2.3 Organisms and Function
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41
In the last two sections of this chapter, I have argued for a nomological
form of metaphysical emergence, in terms of HOV, and I began to argue
for a representational form of epistemological emergence, in terms of an
as-if realism. In the fi nal section of this chapter, I will continue to argue
for both forms of emergence by an investigation of function (also see Arp,
2006b). That organisms have functions and that we must describe—or, at
least, as-if describe—the actual functioning of those organisms are central
to my metaphysical and epistemological versions of emergence. Further,
it is essential to my project that I explain and defend a description of functions
because my hypothesis concerning scenario visualization depends
upon certain functional mechanisms of the mind having evolved to solve
specifi c problems encountered in various Pleistocene environments. As a
biologist (of sorts), the realist in me says that organisms really do have
functions. As a philosopher of biology, the antirealist in me realizes that no
one can know, for sure, if organisms really do have functions, principally
because of the veil of perceptions that mediates between the mind and
world (if there is a world). However, we still must proceed to describe
organisms as if they have functions because (1) such a description is useful
and (2) it would be miraculous if our descriptions did not match up with
what we take to be the real functions of organisms as we perceive them.
Organisms, and the subsystems and processes that comprise them, tend
to operate in certain ways on a regular basis. This operational regularity
not only aids biologists in identifying certain traits but enables biology to
be considered an autonomous science with its own domain of laws (also
see the sections on function in Arp & Ayala, 2008; Arp & Rosenberg, 2008;
Terzis & Arp, 2008). Genetic information is communicated from parent
organism to offspring, mitochondria convert sugar to ATP, the heart pumps
blood, the medulla controls breathing, the complex interactions of the
subsystems and processes of multicellular organisms tend toward the maintenance
of a dynamic equilibrium (homeostasis)—all of this happens in
fairly predictable and reliable ways. Another way of describing the tendency
for processes and subsystems of organisms to operate in predictable
and reliable ways is in terms of the organism’s functions.
In the biological realm, a complete explanation of a trait seems to
include an explanation in terms of function. It is natural to ask of some
trait, What is its function? or What purpose in the organism does the particular
trait serve? or What is the goal of its activity? Thus, for example,
to explain the existence of the human heart as merely a red mass of tissue located in the chest cavity of the torso that pulsates and reverberates
according to the natural laws of physics and chemistry strikes us as an
incomplete explanation. However, as has been argued quite convincingly
by Mayr (1996), Walters (1998), Lennox (1993), Sober (1993), Gould (1977),
Sterelny (2001), Dawkins (1986), and others, biology has its own legitimate
scientifi c principles and terminology (cf. Machamer, Darden, & Craver,
2000; Tabery, 2004; Glennan, 1996). In line with a biological explanation,
it seems we can talk about the heart’s function or purpose in the human
body as an organ that pumps blood. An important part of explaining the
heart is to say that it exists so as to pump blood, or that pumping blood
is the heart’s operation or function.
Beginning in the 1960s with Nagel (1961) and Hempel (1965), philosophers
of science and biology have not only proposed a variety of defi nitions
for the term function but have attempted to specify the conditions
where it may be appropriate to predicate functions of natural and artifi cial
things, and to appeal to these functions in explanations (see Cummins,
1975, 2002; Wright, 1973, 1976; Mayr, 1982, 1988; Millikan, 1984, 1989,
2002; Buller, 1999; Ayala, 1998; Mahner & Bunge, 2001; Neander, 1991,
1999; Hardcastle, 1999; Perlman, 2004). Some thinkers, like Dennett (1987,
1995) and the Churchlands (1986, 1989), offer a promissory note that talk
of functions in biology will be eliminated altogether once a more accurate,
value-free system of terms is invented to describe the operational traits of
organisms. Searle (1990b, p. 414) seems to hold the similar view that functions
are solely the product of intentional and intensional minds, and that
functions are “never intrinsic but are always observer relative.” And Ruse
has affi rmed (1971, 1973) and reaffi rmed (2003) a position similar to that
of Dennett, the Churchlands, and Searle, namely, there is nothing like an
intrinsic or extrinsic ontological purpose or design to be found in nature.
Talk of functions is just that—talk of functions.
Yet Ruse and other thinkers admit something about the biological sciences
that Kant (1987) had admitted in his third Critique; with respect to
organisms, it is useful to think as if these entities have traits and processes
that function in goal-directed ways. Thinkers cannot seem to get around
Trivers’ (1985, p. 5) claim that “even the humblest creature, say, a virus,
appears organized to do something; it acts as if [italics mine] it is trying to
achieve some purpose” or Arnhart’s (1998, p. 245) observation that
“although the evolutionary process does not serve goals, the organisms
emerging from that process do. Darwin’s biology does not deny—rather,
it reaffi rms—the immanent teleology displayed in the striving of each
living being to fulfi ll its specifi c ends. . . . Reproduction, growth, feeding, healing, courtship, parental care for the young—these and many other
activities of organisms are goal-directed” (also see Bogdan, 1994; Stout,
1996; FitzPatrick, 2000; Sterelny & Griffi ths, 1999; Arp, 1998, 1999, 2002,
2006b).
