3.5 Iconic Memory
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41
Having laid out these four levels of visual processing, we can now discuss
visual cognition as being dependent upon iconic memory, attention, and
the synchronous fi ring of the neurons in the areas relevant to the visual
percept. Iconic memory is implicated in visual cognition because the visual
representation has to be held in mind, so to speak—if even for a very
short time—so that unifi cation of the various parallel processes that contribute
to cognition can occur. The idea is that if the disparate pieces of
information were too fl eeting, then there would not be enough salience
in the visual fi eld to be able to encode the incoming information. In
studies where individuals are shown quick fl ashes of objects on a screen
and then asked to identify them, if the object does not remain on the
screen for at least 250 milliseconds (a quarter of a second), then the
individual does not “see” the object or thinks that the test had not begun.
This is so because the object is fl ashed on the screen at such an incredibly
fast rate that the visual system is not even aware of the occurrence (Barrett,
Dunbar, & Lycett, 2001; Julesz, 1983). Through PET scans, activity in the
left prefrontal cortex has been shown to be active in individuals who
attempt to encode visual information (Kosslyn et al., 1999a, 1999b,
2001).
Further, the existence of iconic memory acts as a bridge between noncognitive
visual processing and cognitive visual processing. We are wholly
unaware of the processes in the lowest level of the visual hierarchy comprising
the trajectory from retina, through LGN, to V1. Iconic memory is
kind of like the paused scene on a movie you rent or a snapshot photograph
in your mind that enables you to be aware of or cognitive of a visual
scene—although such a scene or photo can be held in mind for only an
incredibly short amount of time.
When we think of memory, what comes to mind are recollections of
mental maps, events, sights, sounds, smells, and the like. Further, these
recollections are not a jumbled mass of confusion but are organized into
coherent picture-like scenes. With respect to visual memory, these scenes
are, in effect, visual images that we have stored somehow in our brains
and deliberately can recollect if necessary. So how does this storage take
place?
Following leads from Hebb (1949, 1966), Bliss & Lømo (1973) demonstrated
that the hippocampus of the mammalian brain exhibited alterations
in synaptic strength of neurons, depending upon the amount of
stimuli applied. They termed this alteration in synaptic strength long-term potentiation (LTP). LTP could last for hours in brain slices, while in the
intact animal it could last for days. Malenka & Siegelbaum (2001, p. 419)
note that LTP is a “ubiquitous property,” since it has been observed in the
excitatory synapses of a variety of areas of the brain, including the hippocampus,
all layers and areas of the cortex (including the visual cortex), the
amygdala, the thalamus, and the cerebellum.
In addition, Kandel’s (1976) groundbreaking work associated with the
gill-withdraw refl ex of the marine snail, Aplysia, showed that simple forms
of learning—habituation, sensitization, and classical conditioning—could
produce changes in the synaptic strength of neurons resulting in memory
storage. It seems clear that there exists some kind of storage mechanism
at the cellular level. This is something important to keep in mind, as the
organs and processes of the brain are comprised of these collections of
neurons (cf. Maviel, Durkin, Menzaghi, & Bontempi, 2004; Fink, 2003;
Hoffman & McNaughton, 2002).
However, this is not the full story concerning memory storage. Studies
of patients whose association areas are damaged have shown that different
representations of an object are stored differently. For example, a
person suffering from associative visual agnosia whose posterior parietal
cortex has been damaged can identify objects by drawing them but
cannot name them. Conversely, a person suffering from apperceptive visual
agnosia whose occipital lobes are damaged can name objects but cannot
identify them to draw them (Farah, 1990). Another example is prosopagnosia,
the inability to recognize familiar faces or learn new faces that
results from damage to the IT cortex. People who suffer from prosopagnosia,
although unable to process or recall faces, still can process and
recall other objects, such as animals and tools (Geschwind, 1979). These
studies indicate that the visual image is a product of multiple representations
in the brain, each having their own neural correlates and each
concerned with a different aspect of the visual image. This implies that
there is no one deposit memory storage area. Rather, there are multiple
storage areas, and recollection is itself a process of building up disparate
pieces of information.
In this section, I discussed a storage mechanism in the visual system
for at least two reasons. First, such a mechanism is necessary in information
exchange so that a receiving afferent entity actually can be infl uenced
by the information communicated by an efferent entity. Think of
an action potential and neurotransmitter release in the synaptic cleft of
a neuron A and how that affects a neighboring neuron B, possibly causing
another action potential in neuron B. Or, think of the DNA transfer when neurons differentiate. In both of these processes, the effects in
some way must be imprinted within the efferent entity so that the communicated
information evokes some kind of change in the efferent entity.
These processes are representative of the myriad exchanges of information
taking place throughout the entire nervous system.
Second, a memory mechanism is integral for visual imaging. When I
want to deliberately recall my spouse’s face, a process begins whereby the
IT cortex, hippocampus, and other temporal cortical areas are activated.
That I can recall my spouse’s face means I had to imprint her face, and
this process also involved the IT cortex, hippocampus, and other temporal
cortical areas (see Kosslyn, 1987; Kosslyn et al., 2001). Alternatively, say I
wanted to hold an object in my hand—like a shirt off the rack at a department
store—and analyze an aspect of it to check and see if it has any
imperfections. In order to accomplish this task, some kind of temporary
memory would be necessary to sustain its image long enough in my visual
fi eld.
