5.1 Routine and Nonroutine Forms of Problem Solving
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41
The construction of novel tools, as much as language, characterizes our
apparent human uniqueness among species in the animal kingdom. We
are the only species that has evolved the ability to fashion Velcro, construct
microchips, and send folks to the moon, all of which have involved solving
vision-related problems in creative ways. In the previous chapter, I presented
evidence of advanced forms of toolmaking in our hominin past—
specifi cally, those that began at the end of the Mousterian industry—that
require a mind having the capacity to scenario visualize. Considering
that our early hominin ancestors not only had to select certain materials
that were appropriate to solve some problem but also engaged in a number
of mental steps that resulted in the construction of a variety of tool types,
it becomes apparent that a fairly advanced form of cognitive activity had
to occur. I suggested that advanced forms of toolmaking require scenario
visualization, a conscious visual processing whereby visual images are
selected and integrated, then subsequently transformed and projected
in visual scenarios for the purposes of negotiating environments. I also
suggested that scenario visualization emerged as a natural consequence
of our evolutionary history, which includes the development of a complex
nervous system in association with environmental pressures that occasioned
the evolution of such a conscious activity. If an advanced form of
toolmaking acts as a mark of conscious behavior, then given the complex
and changing Pleistocene environments that our hominin ancestors inhabited,
as well as the production of novel tools so as to survive these environments,
visual processing most likely was the primary way in which this
consciousness emerged on the evolutionary scene.
The toolmaking processes in which our early hominins were engaged—
which researchers like Mithen, Wynn, and Pelegrin have been able to simulate—act as a microcosm example of the obstacles human beings face
on a regular basis. Not only do human beings manufacture things but they
successfully negotiate environments, invent, thrive, dominate the planet,
and solve all kinds of vision-related problems in creative ways. Some of
this problem solving is automatic and goes on unbeknownst to us. For
example, we react quickly to, and at times successfully negotiate, certain
situations where fi ghting or fl eeing are called for. Many confrontations
with bears have been avoided by campers in one of a variety of methods,
either by waving their arms, hollering, banging canteens, curling up in the
fetal position, or climbing up a tree (Kaniut, 1997). When asked about why
they chose their particular method, these folks normally respond, “I don’t
know . . . it was automatic.”
On the other hand, some of this problem solving is slower and more
deliberate, requiring us to be consciously aware of the goal of our
endeavor, the potential pitfalls, and the possible “plan Bs” that may
have to be pursued. In the introduction to this text, I used Mayer’s
(1995) terms and drew a distinction between routine problem solving
and nonroutine creative problem solving. In routine problem solving, a
person recognizes many possible solutions to a problem, given that the
problem was solved through one of those solutions in the past. People
constantly perform routine problem solving activities that are concrete
and basic to their survival such as pursue goals that have been established,
form think tanks to troubleshoot regarding product placement,
gather with their girlfriends at Starbucks to plan successful Halloween
parties for their children, devise committees to update school curriculums,
and meet with counselors to talk about how best to carry out an
intervention.
We also can engage in activities that are more abstract and creative, such
as invent new tools based upon mental blueprints, synthesize concepts
that, at fi rst glance, seemed wholly disparate or unrelated, and devise novel
solutions to problems. If a person decided to pursue a wholly new way to
solve a problem by, say, inventing some kind of tool, then we would have
an instance of nonroutine creative problem solving. Nonroutine creative
problem solving involves fi nding a solution to a problem that has not been
solved previously. The invention of a tool would be an example of nonroutine
creative problem solving because the inventor did not possess a
way to solve the problem already. The signifi cant question—the one to
which I have been trying to respond throughout this book—becomes, How
is it that humans are able to engage in vision-related forms of nonroutine
creative problem solving?
In this chapter, I present the ideas and arguments put forward by evolutionary
psychologists such as Cosmides, Tooby, and Mithen that the
mind evolved certain capacities to solve problems creatively. Specifi cally,
Cosmides & Tooby (1987, 1992, 1994) think that the complex activities in
which the human mind can be engaged—such as those that result in
complex problem solving, the construction of novel tools, artwork, and
analogy—are the result of specifi ed mental modules having evolved in our
early hominin Pleistocene past to deal with the various and sundry problems
a human may experience. Mithen (1996, 1999, 2001) shows the
defi ciency in this position and makes an advance upon Cosmides & Tooby’s
idea by arguing that problem solving, the novel construction of tools,
artwork, and the like are possible because the mind has evolved cognitive
fl uidity, an ability to exchange information fl exibly between and among
the mental modules. In fact, according to Mithen, cognitive fl uidity is what
is meant by consciousness, our uniquely human ability.
While I agree with Mithen that cognitive fl uidity acts as a necessary
condition for vision-related, creative problem solving, I disagree that cognitive
fl uidity alone will suffi ce for such an activity. Cognitive fl uidity
allows for the fl exible exchange of information among mental modules.
However, since Mithen’s description of the mind makes it out to be a
passive thing, I transform Mithen’s account by arguing that, while it may
be true that the fl exible exchange of information between and among
mental modules is a feature of consciousness, conscious abilities to select,
integrate, transform, and project information from mental modules into
imagined visual scenarios—in terms of scenario visualization—are what
account for vision-related, nonroutine creative problem solving. In essence,
my hypothesis regarding scenario visualization is an advance upon Mithen’s
account of cognitive fl uidity, which itself (Mithen’s account) is an advance
upon Cosmides & Tooby’s model of the mind as being composed of encapsulated
mental modules (also see Arp, 2005a, 2006a, 2008c).