In the last section, I argued for an as-if realism. This approach acknowledges
that we could never know the nature of anything outside of our
own perceptions for certain. At the same time, as-if realism affi rms that
we must act as if there is a reality out there to be understood and
described; it would be miraculous if there were not a real world out
there to which our perceptions and ideas correspond, given the fecundity
of our scientifi c, philosophic, and other research endeavors. With this
as-if realism in mind, we can still attempt to describe the functions of
the traits and processes of organisms. Thus, I am in agreement with Ruse
and other thinkers who do not attempt to explain away descriptions of
the functions of traits. The as-if realism I endorse works together nicely
with this as-if description of the functioning of biological traits—the
as-if realist in me acknowledges that organisms act as if they are organized
so as to function in specifi c ways. In fact, as noted already, it is
essential to my project that I lay out and defend a description of functions
because, as will be shown in later chapters, my hypothesis concerning
scenario visualization depends upon certain functional mechanisms
of the mind having evolved to solve specifi c problems encountered in
various Pleistocene environments.
There are several views concerning the appropriate defi nition of function
for biological matters, and Perlman (2004) has done a fi ne job of laying
out all of these views as envisioned in the history of Western philosophy.
The two views of function with respect to living things that, in my estimation,
have the most credibility are Cummins’ (1975, 2002) organizational
account and the Griffi ths/Godfrey-Smith modern history account (Griffi ths,
1992, 1993, 1996; Godfrey-Smith, 1993, 1994, 1996), and I am not alone
in this assessment (cf. Boorse, 2002; Millikan, 2002; Schwartz, 2002; Collier,
2000; see also Arp, 2006b). Ultimately, I want to maintain that these two
accounts need not be in competition and, actually, can complement one
another. Further, as will be shown later, my hypothesis concerning the
emergence of scenario visualization will rely upon parts of both of these
accounts.
Cummins explains the function of some trait in terms of the role it plays
in maintaining the overall organization and survival of the organism in
its present state. Traits only have functions in relation to other traits within
the organization of the system as a whole. The function of the heart is a standard case utilized in discussions. Thus, the heart’s function is to pump
blood because this fulfi lls its causal role in relation to the organization
of the animal as a whole. There are two things to notice about this
account.
First, a trait can have—or could have had, or could have—any variety of
functions in relation to the organizational whole. In other words, a single
part could have a variety of functions, depending upon the organization
of the system. The heart could have fi ltered urine if the overall organization
of the animal were different in the past, or it could be co-opted to
perform some other function if the overall organization of the animal
changed in the future. Thus, there is a certain fl exibility or malleability in
some trait’s functionality. I fi nd this to be a virtue of Cummins’ position,
as it is now common knowledge that certain traits may actually be exaptations
or preaptations, rather than adaptations. Although, as we will see,
the fl exibility in a trait’s functionality makes it diffi cult to defi ne exactly
what a trait’s present function in the overall organization of an organism
actually is.
Second, Cummins purposely develops his account independent of any
evolutionary factors that would contribute to the historical origin of a
trait’s functionality. According to Cummins, for a trait to perform some
function, the basic structural components of the trait must already be
present so that it can perform that specifi c function in relation to the
organization of the organism as a whole. In other words, because the function
of some trait cannot precede the presence of that trait, and only comes
to have a function in relation to the contribution it makes to the organization
of the organism as a whole in its present state, it makes no sense to
speak about an evolutionary history with respect to that trait. Thus, hearts
pump blood because of their contribution to the overall maintenance of
the animal’s life, not because they conferred a survival-enhancing capacity
in the animal’s evolutionary ancestry. Whereas the fl exibility and/or malleability
exhibited in a trait’s functionality acts as a virtue of Cummins’
position, I fi nd the neglect of a trait’s history to be a vice of Cummins’
position, as I will demonstrate in a moment.
Conversely, according to the Griffi ths/Godfrey-Smith modern history
account, the function of some trait or process X in an organism is defi ned
by what the trait was naturally selected for doing in the organism’s species’
recent past. This is to say that past advantages to the organism are what
defi ne functions. Griffi ths and Godfrey-Smith add the qualifi cation that
the past advantage must be a recent addition in the species’ history, stemming
from the fact that the original selection for any trait may have favored an entirely different effect than the one that counts as the trait’s
current function. Thus, for example, the heart pumps blood or the kidney
fi lters urine in a cat because these traits enabled the cat’s most recent
ancestors to survive. The hearts that pumped blood and the kidneys that
fi ltered urine most adequately were naturally selected for as a trait in the
feline species, and cats today have hearts and kidneys that function so as
to pump blood and fi lter urine precisely because of this fi tness. Ayala (1998,
p. 45) favors a historical account of functions and notes that some trait is
functional “if it contributes to the reproductive effi ciency of the organism
itself, and if such contribution accounts for the existence of the structure
or process.” Ayala (1998, p. 40) further notes that these traits in organisms
are “biological adaptations. They have arisen as a result of the process of
natural selection. The adaptations of organisms—whether organs, homoeostatic
mechanisms, or patterns of behavior—are explained [functionally]
in that their existence is accounted for in terms of their contribution to
the reproductive fi tness of the population.”
