3.4 Levels of Visual Processing
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41
In the previous section, I noted that visual recognition and discrimination
of objects are key to an animal’s survival, and I went on to suggest that
these activities are possible because of the phenomenon of visual modularity
and the mechanism of visual integration. There is more to the story
concerning an animal’s visual cognition of an object than simply visual
modularity and visual integration. Numerous studies indicate that (1)
iconic memory, namely, a form of short-term memory that lasts no more
than a second or so, as well as (2) attention and (3) the synchronous fi ring
of the neurons in the areas relevant to the visual percept, seem to be necessary
for visual cognition. These parts and processes may not comprise the
suffi cient condition for an overall coherently unifi ed visual percept; this is
to say, there may be some element or elements missing. However, the
empirical evidence seems to indicate that such parts and processes are
necessary for a coherent visual scene.
Before discussing these additional conditions necessary for visual cognition,
I want to distinguish the various levels of visual processing, of
which visual cognition is a part. We can distinguish four levels of visual
processing in the visual system. The fi rst level is a noncognitive visual
processing that occurs at the lowest level of the visual hierarchy associated
with the eye, LGN, and primary visual cortex. At this level, the
animal is wholly unaware of the processing, as the brain receives the
disparate pieces of basic information in the visual fi eld concerned with
lines, shapes, distance, depth, color, and so forth, of an object in the
visual fi eld (Gray, 1999; Julesz, 1984; Merikle & Daneman, 1998; Rees,
Kreiman, & Koch, 2002).
Evidence for this level of processing comes from data gathered from
backward masking experiments as well as from patients who suffer from
visual form agnosia, prosopagnosia, visual neglect, blindsight, and color anomia
(Farah, 1984, 1990, 1997; Cowey & Stoerig, 1995; Crick & Koch, 1998;
Marcel, 1983). The patients in these experiments are able to process
visual information, seemingly without being aware or cognizant of that
information. In his blindsight experiments, Weiskrantz (1986, 1988, 1997)
has shown that limited stimulus detection and movement toward objects
is possible in patients who claim they “cannot see,” that is, have no
awareness of the stimulus. Graves & Jones (1992) also draw a distinction
between nonconscious visual processing and visual awareness as a result
of their experiments with blindsight patients. Humphrey (1992) notes
a case of color anomia where a woman was able to process colors without being aware that she was making mistakes in her conscious
reporting of those colors (also see Oxbury, Oxbury, & Humphrey,
1969).
In his backward masking experiments, Eagle (1959) documented interesting
cases where people were shown a quick image of a man wielding a
knife—approximately one-tenth of a second—followed by a longer lasting
image of the same man standing and smiling. They then were asked to
describe the character of the man in the second longer lasting picture.
Interestingly enough, many subjects were unaware that the fi rst picture
occurred and yet still would judge the character of the man in the second
picture according to what was processed by their visual system in the fi rst
picture. These studies seem to indicate that there is noncognitive visual
processing occurring, despite the absence of awareness and/or conscious
visual experience.
The second level of visual processing is a cognitive visual processing that
occurs at a higher level of visual awareness associated with the what and
the where visual unimodal areas. When it is said that an animal visually
perceives what an object looks like or where an object is located, this means
that the animal is cognitively aware of or cognitively attends to that object in
the visual fi eld. We can infer that cognitive visual processing is taking place
from the fact that if the what system is nonfunctioning, a primate still may
be able to distinguish where an object is; conversely, if the where system is
nonfunctioning, a primate still may be able to distinguish what an object
is (Goodale et al., 1994; Goodale & Murphy, 2000; Ungerleider & Haxby,
1994).
The move from noncognitive visual processing to cognitive visual processing
is a move from the purely neurobiological to the psychological
dimension associated with the brain’s activities. I am using words like cognition,
awareness, and perception to refer to similar psychological discriminatory
abilities of an animal. Cognition enables an animal with a complex
nervous system to negotiate environments as optimally as possible. In the
previous chapter, I argued that the components of an organism are emergent
entities nonreducible to the physicochemical parts of which they are
composed, based upon the way in which the components are organized
to do something directly related to the generalized homeostasis of this
hierarchically organized living system (also see Arp, 2008a). The psychological
dimension associated with the brain’s activities can be considered
as another level of emergent phenomena—psychologically emergent
phenomena—added to the neurobiological hierarchy. Cognition is an
emergent phenomenon because the parts and processes associated with it appear to be organized in such a way so as to aid an animal in discriminating
information in environments. However, the kind of end result or end
product of cognition—although similar to other activities in the animal’s
hierarchy in having generalized homeostasis as the goal—is different in
that such a product is a psychological phenomenon that aids in generalized
homeostasis.
