3.7 Neuronal Synchrony
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41
Along with iconic memory and attention, the synchronous fi ring of
neurons in areas relevant to the processing of information gathered from
a visual scene has been posited as a kind of neuronal binding mechanism.
One version of the hypothesis, put forward most forcibly by Crick & Koch
(1990, 1998, 1999, 2003), is that sets of cortical areas related to the parallel
processing of visual information are coordinated in the thalamus at a fi ring
rate of around the 40-Hertz range. Von der Malsburg (1981), Gray (1999),
Singer (1999, 2000), and Singer & Gray (1995) have put forward similar
positions that a coherent visual scene results from the synchronous fi ring
of cooperative interactions of neurons in the cortical network. The idea is
that the synchronous fi ring would bind the cells responding to different
features of the same object together for a short amount of time, so as to
produce a coherent visual perception. Neuronal synchrony has been
accepted by many as a plausible binding mechanism, since experimental
evidence has shown that relevant neuronal areas associated with the awareness
of a visual scene, even areas that are quite a distance from one another,
fi re at about the same rate (Kosslyn & Koenig, 1995; Castalo-Branco et al.,
1998; Engel, Kreiter, König, & Singer, 1991; Fries, Roelfsema, Engel, König,
& Singer, 1997; Gray, Knig, Engel, & Singer, 1989; Rodriguez, George,
Lachaux, Martinerie, Renault, & Varela, 1999; Roelfsema, Engel, König, &
Singer, 1996; Usher & Donnelly, 1998; Vaadia, Aertsen, & Nelken, 1995;
Lumer, Edelman, & Tononi, 1997; Ritz & Sejnowski, 1997). Such synchrony
could be the “holy grail” the scientist is seeking as a plausible neurological
correlate for the unifi ed phenomenal visual perception.
In one of their fi nal papers together, Crick & Koch (2003) added to the
neuronal synchrony hypothesis by putting forward the idea that cognitive
visual processing is sustained by shifting coalitions of neurons. The neurons
in a particular coalition support one another directly or indirectly and
increase the activity of their fellow members, much like what is known as
a synfi re chain. A synfi re chain, originally put forward by Abeles (1991),
refers to a signifi cant pool of neurons whose simultaneous fi ring raises the
potential of adjacent pools of neurons to allow them to fi re. Coalitions of
neurons are in a kind of competition, and attention may help in giving
one coalition a dominant position over another. When an animal attends
to a visual scene, that is, when such an animal is cognitively aware of that
scene, the neural correlation of this coherent visual scene is simply the
winning coalition. This is yet another attempt on the part of Crick & Koch
to address the binding problem, since the coalition of neurons acts as the
correlate to the bound, integrated, and coherent features of a single object
in a visual perception.
Crick & Koch’s latest idea has initial intuitive appeal because not only
do they pull together research and ideas from neuroscientists and philosophers
over the last fi fty years but they view the integrated visual scene as
resulting from a competition of coalitions of neurons. Blake & Logothetis
(2002), DiLollo, Enns, & Rensink (2000), Tononi, Srinivasan, Russell, &
Edelman (1998), and Dennett (1991) are representative of thinkers who
believe cognitive awareness results from a kind of competition, much like
Crick & Koch. Given the brain’s vast assembly of neurons receiving electrochemical
signals from other neurons and passing those on to other
neurons, Dennett (1991) thinks that cognition takes the form of something
like a pandemonium of competing bits of content, and the ones that win
the competition are the ones that are conscious.
We are now in a position to specify what is meant by visual cognition.
Visual cognition is the phenomenal representation of some object in the
animal’s visual fi eld that is the result of the integration of modular visual
information received from that object in association with iconic memory,
attention, and the synchronous fi ring of neurons in the areas of the brain
relevant to the processing of the visual percept. This defi nition is an
attempt to point in the direction of a solution to the visual binding
problem. These parts and processes may not comprise the suffi cient condition
for an overall coherently unifi ed visual percept; this is to say, there
may be some element or elements missing. However, the empirical evidence
seems to indicate that such conditions are necessary for a coherent
visual scene.