According to Cummins, the function of some trait X has to do with the
trait’s contribution to some greater capacity or propensity of the organism
to survive rather than its evolutionary history. From Cummins’ perspective,
to say that the heart’s function is simply its adaptive ability to pump
blood—as proponents of the Griffi ths/Godfrey-Smith modern history
account want to do—is to miss other relevant effects of the heart that
contribute to the overall survival value of the organism. The heart produces
sound, weighs a certain amount, and has a certain structure, and these are
all factors besides its pumping of blood that supposedly contribute to the
overall maintenance, survival, and propensity for survival in the organism
(cf. Bigelow & Pargetter, 1998; Bechtel, 1989; Allen, Bekoff, & Lauder, 1998;
Staddon, 1987; Horan, 1989).
Unfortunately, the problem with this description of functions is that it
is too broad. Cummins fails to distinguish effects it is the function of a
trait or organ to produce from those it is not its function to produce.
Almost any effect can be understood as contributing to the survival value
of an organism on this interpretation of function. In other words, describing
functions purely in terms of organizational capacities and propensities
for survival puts us in the awkward position of not being able to distinguish
between the salient and nonsalient purposive features of traits. Concerning
the example of the heart, Cummins wants to say that weighing a certain
amount, producing sound, having a certain structure, and pumping blood
are all potential functions of the heart. However, there does not seem to
be any signifi cant evidence or theoretical precedent to show that the heart’s producing of sounds or weighing a certain amount per se confers
any propensity for survival in an organism.
There is a further problem with Cummins’ account. Recall that a trait
can have—or could have had, or could have—any variety of functions in
relation to the organizational whole. A single part could have a variety of
functions, depending upon the organization of the system. However, it
does not seem right to speak about the function of some trait by reference
to a propensity that will confer future advantage, because the future has
not occurred for us to know if in fact the advantage will be conferred. As
Cummins himself acknowledges, it is possible that a trait adapted to function
in an environment now may be co-opted for a different use in that
same environment later. The ability to fl y in birds may have come about
in this way. Feathers probably were selected for in archaic birds to protect
them from the cold but eventually became co-opted for fl ight (Feduccia,
1996; Ostrom, 1979; Gould & Vrba, 1982).
Also consistent with Cummins’ account is the fact that the environment
may change, possibly making it such that a trait that functioned in the
previous environment will become nonfunctional in the present environment.
It is likely that the existence of vestigial organs testifi es to this kind
of change (Berra, 1990). Further, it may be possible that an environment
changes, and a trait adapted to function in the previous environment gets
altered and co-opted for a different use in the present environment. This
may be the way in which conscious decision making arose in humans
when the hominin line was forced to move from jungle to savanna in
Africa during the Pleistocene epoch (see Tattersall, 2001, 2002; Arp, 2005a,
2006a). Thus, we never really can say that a trait will have some future
functioning advantage. At best, we look at its present functioning in relation
to some environment and surmise about its past functioning—again,
recent past, as per the qualifi cation of Griffi ths and Godfrey-Smith—in
some similar or dissimilar environment.
So, Cummins seems to do at least two things that are misguided. First,
he inappropriately neglects the role that recent evolutionary history plays
in a trait’s functional development. Second, in the tongue-in-cheek words
of Achinstein (1977, p. 344), he “saddles us with a bevy of unwanted functions.”
Most biologists would agree with the Griffi ths/Godfrey-Smith
account and want to say that the proper function of the heart—given its
recent selection in evolutionary history—is to pump blood, and only in an
ancillary way is the heart’s function to produce sounds, weigh a certain
amount, or have a certain structure (see Neander, 1999; Ayala, 1972; Sober,
1993; Millikan, 1984, 2002; Mayr, 1993; Dawkins, 1986; Ruse, 1973).
Nonetheless, it seems to me that the accounts of Cummins and Griffi ths/
Godfrey-Smith can complement and be made compatible with one another.
The part of Cummins’ account of functions that seems correct has to do
with the function of a trait understood as both (1) contributing to the
overall organizational structure of the organic system and (2) being fl exible
or malleable enough to be co-opted for some other function. These qualities
can complement the idea that the functioning of a trait must arise
within the context of an evolutionary history. There is nothing incompatible
or contradictory in maintaining that some trait functions so as to
contribute to the general organization of some organism’s structure while
at the same time describing the emergence of that trait’s functional contribution
to the organizational structure of the organism by reference to a
recent evolutionary history. So too, there is nothing incompatible or contradictory
in maintaining that some trait is malleable enough to be utilized
for several potential functions while at the same time describing the present
status of that trait in reference to a recent evolutionary history. Given that
structure, organization, operational fl exibility, function, and evolutionary
history are all factors to be considered in an organism’s makeup, we should
expect that the traits of an organism function the way they do because
such traits presently contribute to the overall organization of the organism
(Cummins) as well as were selected for in the organism’s species’ recent
ancestry (Griffi ths/Godfrey-Smith).
In attacking historical accounts of function, including the modern
history account, Bigelow & Pargetter (1998) entertain the thought experiment
that the tenets of evolutionary biology may turn out to be false. For
example, your grandparents could have been put together randomly out
of swamp material, and hence, you would have no evolutionary history to
speak of. If that happened to be the case, then the backward-looking, historical
explanation of function would lose its very backward support! I will
risk sounding ad hominem and point out—as Churchland (1993, p. 746)
has done—that this kind of thought experiment suffers from the fl aw of
most armchair philosophical thought experiments, namely, “too much
thought and not enough experiment!” One of the marks of good scientifi
c theorizing has to do with being open to the possibility that a wellestablished
theory may one day be debunked by evidence that disconfi rms
the theory. In other words, good science entails the falsifi cation of theory.