There is a huge amount of literature devoted to questions about the
existence of psychological phenomena and whether psychological phenomena
supervene upon or emerge from neurobiological phenomena (for
starters, see Heil, 2004a, 2004b; Stich & Warfi eld, 2003; Chalmers, 1996;
McGinn, 1982; Hasker, 1999; Hatfi eld, 1999; Mesalum, 1998; Kim, 2000;
Lycan, 1995; Searle, 1992; Arp, 2005b, 2007b, 2008d). Working out the
problems associated with these issues constitutes solving several so-called
mind–body problems. Now, no one has been able to give a satisfactory
account of how it is that psychological states—particularly conscious psychological
states—arise from, as well as interact with, the gray matter of
the brain. However, my intuition concerning the emergence of psychological
states is that just as the components at various levels of neurobiological
and biological hierarchies—such as organelles, cells, tissues, and organs—
cannot be reduced to the physicochemical parts of which they are composed,
so too visual cognition, although dependent upon neurobiological
processes, is not reducible to such processes. Again, the main reason why
psychological phenomena are nonreducible to neurobiological phenomena
is the same reason why neurobiological and biological components
are nonreducible to the physicochemical parts of which they are composed,
namely, such components and phenomena emerge as a result of
the way in which they are organized to do something directly related to
generalized homeostasis of the organism. I will have more to say about
this in the next two chapters when I speak more directly about the evolution
of scenario visualization in our species’ psychology.
The third level of visual processing is a cognitive visual processing that
occurs at an even higher level of visual awareness concerned with the
integration of the disparate pieces of visual unimodal information in the
visual unimodal association area. There are times when an animal must
determine both what an object is and where it is located, and this level of
visual processing makes such a determination possible.
The fourth level of visual processing is a conscious cognitive visual processing
that occurs at the highest level of the visual hierarchy associated with
the multimodal areas, frontal areas, and, most probably, the summated
areas of the cerebral cortex. This is the kind of visual processing related to
human visual awareness and visual experience, and evidence for this level
comes from reports made by individuals, as well as from observing human
behavior (Roth, 2000; James, 1890; Chalmers, 1996). As I will make clear
in the next two chapters, one form of conscious cognitive visual processing
is scenario visualization, namely, the selection and integration of visual
images from mental modules, as well as the projection of visual images
into future scenarios for the purposes of negotiating environments.
In this project, I am concerned mostly with the progression from cognitive
visual processing to conscious cognitive visual processing, the relationship
of these processes to one another, and, ultimately, how conscious
cognitive visual processing evolved from cognitive visual processing. This
is so because, as I show, conscious cognitive visual processing—in terms of
what I call scenario visualization—is necessary for vision-related, nonroutine
creative problem solving. Although I will not be able to solve completely
the mind–body problem of how it is that conscious experience can
emerge from and interact with the gray matter of the brain, my hypothesis
concerning scenario visualization is an attempt to explain a part of our
conscious abilities and the reason for its emergence in our species.
We can think of the four levels of processing in relation to the various
species in the animal kingdom. All vertebrate species in the phylum
Chordata with a rudimentary visual system—mammals, birds, reptiles,
amphibians, and fi sh—exhibit noncognitive visual processing of some
kind. These same vertebrate species also exhibit cognitive visual processing
to some degree or another. Besides the numerous studies on apes, monkeys,
dolphins, cats, dogs, birds, and turtles that seem to indicate that they have
cognitive abilities such as awareness and associative learning (for starters,
see Marten & Psarakos, 1994; Byrne, 1995; Pearce, 1997; Stamp Dawkins,
1993; Parker, 1996; Tomasello et al., 1993; Weir, Chappell, & Kacelnik,
2002; Eimer & van Velzen, 2002), I have witnessed my own cat’s abilities
to perceive and recall where her treat is located in the cabinet, as well as
her abilities to expect the treat and go for the treat when I have left the
room. (Sometimes, she actually would open the cabinet where the can of
treats was kept and knock the can to the counter below!) Given the data,
I agree with Roth (2000, p. 95) that “it is fair to assume that all vertebrates
with larger cortexlike structures, particularly those with cortices showing
cross-modality information transfer, have awareness about what is going
on around them.” However, within the order primates, human beings
alone seem to exhibit conscious cognitive visual processing to a full degree,
while the other primates may do so to a lesser degree (cf. Parker, 1996;
Whiten et al., 1999; Mitchell, 1993).