To recapitulate: visual cognition requires the integration of parallel
pieces of information concerning form, depth, motion, and so forth from
the what and the where unimodal areas (the modularity and integration
criteria); these pieces of information must be held in mind for at least 250
milliseconds (the iconic memory criterion); the pieces of information are
selected as relevant to a visual scene (the attention criterion); and neurons
relevant to the processing of such information are fi ring at relatively the
same time (the neural synchrony criterion). The end result is a coherently
bound phenomenal visual scene of which an animal is cognitively aware
when it looks at or sees something in its visual fi eld.
It is important to note again that visual cognition need not be accompanied
by consciousness. I agree with Roth (2000, p. 78) when he claims
that cognition includes perception, learning, and memory as well as limited
forms of imagination, thinking, expecting, and planning, “whether accom84 panied by consciousness or not [italics mine]” (also see Arp, 2007b, 2008b,
2008d). The above defi nition of cognition applies to all vertebrate species
in the phylum Chordata, including mammals, birds, reptiles, amphibians,
and fi sh. Roth correctly notes that consciousness comprises subjective
awareness, experience, intentionality, indexicality, and self-refl exivity.
These would be additional phenomenal states over and above visual cognition
that humans with fully functioning nervous systems have to the
fullest degree.
Several animal species engage in cognitive visual processing. They
appear to know to some degree what is going on around them as well
as being able to recall memories, make associations between objects in
their visual fi eld, and make associations between objects in their visual
fi eld and percepts stored in memory. Nevertheless, in comparison to the
human mind, there is obviously some characteristic that is missing in
the animal mind. What is it about the human mind that enables us to
solve problems to a degree such that we can fl ourish, theorize, and
dominate the earth? Humans have conscious visual experiences, as well
as other conscious phenomenal states that other species (apparently)
lack. As we will see in the next two chapters, my hypothesis of scenario
visualization will be added to the list of conscious phenomenal states,
the evolution of which has enabled humans to solve vision-related problems
creatively, construct advanced tools and other products, and dominate
the earth.
Along with iconic memory and attention, the synchronous fi ring of
neurons in areas relevant to the processing of information gathered from
a visual scene has been posited as a kind of neuronal binding mechanism.
One version of the hypothesis, put forward most forcibly by Crick & Koch
(1990, 1998, 1999, 2003), is that sets of cortical areas related to the parallel
processing of visual information are coordinated in the thalamus at a fi ring
rate of around the 40-Hertz range. Von der Malsburg (1981), Gray (1999),
Singer (1999, 2000), and Singer & Gray (1995) have put forward similar
positions that a coherent visual scene results from the synchronous fi ring
of cooperative interactions of neurons in the cortical network. The idea is
that the synchronous fi ring would bind the cells responding to different
features of the same object together for a short amount of time, so as to
produce a coherent visual perception. Neuronal synchrony has been
accepted by many as a plausible binding mechanism, since experimental
evidence has shown that relevant neuronal areas associated with the awareness
of a visual scene, even areas that are quite a distance from one another,
fi re at about the same rate (Kosslyn & Koenig, 1995; Castalo-Branco et al.,
1998; Engel, Kreiter, König, & Singer, 1991; Fries, Roelfsema, Engel, König,
& Singer, 1997; Gray, Knig, Engel, & Singer, 1989; Rodriguez, George,
Lachaux, Martinerie, Renault, & Varela, 1999; Roelfsema, Engel, König, &
Singer, 1996; Usher & Donnelly, 1998; Vaadia, Aertsen, & Nelken, 1995;
Lumer, Edelman, & Tononi, 1997; Ritz & Sejnowski, 1997). Such synchrony
could be the “holy grail” the scientist is seeking as a plausible neurological
correlate for the unifi ed phenomenal visual perception.