The swamp grandparents thought experiment hints at this falsifi cation
with respect to evolutionary theory. However, as Millikan (1989, 2002)
and Neander (1991) affi rm, there is enough evidence to suggest that we
should not abandon evolutionary theory just yet, despite such a thought experiment. I will point to a lot of this evidence when I build my case for
the evolution of the brain, visual system, and scenario visualization later
in this book. The work of biologists, neuroscientists, geologists, archeologists,
psychologists, philosophers, anthropologists, and zoologists, among
legions of other thinkers and researchers, establishes evolutionary theory
on a fi rm footing.
Despite the divergent views concerning the defi nition of a biological
function, both proponents of Cummins-style functions and proponents of
Griffi ths/Godfrey-Smith-style functions agree that evolution has taken
place and continues to take place. Given that evolution is understood as
the result of the complex workings of such factors as differential reproduction,
artifi cial selection, sexual selection, mutation, genetic drift, and
genetic recombination in a historical context, this historicity lends further
support to approaching the functions of traits from the perspective of the
modern history account.
The modern history account gives elucidation to Mayr’s (1996, p. 103)
description of organisms as “operating on the basis of historically acquired
programs of information.” Crudely and simply put, the information that
organisms acquire is to be found in the particular genetic code received
from their parent(s). However, as Plotkin (1997, p. 1) has observed, “nothing
in biology makes complete sense [italics mine] except in light of evolution.”
Therefore, any description of biological phenomena must include an evolutionary
perspective to be considered as a fully explanatory description
of the biological phenomena under investigation.
The account of functions I endorse is an evolutionary adaptationist
explanation. It is well-known that the primary mechanism of evolution is
natural selection. Through natural selection, environmental infl uences
affect populations of organisms, and the chance that benefi cial traits will
dominate in successor generations is increased by the adaptive ability and
reproductive success of individuals possessing optimal genetic variants.
When a trait contributes to the fi tness of the organism in its current environment,
it is said to be functionally adaptive. For example, as was mentioned
in the previous chapter, the various kinds of fi nches that Darwin
described on the Galapagos Islands have different beak structures as a
functionally adaptive response to their particular food source. Dawkins
(1986, p. 178) is correct in maintaining that adaptations “affect every part
of the body, its shape and colour, its internal organs, its behaviour, and
the chemistry of its cells.”
A Cummins-style explanation is a necessary ingredient in the description
of a biological function, given the dual emphasis placed upon a trait’s role in the overall organization of the organism and the fl exibility associated
with a trait’s function. However, a complete account of the function of
some trait requires an explanation of how the trait came to be useful for
the organism. Thinkers who utilize the evolutionary adaptationist methodology
view traits as adaptations that have evolved due to past contributions
to the fi tness of the organism in some environment. Sober (1993,
p. 83) is representative of this kind of thinking, and he links adaptation
to a historical account in a clear fashion: “To say that a trait is an ‘adaptation’
is to comment not on its current utility but on its history. To say that
the mammalian heart is (now) an adaptation for pumping blood is to say
that mammals now have hearts because ancestrally, having a heart conferred
a fi tness advantage; the trait evolved because there was selection for
having a heart, and hearts were selected because they pump blood.”
The biologist in me takes it as a real given that evolution has occurred
and that accounts of the functioning of traits and processes require an
evolutionary explanation. The philosopher of biology in me is not sure if
there is anything real out there to speak of as having a function; however,
my as-if realism tells me that it makes sense to proceed as if there were
realities out there with functions based in an evolutionary history. Thus,
in the end, given my endorsement of the modern history account as
necessary to explain how it is that organisms have become hierarchically
organized functioning systems, I take Plotkin’s claim that a biological
phenomenon only makes complete sense in light of evolutionary theory
seriously.
In the fi rst chapter, I described an organism as a living entity, the components
of which are hierarchically organized in subsystems and processes
operating so as to achieve particularized and generalized homeostasis. The
subsystems and processes possess certain properties, including abilities to
fl exibly exchange data, convert data to information in a selection process,
integrate information, and process information from environments. In this
chapter, I endorsed a form of metaphysical emergence whereby entities,
properties, or substances arise out of more fundamental entities, properties,
or substances and yet are not wholly reducible to them. I argued for this
form of emergence based upon HOV, namely, the fact that the subsystems
and processes of organisms coordinate their functions so as to produce
particularized and generalized homeostasis. I also argued for an epistemological
form of emergence that is rooted in the language of teleology and
as-if realism.
In completing my account of organisms understood as hierarchically
organized systems, I argued that the components of organisms function the way they do as a result of recent past adaptive advantages. The evolutionary
explanation I endorsed is a type of causal explanation of how it is
that the recent history of a trait has had certain adaptive effects, which
have facilitated the selection of that trait. We will see in subsequent chapters
that the brain and visual system, as well as the psychological phenomena
emerging from brain processes that enable humans to solve problems
creatively, exhibit similar biological properties and abide by the same
evolutionary principles laid out and explained in these last two chapters.