Having laid out these four levels of visual processing, we can now discuss
visual cognition as being dependent upon iconic memory, attention, and
the synchronous fi ring of the neurons in the areas relevant to the visual
percept. Iconic memory is implicated in visual cognition because the visual
representation has to be held in mind, so to speak—if even for a very
short time—so that unifi cation of the various parallel processes that contribute
to cognition can occur. The idea is that if the disparate pieces of
information were too fl eeting, then there would not be enough salience
in the visual fi eld to be able to encode the incoming information. In
studies where individuals are shown quick fl ashes of objects on a screen
and then asked to identify them, if the object does not remain on the
screen for at least 250 milliseconds (a quarter of a second), then the
individual does not “see” the object or thinks that the test had not begun.
This is so because the object is fl ashed on the screen at such an incredibly
fast rate that the visual system is not even aware of the occurrence (Barrett,
Dunbar, & Lycett, 2001; Julesz, 1983). Through PET scans, activity in the
left prefrontal cortex has been shown to be active in individuals who
attempt to encode visual information (Kosslyn et al., 1999a, 1999b,
2001).
Further, the existence of iconic memory acts as a bridge between noncognitive
visual processing and cognitive visual processing. We are wholly
unaware of the processes in the lowest level of the visual hierarchy comprising
the trajectory from retina, through LGN, to V1. Iconic memory is
kind of like the paused scene on a movie you rent or a snapshot photograph
in your mind that enables you to be aware of or cognitive of a visual
scene—although such a scene or photo can be held in mind for only an
incredibly short amount of time.
When we think of memory, what comes to mind are recollections of
mental maps, events, sights, sounds, smells, and the like. Further, these
recollections are not a jumbled mass of confusion but are organized into
coherent picture-like scenes. With respect to visual memory, these scenes
are, in effect, visual images that we have stored somehow in our brains
and deliberately can recollect if necessary. So how does this storage take
place?
Following leads from Hebb (1949, 1966), Bliss & Lømo (1973) demonstrated
that the hippocampus of the mammalian brain exhibited alterations
in synaptic strength of neurons, depending upon the amount of
stimuli applied. They termed this alteration in synaptic strength long-term potentiation (LTP). LTP could last for hours in brain slices, while in the
intact animal it could last for days. Malenka & Siegelbaum (2001, p. 419)
note that LTP is a “ubiquitous property,” since it has been observed in the
excitatory synapses of a variety of areas of the brain, including the hippocampus,
all layers and areas of the cortex (including the visual cortex), the
amygdala, the thalamus, and the cerebellum.
In addition, Kandel’s (1976) groundbreaking work associated with the
gill-withdraw refl ex of the marine snail, Aplysia, showed that simple forms
of learning—habituation, sensitization, and classical conditioning—could
produce changes in the synaptic strength of neurons resulting in memory
storage. It seems clear that there exists some kind of storage mechanism
at the cellular level. This is something important to keep in mind, as the
organs and processes of the brain are comprised of these collections of
neurons (cf. Maviel, Durkin, Menzaghi, & Bontempi, 2004; Fink, 2003;
Hoffman & McNaughton, 2002).
However, this is not the full story concerning memory storage. Studies
of patients whose association areas are damaged have shown that different
representations of an object are stored differently. For example, a
person suffering from associative visual agnosia whose posterior parietal
cortex has been damaged can identify objects by drawing them but
cannot name them. Conversely, a person suffering from apperceptive visual
agnosia whose occipital lobes are damaged can name objects but cannot
identify them to draw them (Farah, 1990). Another example is prosopagnosia,
the inability to recognize familiar faces or learn new faces that
results from damage to the IT cortex. People who suffer from prosopagnosia,
although unable to process or recall faces, still can process and
recall other objects, such as animals and tools (Geschwind, 1979). These
studies indicate that the visual image is a product of multiple representations
in the brain, each having their own neural correlates and each
concerned with a different aspect of the visual image. This implies that
there is no one deposit memory storage area. Rather, there are multiple
storage areas, and recollection is itself a process of building up disparate
pieces of information.
In this section, I discussed a storage mechanism in the visual system
for at least two reasons. First, such a mechanism is necessary in information
exchange so that a receiving afferent entity actually can be infl uenced
by the information communicated by an efferent entity. Think of
an action potential and neurotransmitter release in the synaptic cleft of
a neuron A and how that affects a neighboring neuron B, possibly causing
another action potential in neuron B. Or, think of the DNA transfer when neurons differentiate. In both of these processes, the effects in
some way must be imprinted within the efferent entity so that the communicated
information evokes some kind of change in the efferent entity.
These processes are representative of the myriad exchanges of information
taking place throughout the entire nervous system.
Second, a memory mechanism is integral for visual imaging. When I
want to deliberately recall my spouse’s face, a process begins whereby the
IT cortex, hippocampus, and other temporal cortical areas are activated.
That I can recall my spouse’s face means I had to imprint her face, and
this process also involved the IT cortex, hippocampus, and other temporal
cortical areas (see Kosslyn, 1987; Kosslyn et al., 2001). Alternatively, say I
wanted to hold an object in my hand—like a shirt off the rack at a department
store—and analyze an aspect of it to check and see if it has any
imperfections. In order to accomplish this task, some kind of temporary
memory would be necessary to sustain its image long enough in my visual
fi eld.