It was
shown that because the various processes and subsystems of an organism
are functioning properly in their internal environments (particularized
homeostasis), the organism is able to live its life effectively in some environment
external to it (generalized homeostasis). Here, the very existence
of components and their activities at various levels in the organism’s hierarchy
is linked to the coordination of such components so as ultimately
to produce generalized homeostasis. The components of an organism are
organized in such a way that the resultant outcome of their processes becomes
fi rst particularized homeostasis and then generalized homeostasis.
That components are organized to perform some function resulting in homeostasis is one feature that marks them out to be novel emergent
entities distinguishable from the very physicochemical processes of which
they are composed.
It was noted already that homeostasis fi rst occurs at the basic level of
the organized coordination of the activities of organelles in a cell. Researchers
like Audesirk et al. (2002), Kandel et al. (2000), Voet et al. (2002),
Campbell & Reece (1999), and Smolensky (1988) document cellular homeostasis.
At this basic level of organelle interaction within the cell, we also
would have the fi rst instances of salient emergent biological properties that
are distinct from the physicochemical properties upon which they depend.
Consider all of the information being exchanged between and among the
organelles of an animal cell. The nucleus is in constant communication
with each mitochondrion, centriole, golgi apparatus, ribosome, and endoplasmic
reticulum, each of which has its own function in maintaining the
overall homeostasis of the cell (see fi gure 2.1): the nucleus contains the
nucleolus and houses DNA, the mitochondrion supplies the cell with
energy, centrioles are important for cell division, the Golgi apparatus stores
Ribosomes
Endoplasmic
Reticulum
Nucleus
Nucleolus
Centriole
Golgi
Apparatus
Plasma
Membrane
Mitochondrion
Figure 2.1
The major organelles of the animal cell proteins, ribosomes are the sites for protein synthesis, the endoplasmic
reticulum expedites the transport of cellular material, and the plasma
membrane permits materials to move into and out of the cell.
In fact, components of organisms as they have been described—
organelles, cells, organs, and subsystems, as well as the organism itself—all
would be considered emergent entities. Referring to the schematization
of an organism as one huge triangle containing smaller triangles that was
used in fi gure 1.1 of the previous chapter, each one of those triangles—
from biggest to smallest—represents a biologically emergent phenomenon.
For example, although the organelles of a cell themselves are made up of
physicochemical entities, they engage in coordinated kinds of activities
that benefi t the overall homeostasis of the cell; so too, although kidney
cells are made up of organelles—which are made up of physicochemical
entities—the kidney cells themselves engage in coordinated activities that
benefi t the homeostasis of the kidney; and so on, up the hierarchy of the
mammal. This point was reiterated in my discussions with Jerry Morrissey
at his lab at Washington University in St. Louis, where Morrissey conducts
research on kidney cells (see the fi nal section of Kaneto, Morrissey,
McCracken, Reyes, & Klahr, 1998).
Now, in arguing for HOV, I am not advocating some “spooky stuff”
principle (this terminology is borrowed from Churchland, 1993) of internal
“vitalism” or external “design,” the likes of which might be put forward
by an organicist or a creationist (also see Arp, 1998, 1999, 2002). As was
mentioned in the last chapter, the property of internal–hierarchical data
exchange in an organism manifests upward causation, whereby the lower
levels of the hierarchy exhibit causal infl uence over the higher levels.
Likewise, the dual properties of data selectivity and informational integration
manifest downward causation, whereby the higher levels of the hierarchy
exhibit causal infl uence over the lower levels, in terms of control.
Consider that an organism like the human body is a complex multicllular
entity made up of levels of independently organized entities
that perform certain operations. These organized entities are hierarchically
arranged from organ systems (e.g., the nervous system), composed of
organs (brain, spinal cord, etc.), that are composed of tissues (nervous
tissue), which are composed of cells (neurons, glial cells), each of which is
composed of organelles (mitochondrion, nucleus, etc.), that are composed
of organic molecules (carbon, nitrogen, oxygen, DNA, etc.). Each of these
entities functions such that the operations at the lower levels contribute
to the emergence of entities and their operations at the higher levels.
Because of the activities of organic molecules, it is possible for organelles and their attending activities at a higher level to emerge, and because of
the activities of organelles, it is possible for cells and their attending activities
at a higher level to emerge, and so on.