In the last two sections of this chapter, I have argued for a nomological
form of metaphysical emergence, in terms of HOV, and I began to argue
for a representational form of epistemological emergence, in terms of an
as-if realism. In the fi nal section of this chapter, I will continue to argue
for both forms of emergence by an investigation of function (also see Arp,
2006b). That organisms have functions and that we must describe—or, at
least, as-if describe—the actual functioning of those organisms are central
to my metaphysical and epistemological versions of emergence. Further,
it is essential to my project that I explain and defend a description of functions
because my hypothesis concerning scenario visualization depends
upon certain functional mechanisms of the mind having evolved to solve
specifi c problems encountered in various Pleistocene environments. As a
biologist (of sorts), the realist in me says that organisms really do have
functions. As a philosopher of biology, the antirealist in me realizes that no
one can know, for sure, if organisms really do have functions, principally
because of the veil of perceptions that mediates between the mind and
world (if there is a world). However, we still must proceed to describe
organisms as if they have functions because (1) such a description is useful
and (2) it would be miraculous if our descriptions did not match up with
what we take to be the real functions of organisms as we perceive them.
Organisms, and the subsystems and processes that comprise them, tend
to operate in certain ways on a regular basis. This operational regularity
not only aids biologists in identifying certain traits but enables biology to
be considered an autonomous science with its own domain of laws (also
see the sections on function in Arp & Ayala, 2008; Arp & Rosenberg, 2008;
Terzis & Arp, 2008). Genetic information is communicated from parent
organism to offspring, mitochondria convert sugar to ATP, the heart pumps
blood, the medulla controls breathing, the complex interactions of the
subsystems and processes of multicellular organisms tend toward the maintenance
of a dynamic equilibrium (homeostasis)—all of this happens in
fairly predictable and reliable ways. Another way of describing the tendency
for processes and subsystems of organisms to operate in predictable
and reliable ways is in terms of the organism’s functions.
In the biological realm, a complete explanation of a trait seems to
include an explanation in terms of function. It is natural to ask of some
trait, What is its function? or What purpose in the organism does the particular
trait serve? or What is the goal of its activity? Thus, for example,
to explain the existence of the human heart as merely a red mass of tissue located in the chest cavity of the torso that pulsates and reverberates
according to the natural laws of physics and chemistry strikes us as an
incomplete explanation. However, as has been argued quite convincingly
by Mayr (1996), Walters (1998), Lennox (1993), Sober (1993), Gould (1977),
Sterelny (2001), Dawkins (1986), and others, biology has its own legitimate
scientifi c principles and terminology (cf. Machamer, Darden, & Craver,
2000; Tabery, 2004; Glennan, 1996). In line with a biological explanation,
it seems we can talk about the heart’s function or purpose in the human
body as an organ that pumps blood. An important part of explaining the
heart is to say that it exists so as to pump blood, or that pumping blood
is the heart’s operation or function.
Beginning in the 1960s with Nagel (1961) and Hempel (1965), philosophers
of science and biology have not only proposed a variety of defi nitions
for the term function but have attempted to specify the conditions
where it may be appropriate to predicate functions of natural and artifi cial
things, and to appeal to these functions in explanations (see Cummins,
1975, 2002; Wright, 1973, 1976; Mayr, 1982, 1988; Millikan, 1984, 1989,
2002; Buller, 1999; Ayala, 1998; Mahner & Bunge, 2001; Neander, 1991,
1999; Hardcastle, 1999; Perlman, 2004). Some thinkers, like Dennett (1987,
1995) and the Churchlands (1986, 1989), offer a promissory note that talk
of functions in biology will be eliminated altogether once a more accurate,
value-free system of terms is invented to describe the operational traits of
organisms. Searle (1990b, p. 414) seems to hold the similar view that functions
are solely the product of intentional and intensional minds, and that
functions are “never intrinsic but are always observer relative.” And Ruse
has affi rmed (1971, 1973) and reaffi rmed (2003) a position similar to that
of Dennett, the Churchlands, and Searle, namely, there is nothing like an
intrinsic or extrinsic ontological purpose or design to be found in nature.
Talk of functions is just that—talk of functions.
Yet Ruse and other thinkers admit something about the biological sciences
that Kant (1987) had admitted in his third Critique; with respect to
organisms, it is useful to think as if these entities have traits and processes
that function in goal-directed ways. Thinkers cannot seem to get around
Trivers’ (1985, p. 5) claim that “even the humblest creature, say, a virus,
appears organized to do something; it acts as if [italics mine] it is trying to
achieve some purpose” or Arnhart’s (1998, p. 245) observation that
“although the evolutionary process does not serve goals, the organisms
emerging from that process do. Darwin’s biology does not deny—rather,
it reaffi rms—the immanent teleology displayed in the striving of each
living being to fulfi ll its specifi c ends. . . . Reproduction, growth, feeding, healing, courtship, parental care for the young—these and many other
activities of organisms are goal-directed” (also see Bogdan, 1994; Stout,
1996; FitzPatrick, 2000; Sterelny & Griffi ths, 1999; Arp, 1998, 1999, 2002,
2006b).