In the previous section, I noted that visual recognition and discrimination
of objects are key to an animal’s survival, and I went on to suggest that
these activities are possible because of the phenomenon of visual modularity
and the mechanism of visual integration. There is more to the story
concerning an animal’s visual cognition of an object than simply visual
modularity and visual integration. Numerous studies indicate that (1)
iconic memory, namely, a form of short-term memory that lasts no more
than a second or so, as well as (2) attention and (3) the synchronous fi ring
of the neurons in the areas relevant to the visual percept, seem to be necessary
for visual cognition. These parts and processes may not comprise the
suffi cient condition for an overall coherently unifi ed visual percept; this is
to say, there may be some element or elements missing. However, the
empirical evidence seems to indicate that such parts and processes are
necessary for a coherent visual scene.
Before discussing these additional conditions necessary for visual cognition,
I want to distinguish the various levels of visual processing, of
which visual cognition is a part. We can distinguish four levels of visual
processing in the visual system. The fi rst level is a noncognitive visual
processing that occurs at the lowest level of the visual hierarchy associated
with the eye, LGN, and primary visual cortex. At this level, the
animal is wholly unaware of the processing, as the brain receives the
disparate pieces of basic information in the visual fi eld concerned with
lines, shapes, distance, depth, color, and so forth, of an object in the
visual fi eld (Gray, 1999; Julesz, 1984; Merikle & Daneman, 1998; Rees,
Kreiman, & Koch, 2002).
Evidence for this level of processing comes from data gathered from
backward masking experiments as well as from patients who suffer from
visual form agnosia, prosopagnosia, visual neglect, blindsight, and color anomia
(Farah, 1984, 1990, 1997; Cowey & Stoerig, 1995; Crick & Koch, 1998;
Marcel, 1983). The patients in these experiments are able to process
visual information, seemingly without being aware or cognizant of that
information. In his blindsight experiments, Weiskrantz (1986, 1988, 1997)
has shown that limited stimulus detection and movement toward objects
is possible in patients who claim they “cannot see,” that is, have no
awareness of the stimulus. Graves & Jones (1992) also draw a distinction
between nonconscious visual processing and visual awareness as a result
of their experiments with blindsight patients. Humphrey (1992) notes
a case of color anomia where a woman was able to process colors without being aware that she was making mistakes in her conscious
reporting of those colors (also see Oxbury, Oxbury, & Humphrey,
1969).
In his backward masking experiments, Eagle (1959) documented interesting
cases where people were shown a quick image of a man wielding a
knife—approximately one-tenth of a second—followed by a longer lasting
image of the same man standing and smiling. They then were asked to
describe the character of the man in the second longer lasting picture.
Interestingly enough, many subjects were unaware that the fi rst picture
occurred and yet still would judge the character of the man in the second
picture according to what was processed by their visual system in the fi rst
picture. These studies seem to indicate that there is noncognitive visual
processing occurring, despite the absence of awareness and/or conscious
visual experience.
The second level of visual processing is a cognitive visual processing that
occurs at a higher level of visual awareness associated with the what and
the where visual unimodal areas. When it is said that an animal visually
perceives what an object looks like or where an object is located, this means
that the animal is cognitively aware of or cognitively attends to that object in
the visual fi eld. We can infer that cognitive visual processing is taking place
from the fact that if the what system is nonfunctioning, a primate still may
be able to distinguish where an object is; conversely, if the where system is
nonfunctioning, a primate still may be able to distinguish what an object
is (Goodale et al., 1994; Goodale & Murphy, 2000; Ungerleider & Haxby,
1994).
The move from noncognitive visual processing to cognitive visual processing
is a move from the purely neurobiological to the psychological
dimension associated with the brain’s activities. I am using words like cognition,
awareness, and perception to refer to similar psychological discriminatory
abilities of an animal. Cognition enables an animal with a complex
nervous system to negotiate environments as optimally as possible. In the
previous chapter, I argued that the components of an organism are emergent
entities nonreducible to the physicochemical parts of which they are
composed, based upon the way in which the components are organized
to do something directly related to the generalized homeostasis of this
hierarchically organized living system (also see Arp, 2008a). The psychological
dimension associated with the brain’s activities can be considered
as another level of emergent phenomena—psychologically emergent
phenomena—added to the neurobiological hierarchy. Cognition is an
emergent phenomenon because the parts and processes associated with it appear to be organized in such a way so as to aid an animal in discriminating
information in environments. However, the kind of end result or end
product of cognition—although similar to other activities in the animal’s
hierarchy in having generalized homeostasis as the goal—is different in
that such a product is a psychological phenomenon that aids in generalized
homeostasis.