The construction of novel tools, as much as language, characterizes our
apparent human uniqueness among species in the animal kingdom. We
are the only species that has evolved the ability to fashion Velcro, construct
microchips, and send folks to the moon, all of which have involved solving
vision-related problems in creative ways. In the previous chapter, I presented
evidence of advanced forms of toolmaking in our hominin past—
specifi cally, those that began at the end of the Mousterian industry—that
require a mind having the capacity to scenario visualize. Considering
that our early hominin ancestors not only had to select certain materials
that were appropriate to solve some problem but also engaged in a number
of mental steps that resulted in the construction of a variety of tool types,
it becomes apparent that a fairly advanced form of cognitive activity had
to occur. I suggested that advanced forms of toolmaking require scenario
visualization, a conscious visual processing whereby visual images are
selected and integrated, then subsequently transformed and projected
in visual scenarios for the purposes of negotiating environments. I also
suggested that scenario visualization emerged as a natural consequence
of our evolutionary history, which includes the development of a complex
nervous system in association with environmental pressures that occasioned
the evolution of such a conscious activity. If an advanced form of
toolmaking acts as a mark of conscious behavior, then given the complex
and changing Pleistocene environments that our hominin ancestors inhabited,
as well as the production of novel tools so as to survive these environments,
visual processing most likely was the primary way in which this
consciousness emerged on the evolutionary scene.
The toolmaking processes in which our early hominins were engaged—
which researchers like Mithen, Wynn, and Pelegrin have been able to simulate—act as a microcosm example of the obstacles human beings face
on a regular basis. Not only do human beings manufacture things but they
successfully negotiate environments, invent, thrive, dominate the planet,
and solve all kinds of vision-related problems in creative ways. Some of
this problem solving is automatic and goes on unbeknownst to us. For
example, we react quickly to, and at times successfully negotiate, certain
situations where fi ghting or fl eeing are called for. Many confrontations
with bears have been avoided by campers in one of a variety of methods,
either by waving their arms, hollering, banging canteens, curling up in the
fetal position, or climbing up a tree (Kaniut, 1997). When asked about why
they chose their particular method, these folks normally respond, “I don’t
know . . . it was automatic.”
On the other hand, some of this problem solving is slower and more
deliberate, requiring us to be consciously aware of the goal of our
endeavor, the potential pitfalls, and the possible “plan Bs” that may
have to be pursued. In the introduction to this text, I used Mayer’s
(1995) terms and drew a distinction between routine problem solving
and nonroutine creative problem solving. In routine problem solving, a
person recognizes many possible solutions to a problem, given that the
problem was solved through one of those solutions in the past. People
constantly perform routine problem solving activities that are concrete
and basic to their survival such as pursue goals that have been established,
form think tanks to troubleshoot regarding product placement,
gather with their girlfriends at Starbucks to plan successful Halloween
parties for their children, devise committees to update school curriculums,
and meet with counselors to talk about how best to carry out an
intervention.
We also can engage in activities that are more abstract and creative, such
as invent new tools based upon mental blueprints, synthesize concepts
that, at fi rst glance, seemed wholly disparate or unrelated, and devise novel
solutions to problems. If a person decided to pursue a wholly new way to
solve a problem by, say, inventing some kind of tool, then we would have
an instance of nonroutine creative problem solving. Nonroutine creative
problem solving involves fi nding a solution to a problem that has not been
solved previously. The invention of a tool would be an example of nonroutine
creative problem solving because the inventor did not possess a
way to solve the problem already. The signifi cant question—the one to
which I have been trying to respond throughout this book—becomes, How
is it that humans are able to engage in vision-related forms of nonroutine
creative problem solving?
In this chapter, I present the ideas and arguments put forward by evolutionary
psychologists such as Cosmides, Tooby, and Mithen that the
mind evolved certain capacities to solve problems creatively. Specifi cally,
Cosmides & Tooby (1987, 1992, 1994) think that the complex activities in
which the human mind can be engaged—such as those that result in
complex problem solving, the construction of novel tools, artwork, and
analogy—are the result of specifi ed mental modules having evolved in our
early hominin Pleistocene past to deal with the various and sundry problems
a human may experience. Mithen (1996, 1999, 2001) shows the
defi ciency in this position and makes an advance upon Cosmides & Tooby’s
idea by arguing that problem solving, the novel construction of tools,
artwork, and the like are possible because the mind has evolved cognitive
fl uidity, an ability to exchange information fl exibly between and among
the mental modules. In fact, according to Mithen, cognitive fl uidity is what
is meant by consciousness, our uniquely human ability.
While I agree with Mithen that cognitive fl uidity acts as a necessary
condition for vision-related, creative problem solving, I disagree that cognitive
fl uidity alone will suffi ce for such an activity. Cognitive fl uidity
allows for the fl exible exchange of information among mental modules.
However, since Mithen’s description of the mind makes it out to be a
passive thing, I transform Mithen’s account by arguing that, while it may
be true that the fl exible exchange of information between and among
mental modules is a feature of consciousness, conscious abilities to select,
integrate, transform, and project information from mental modules into
imagined visual scenarios—in terms of scenario visualization—are what
account for vision-related, nonroutine creative problem solving. In essence,
my hypothesis regarding scenario visualization is an advance upon Mithen’s
account of cognitive fl uidity, which itself (Mithen’s account) is an advance
upon Cosmides & Tooby’s model of the mind as being composed of encapsulated
mental modules (also see Arp, 2005a, 2006a, 2008c).