In the last section, I argued for an as-if realism. This approach acknowledges
that we could never know the nature of anything outside of our
own perceptions for certain. At the same time, as-if realism affi rms that
we must act as if there is a reality out there to be understood and
described; it would be miraculous if there were not a real world out
there to which our perceptions and ideas correspond, given the fecundity
of our scientifi c, philosophic, and other research endeavors. With this
as-if realism in mind, we can still attempt to describe the functions of
the traits and processes of organisms. Thus, I am in agreement with Ruse
and other thinkers who do not attempt to explain away descriptions of
the functions of traits. The as-if realism I endorse works together nicely
with this as-if description of the functioning of biological traits—the
as-if realist in me acknowledges that organisms act as if they are organized
so as to function in specifi c ways. In fact, as noted already, it is
essential to my project that I lay out and defend a description of functions
because, as will be shown in later chapters, my hypothesis concerning
scenario visualization depends upon certain functional mechanisms
of the mind having evolved to solve specifi c problems encountered in
various Pleistocene environments.
There are several views concerning the appropriate defi nition of function
for biological matters, and Perlman (2004) has done a fi ne job of laying
out all of these views as envisioned in the history of Western philosophy.
The two views of function with respect to living things that, in my estimation,
have the most credibility are Cummins’ (1975, 2002) organizational
account and the Griffi ths/Godfrey-Smith modern history account (Griffi ths,
1992, 1993, 1996; Godfrey-Smith, 1993, 1994, 1996), and I am not alone
in this assessment (cf. Boorse, 2002; Millikan, 2002; Schwartz, 2002; Collier,
2000; see also Arp, 2006b). Ultimately, I want to maintain that these two
accounts need not be in competition and, actually, can complement one
another. Further, as will be shown later, my hypothesis concerning the
emergence of scenario visualization will rely upon parts of both of these
accounts.
Cummins explains the function of some trait in terms of the role it plays
in maintaining the overall organization and survival of the organism in
its present state. Traits only have functions in relation to other traits within
the organization of the system as a whole. The function of the heart is a standard case utilized in discussions. Thus, the heart’s function is to pump
blood because this fulfi lls its causal role in relation to the organization
of the animal as a whole. There are two things to notice about this
account.
First, a trait can have—or could have had, or could have—any variety of
functions in relation to the organizational whole. In other words, a single
part could have a variety of functions, depending upon the organization
of the system. The heart could have fi ltered urine if the overall organization
of the animal were different in the past, or it could be co-opted to
perform some other function if the overall organization of the animal
changed in the future. Thus, there is a certain fl exibility or malleability in
some trait’s functionality. I fi nd this to be a virtue of Cummins’ position,
as it is now common knowledge that certain traits may actually be exaptations
or preaptations, rather than adaptations. Although, as we will see,
the fl exibility in a trait’s functionality makes it diffi cult to defi ne exactly
what a trait’s present function in the overall organization of an organism
actually is.
Second, Cummins purposely develops his account independent of any
evolutionary factors that would contribute to the historical origin of a
trait’s functionality. According to Cummins, for a trait to perform some
function, the basic structural components of the trait must already be
present so that it can perform that specifi c function in relation to the
organization of the organism as a whole. In other words, because the function
of some trait cannot precede the presence of that trait, and only comes
to have a function in relation to the contribution it makes to the organization
of the organism as a whole in its present state, it makes no sense to
speak about an evolutionary history with respect to that trait. Thus, hearts
pump blood because of their contribution to the overall maintenance of
the animal’s life, not because they conferred a survival-enhancing capacity
in the animal’s evolutionary ancestry. Whereas the fl exibility and/or malleability
exhibited in a trait’s functionality acts as a virtue of Cummins’
position, I fi nd the neglect of a trait’s history to be a vice of Cummins’
position, as I will demonstrate in a moment.
Conversely, according to the Griffi ths/Godfrey-Smith modern history
account, the function of some trait or process X in an organism is defi ned
by what the trait was naturally selected for doing in the organism’s species’
recent past. This is to say that past advantages to the organism are what
defi ne functions. Griffi ths and Godfrey-Smith add the qualifi cation that
the past advantage must be a recent addition in the species’ history, stemming
from the fact that the original selection for any trait may have favored an entirely different effect than the one that counts as the trait’s
current function. Thus, for example, the heart pumps blood or the kidney
fi lters urine in a cat because these traits enabled the cat’s most recent
ancestors to survive. The hearts that pumped blood and the kidneys that
fi ltered urine most adequately were naturally selected for as a trait in the
feline species, and cats today have hearts and kidneys that function so as
to pump blood and fi lter urine precisely because of this fi tness. Ayala (1998,
p. 45) favors a historical account of functions and notes that some trait is
functional “if it contributes to the reproductive effi ciency of the organism
itself, and if such contribution accounts for the existence of the structure
or process.” Ayala (1998, p. 40) further notes that these traits in organisms
are “biological adaptations. They have arisen as a result of the process of
natural selection. The adaptations of organisms—whether organs, homoeostatic
mechanisms, or patterns of behavior—are explained [functionally]
in that their existence is accounted for in terms of their contribution to
the reproductive fi tness of the population.”