There is a huge amount of literature devoted to questions about the
existence of psychological phenomena and whether psychological phenomena
supervene upon or emerge from neurobiological phenomena (for
starters, see Heil, 2004a, 2004b; Stich & Warfi eld, 2003; Chalmers, 1996;
McGinn, 1982; Hasker, 1999; Hatfi eld, 1999; Mesalum, 1998; Kim, 2000;
Lycan, 1995; Searle, 1992; Arp, 2005b, 2007b, 2008d). Working out the
problems associated with these issues constitutes solving several so-called
mind–body problems. Now, no one has been able to give a satisfactory
account of how it is that psychological states—particularly conscious psychological
states—arise from, as well as interact with, the gray matter of
the brain. However, my intuition concerning the emergence of psychological
states is that just as the components at various levels of neurobiological
and biological hierarchies—such as organelles, cells, tissues, and organs—
cannot be reduced to the physicochemical parts of which they are composed,
so too visual cognition, although dependent upon neurobiological
processes, is not reducible to such processes. Again, the main reason why
psychological phenomena are nonreducible to neurobiological phenomena
is the same reason why neurobiological and biological components
are nonreducible to the physicochemical parts of which they are composed,
namely, such components and phenomena emerge as a result of
the way in which they are organized to do something directly related to
generalized homeostasis of the organism. I will have more to say about
this in the next two chapters when I speak more directly about the evolution
of scenario visualization in our species’ psychology.
The third level of visual processing is a cognitive visual processing that
occurs at an even higher level of visual awareness concerned with the
integration of the disparate pieces of visual unimodal information in the
visual unimodal association area. There are times when an animal must
determine both what an object is and where it is located, and this level of
visual processing makes such a determination possible.
The fourth level of visual processing is a conscious cognitive visual processing
that occurs at the highest level of the visual hierarchy associated with
the multimodal areas, frontal areas, and, most probably, the summated
areas of the cerebral cortex. This is the kind of visual processing related to
human visual awareness and visual experience, and evidence for this level
comes from reports made by individuals, as well as from observing human
behavior (Roth, 2000; James, 1890; Chalmers, 1996). As I will make clear
in the next two chapters, one form of conscious cognitive visual processing
is scenario visualization, namely, the selection and integration of visual
images from mental modules, as well as the projection of visual images
into future scenarios for the purposes of negotiating environments.
In this project, I am concerned mostly with the progression from cognitive
visual processing to conscious cognitive visual processing, the relationship
of these processes to one another, and, ultimately, how conscious
cognitive visual processing evolved from cognitive visual processing. This
is so because, as I show, conscious cognitive visual processing—in terms of
what I call scenario visualization—is necessary for vision-related, nonroutine
creative problem solving. Although I will not be able to solve completely
the mind–body problem of how it is that conscious experience can
emerge from and interact with the gray matter of the brain, my hypothesis
concerning scenario visualization is an attempt to explain a part of our
conscious abilities and the reason for its emergence in our species.
We can think of the four levels of processing in relation to the various
species in the animal kingdom. All vertebrate species in the phylum
Chordata with a rudimentary visual system—mammals, birds, reptiles,
amphibians, and fi sh—exhibit noncognitive visual processing of some
kind. These same vertebrate species also exhibit cognitive visual processing
to some degree or another. Besides the numerous studies on apes, monkeys,
dolphins, cats, dogs, birds, and turtles that seem to indicate that they have
cognitive abilities such as awareness and associative learning (for starters,
see Marten & Psarakos, 1994; Byrne, 1995; Pearce, 1997; Stamp Dawkins,
1993; Parker, 1996; Tomasello et al., 1993; Weir, Chappell, & Kacelnik,
2002; Eimer & van Velzen, 2002), I have witnessed my own cat’s abilities
to perceive and recall where her treat is located in the cabinet, as well as
her abilities to expect the treat and go for the treat when I have left the
room. (Sometimes, she actually would open the cabinet where the can of
treats was kept and knock the can to the counter below!) Given the data,
I agree with Roth (2000, p. 95) that “it is fair to assume that all vertebrates
with larger cortexlike structures, particularly those with cortices showing
cross-modality information transfer, have awareness about what is going
on around them.” However, within the order primates, human beings
alone seem to exhibit conscious cognitive visual processing to a full degree,
while the other primates may do so to a lesser degree (cf. Parker, 1996;
Whiten et al., 1999; Mitchell, 1993).