Now, think of all of the complex upward and downward causal relations
taking place when the human body simply gets up out of bed. Put crudely,
the brain must exhibit downward causation, as a necessary condition,
upon its own neurochemical constituents in order to cause the body to get
up, while the neurochemical constituents must exhibit upward causation,
as a necessary condition, for movement to occur in the fi rst place. There
is no “spooky” vitalism or design in any of this upward and downward
causal interaction.
In fact, HOV provides an important addition to one standard interpretation
of a hierarchical mechanism. In philosophy of science and philosophy
of mind literature, it is now commonplace to fi nd references to Craver’s
(2001) Cummins-infl uenced description of a mechanism hierarchy as some
mechanism S, which is -ing, composed of smaller entity Xs, which are
-ing. These Xs are little mechanisms themselves consisting of smaller
entity Ps, which are -ing (also see Machamer, Darden, & Craver, 2000).
This view has the benefi t of describing some mechanism as a hierarchically
organized system, in a nonspooky fashion, consisting of entities engaging
in inter- and intraleveled causally effi cacious activities. Also, this view is
specifi cally supposed to account for living mechanisms, which classically
have resisted a mechanistic description. In fact, Craver’s view of a hierarchical
mechanism maps onto my schematization of a hierarchically organized
system schematized as nested triangles, and our two views have
much in common.
However, as I pointed out to Carl Craver at a conference at Washington
University in St. Louis, the problem with his view of mechanisms is that
it neglects the more specifi ed kinds of organized homeostatic activities in
which the processes of organismic hierarchies are engaged. It is arguable
that physicochemical entities—the so-called smaller entity Ps, which are
-ing, that make up the organelles, which are -ing—themselves are not
coordinated in such a way so as to produce homeostatic results; they are
not organized to do something, or achieve some result in this homeostatic
manner. Further, it is arguable that physicochemical entities are not
organized in hierarchical ways such that we could say they are engaged
in particularized homeostatic processes contributing to a generalized
homeostasis.
Organisms are responsive to their environments in such a way that they
can adapt to changes. A callous on your foot is a simple example of the integumentary subsystem of your body adapting to a change in its external
environment. Organisms, as well as the subsystems and processes of which
they are composed, exhibit a certain amount of fl exibility and malleability
in relation to their internal and external environments. In fact, as we have
already seen, the subsystems and processes of organisms produce particularized
and generalized homeostasis, namely, a relatively constant coordination
among the components of an organism, given the interaction
of these components with environments internal to and external to the
organism. Homeostasis and adaptability are two sides of the same coin. As
was intimated already, this property of adaptability in relation to environments
is yet another essential feature that distinguishes living entities,
properties, or substances from nonliving ones. Another way to say this is
that the adaptability of processes and subsystems in organisms can be
pointed to as a clear way in which to distinguish the biological from the
physicochemical realms.
Consider a rock. A rock would be classifi ed as a nonliving, physicochemical
entity because it does not have this ability to adapt to environments
and situations the way that living, biological entities do. If a rock
is hit by a hammer with a certain amount of force, it breaks up into
pieces, the pieces fall where they may according to physicochemical laws,
and that is the end of the story—this is its “response” to the environment.
Alternatively, if one’s forearm is hit by a hammer such that a bone
breaks, the various systems of the body go to work to repair the damage
so that some form of homeostasis can be reachieved. The body adaptively
responds to this environmental pressure, and the hierarchy goes to work
on fi xing the problem. Further, if the bone does not heal correctly or the
muscles surrounding it have atrophied because of the blow, the subsystems
and processes of the body can compensate for the injury. If the hierarchy
cannot fi x the problem, it adjusts or readjusts if necessary.
Homeostasis in an organism entails adaptability as a necessary condition,
for it is the organism’s response to its ever-changing environment that
will occasion the need for either particularized or generalized homeostasis.
Of course, biological entities are constructed of physicochemical components
and are subject to the same physicochemical laws as any other
piece of matter in the world; again, there is upward physicochemical causation
that acts as a necessary condition for biological functioning.
However, biological entities, as hierarchically organized living systems,
have this distinguishing property whereby the subsystems and processes
adaptively respond to their environments in ways that other physicochemical
entities do not.