According to Cummins, the function of some trait X has to do with the
trait’s contribution to some greater capacity or propensity of the organism
to survive rather than its evolutionary history. From Cummins’ perspective,
to say that the heart’s function is simply its adaptive ability to pump
blood—as proponents of the Griffi ths/Godfrey-Smith modern history
account want to do—is to miss other relevant effects of the heart that
contribute to the overall survival value of the organism. The heart produces
sound, weighs a certain amount, and has a certain structure, and these are
all factors besides its pumping of blood that supposedly contribute to the
overall maintenance, survival, and propensity for survival in the organism
(cf. Bigelow & Pargetter, 1998; Bechtel, 1989; Allen, Bekoff, & Lauder, 1998;
Staddon, 1987; Horan, 1989).
Unfortunately, the problem with this description of functions is that it
is too broad. Cummins fails to distinguish effects it is the function of a
trait or organ to produce from those it is not its function to produce.
Almost any effect can be understood as contributing to the survival value
of an organism on this interpretation of function. In other words, describing
functions purely in terms of organizational capacities and propensities
for survival puts us in the awkward position of not being able to distinguish
between the salient and nonsalient purposive features of traits. Concerning
the example of the heart, Cummins wants to say that weighing a certain
amount, producing sound, having a certain structure, and pumping blood
are all potential functions of the heart. However, there does not seem to
be any signifi cant evidence or theoretical precedent to show that the heart’s producing of sounds or weighing a certain amount per se confers
any propensity for survival in an organism.
There is a further problem with Cummins’ account. Recall that a trait
can have—or could have had, or could have—any variety of functions in
relation to the organizational whole. A single part could have a variety of
functions, depending upon the organization of the system. However, it
does not seem right to speak about the function of some trait by reference
to a propensity that will confer future advantage, because the future has
not occurred for us to know if in fact the advantage will be conferred. As
Cummins himself acknowledges, it is possible that a trait adapted to function
in an environment now may be co-opted for a different use in that
same environment later. The ability to fl y in birds may have come about
in this way. Feathers probably were selected for in archaic birds to protect
them from the cold but eventually became co-opted for fl ight (Feduccia,
1996; Ostrom, 1979; Gould & Vrba, 1982).
Also consistent with Cummins’ account is the fact that the environment
may change, possibly making it such that a trait that functioned in the
previous environment will become nonfunctional in the present environment.
It is likely that the existence of vestigial organs testifi es to this kind
of change (Berra, 1990). Further, it may be possible that an environment
changes, and a trait adapted to function in the previous environment gets
altered and co-opted for a different use in the present environment. This
may be the way in which conscious decision making arose in humans
when the hominin line was forced to move from jungle to savanna in
Africa during the Pleistocene epoch (see Tattersall, 2001, 2002; Arp, 2005a,
2006a). Thus, we never really can say that a trait will have some future
functioning advantage. At best, we look at its present functioning in relation
to some environment and surmise about its past functioning—again,
recent past, as per the qualifi cation of Griffi ths and Godfrey-Smith—in
some similar or dissimilar environment.
So, Cummins seems to do at least two things that are misguided. First,
he inappropriately neglects the role that recent evolutionary history plays
in a trait’s functional development. Second, in the tongue-in-cheek words
of Achinstein (1977, p. 344), he “saddles us with a bevy of unwanted functions.”
Most biologists would agree with the Griffi ths/Godfrey-Smith
account and want to say that the proper function of the heart—given its
recent selection in evolutionary history—is to pump blood, and only in an
ancillary way is the heart’s function to produce sounds, weigh a certain
amount, or have a certain structure (see Neander, 1999; Ayala, 1972; Sober,
1993; Millikan, 1984, 2002; Mayr, 1993; Dawkins, 1986; Ruse, 1973).
Nonetheless, it seems to me that the accounts of Cummins and Griffi ths/
Godfrey-Smith can complement and be made compatible with one another.
The part of Cummins’ account of functions that seems correct has to do
with the function of a trait understood as both (1) contributing to the
overall organizational structure of the organic system and (2) being fl exible
or malleable enough to be co-opted for some other function. These qualities
can complement the idea that the functioning of a trait must arise
within the context of an evolutionary history. There is nothing incompatible
or contradictory in maintaining that some trait functions so as to
contribute to the general organization of some organism’s structure while
at the same time describing the emergence of that trait’s functional contribution
to the organizational structure of the organism by reference to a
recent evolutionary history. So too, there is nothing incompatible or contradictory
in maintaining that some trait is malleable enough to be utilized
for several potential functions while at the same time describing the present
status of that trait in reference to a recent evolutionary history. Given that
structure, organization, operational fl exibility, function, and evolutionary
history are all factors to be considered in an organism’s makeup, we should
expect that the traits of an organism function the way they do because
such traits presently contribute to the overall organization of the organism
(Cummins) as well as were selected for in the organism’s species’ recent
ancestry (Griffi ths/Godfrey-Smith).
In attacking historical accounts of function, including the modern
history account, Bigelow & Pargetter (1998) entertain the thought experiment
that the tenets of evolutionary biology may turn out to be false. For
example, your grandparents could have been put together randomly out
of swamp material, and hence, you would have no evolutionary history to
speak of. If that happened to be the case, then the backward-looking, historical
explanation of function would lose its very backward support! I will
risk sounding ad hominem and point out—as Churchland (1993, p. 746)
has done—that this kind of thought experiment suffers from the fl aw of
most armchair philosophical thought experiments, namely, “too much
thought and not enough experiment!” One of the marks of good scientifi
c theorizing has to do with being open to the possibility that a wellestablished
theory may one day be debunked by evidence that disconfi rms
the theory. In other words, good science entails the falsifi cation of theory.