In one of their fi nal papers together, Crick & Koch (2003) added to the
neuronal synchrony hypothesis by putting forward the idea that cognitive
visual processing is sustained by shifting coalitions of neurons. The neurons
in a particular coalition support one another directly or indirectly and
increase the activity of their fellow members, much like what is known as
a synfi re chain. A synfi re chain, originally put forward by Abeles (1991),
refers to a signifi cant pool of neurons whose simultaneous fi ring raises the
potential of adjacent pools of neurons to allow them to fi re. Coalitions of
neurons are in a kind of competition, and attention may help in giving
one coalition a dominant position over another. When an animal attends
to a visual scene, that is, when such an animal is cognitively aware of that
scene, the neural correlation of this coherent visual scene is simply the
winning coalition. This is yet another attempt on the part of Crick & Koch
to address the binding problem, since the coalition of neurons acts as the
correlate to the bound, integrated, and coherent features of a single object
in a visual perception.
Crick & Koch’s latest idea has initial intuitive appeal because not only
do they pull together research and ideas from neuroscientists and philosophers
over the last fi fty years but they view the integrated visual scene as
resulting from a competition of coalitions of neurons. Blake & Logothetis
(2002), DiLollo, Enns, & Rensink (2000), Tononi, Srinivasan, Russell, &
Edelman (1998), and Dennett (1991) are representative of thinkers who
believe cognitive awareness results from a kind of competition, much like
Crick & Koch. Given the brain’s vast assembly of neurons receiving electrochemical
signals from other neurons and passing those on to other
neurons, Dennett (1991) thinks that cognition takes the form of something
like a pandemonium of competing bits of content, and the ones that win
the competition are the ones that are conscious.
We are now in a position to specify what is meant by visual cognition.
Visual cognition is the phenomenal representation of some object in the
animal’s visual fi eld that is the result of the integration of modular visual
information received from that object in association with iconic memory,
attention, and the synchronous fi ring of neurons in the areas of the brain
relevant to the processing of the visual percept. This defi nition is an
attempt to point in the direction of a solution to the visual binding
problem. These parts and processes may not comprise the suffi cient condition
for an overall coherently unifi ed visual percept; this is to say, there
may be some element or elements missing. However, the empirical evidence
seems to indicate that such conditions are necessary for a coherent
visual scene.
To recapitulate: visual cognition requires the integration of parallel
pieces of information concerning form, depth, motion, and so forth from
the what and the where unimodal areas (the modularity and integration
criteria); these pieces of information must be held in mind for at least 250
milliseconds (the iconic memory criterion); the pieces of information are
selected as relevant to a visual scene (the attention criterion); and neurons
relevant to the processing of such information are fi ring at relatively the
same time (the neural synchrony criterion). The end result is a coherently
bound phenomenal visual scene of which an animal is cognitively aware
when it looks at or sees something in its visual fi eld.
It is important to note again that visual cognition need not be accompanied
by consciousness. I agree with Roth (2000, p. 78) when he claims
that cognition includes perception, learning, and memory as well as limited
forms of imagination, thinking, expecting, and planning, “whether accom84 panied by consciousness or not [italics mine]” (also see Arp, 2007b, 2008b,
2008d). The above defi nition of cognition applies to all vertebrate species
in the phylum Chordata, including mammals, birds, reptiles, amphibians,
and fi sh. Roth correctly notes that consciousness comprises subjective
awareness, experience, intentionality, indexicality, and self-refl exivity.
These would be additional phenomenal states over and above visual cognition
that humans with fully functioning nervous systems have to the
fullest degree.
Several animal species engage in cognitive visual processing. They
appear to know to some degree what is going on around them as well
as being able to recall memories, make associations between objects in
their visual fi eld, and make associations between objects in their visual
fi eld and percepts stored in memory. Nevertheless, in comparison to the
human mind, there is obviously some characteristic that is missing in
the animal mind. What is it about the human mind that enables us to
solve problems to a degree such that we can fl ourish, theorize, and
dominate the earth? Humans have conscious visual experiences, as well
as other conscious phenomenal states that other species (apparently)
lack. As we will see in the next two chapters, my hypothesis of scenario
visualization will be added to the list of conscious phenomenal states,
the evolution of which has enabled humans to solve vision-related problems
creatively, construct advanced tools and other products, and dominate
the earth.