The swamp grandparents thought experiment hints at this falsifi cation
with respect to evolutionary theory. However, as Millikan (1989, 2002)
and Neander (1991) affi rm, there is enough evidence to suggest that we
should not abandon evolutionary theory just yet, despite such a thought experiment. I will point to a lot of this evidence when I build my case for
the evolution of the brain, visual system, and scenario visualization later
in this book. The work of biologists, neuroscientists, geologists, archeologists,
psychologists, philosophers, anthropologists, and zoologists, among
legions of other thinkers and researchers, establishes evolutionary theory
on a fi rm footing.
Despite the divergent views concerning the defi nition of a biological
function, both proponents of Cummins-style functions and proponents of
Griffi ths/Godfrey-Smith-style functions agree that evolution has taken
place and continues to take place. Given that evolution is understood as
the result of the complex workings of such factors as differential reproduction,
artifi cial selection, sexual selection, mutation, genetic drift, and
genetic recombination in a historical context, this historicity lends further
support to approaching the functions of traits from the perspective of the
modern history account.
The modern history account gives elucidation to Mayr’s (1996, p. 103)
description of organisms as “operating on the basis of historically acquired
programs of information.” Crudely and simply put, the information that
organisms acquire is to be found in the particular genetic code received
from their parent(s). However, as Plotkin (1997, p. 1) has observed, “nothing
in biology makes complete sense [italics mine] except in light of evolution.”
Therefore, any description of biological phenomena must include an evolutionary
perspective to be considered as a fully explanatory description
of the biological phenomena under investigation.
The account of functions I endorse is an evolutionary adaptationist
explanation. It is well-known that the primary mechanism of evolution is
natural selection. Through natural selection, environmental infl uences
affect populations of organisms, and the chance that benefi cial traits will
dominate in successor generations is increased by the adaptive ability and
reproductive success of individuals possessing optimal genetic variants.
When a trait contributes to the fi tness of the organism in its current environment,
it is said to be functionally adaptive. For example, as was mentioned
in the previous chapter, the various kinds of fi nches that Darwin
described on the Galapagos Islands have different beak structures as a
functionally adaptive response to their particular food source. Dawkins
(1986, p. 178) is correct in maintaining that adaptations “affect every part
of the body, its shape and colour, its internal organs, its behaviour, and
the chemistry of its cells.”
A Cummins-style explanation is a necessary ingredient in the description
of a biological function, given the dual emphasis placed upon a trait’s role in the overall organization of the organism and the fl exibility associated
with a trait’s function. However, a complete account of the function of
some trait requires an explanation of how the trait came to be useful for
the organism. Thinkers who utilize the evolutionary adaptationist methodology
view traits as adaptations that have evolved due to past contributions
to the fi tness of the organism in some environment. Sober (1993,
p. 83) is representative of this kind of thinking, and he links adaptation
to a historical account in a clear fashion: “To say that a trait is an ‘adaptation’
is to comment not on its current utility but on its history. To say that
the mammalian heart is (now) an adaptation for pumping blood is to say
that mammals now have hearts because ancestrally, having a heart conferred
a fi tness advantage; the trait evolved because there was selection for
having a heart, and hearts were selected because they pump blood.”
The biologist in me takes it as a real given that evolution has occurred
and that accounts of the functioning of traits and processes require an
evolutionary explanation. The philosopher of biology in me is not sure if
there is anything real out there to speak of as having a function; however,
my as-if realism tells me that it makes sense to proceed as if there were
realities out there with functions based in an evolutionary history. Thus,
in the end, given my endorsement of the modern history account as
necessary to explain how it is that organisms have become hierarchically
organized functioning systems, I take Plotkin’s claim that a biological
phenomenon only makes complete sense in light of evolutionary theory
seriously.
In the fi rst chapter, I described an organism as a living entity, the components
of which are hierarchically organized in subsystems and processes
operating so as to achieve particularized and generalized homeostasis. The
subsystems and processes possess certain properties, including abilities to
fl exibly exchange data, convert data to information in a selection process,
integrate information, and process information from environments. In this
chapter, I endorsed a form of metaphysical emergence whereby entities,
properties, or substances arise out of more fundamental entities, properties,
or substances and yet are not wholly reducible to them. I argued for this
form of emergence based upon HOV, namely, the fact that the subsystems
and processes of organisms coordinate their functions so as to produce
particularized and generalized homeostasis. I also argued for an epistemological
form of emergence that is rooted in the language of teleology and
as-if realism.
In completing my account of organisms understood as hierarchically
organized systems, I argued that the components of organisms function the way they do as a result of recent past adaptive advantages. The evolutionary
explanation I endorsed is a type of causal explanation of how it is
that the recent history of a trait has had certain adaptive effects, which
have facilitated the selection of that trait. We will see in subsequent chapters
that the brain and visual system, as well as the psychological phenomena
emerging from brain processes that enable humans to solve problems
creatively, exhibit similar biological properties and abide by the same
evolutionary principles laid out and explained in these last two chapters.