3.8 The Visual System and Environmental Information Exchange
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41
In the fi rst chapter, it was made clear that organisms exchange information
with environments, that these environments can comprise interactions
within the organism as well as interactions with the external world
of the organism, and that environmental pressures can be described in
terms of information that is exchanged within the organism and/or
between environment and organism. Such exchanges with environments
also affect the visual system. This is the last section of this chapter, and
it acts as an important segue into the next chapter where I deal with
the evolution of the visual system. This is so for two reasons: it is the
internal environment of the cell related to genetic mutations in cell differentiation
where evolution principally takes place, and, it is the external
environment of the organism as a whole that acts as the condition for
the possibility of the evolution of the visual system and scenario visualization.
In this section, I describe fi rst how the internal environment of the organism’s processes and subsystems has an effect upon the visual
system. Then, I describe the effects of the external environment upon
the visual system.
The following examples all illustrate that the workings and interactions
of the brain act as internal environmental pressures that affect the processes
and functioning of the visual system. First of all, with the discovery
of HOX genes it has been shown that much of an organism’s phenotypic
characteristics are under direct genetic control. For example, moving
around, replacing, or taking out certain Drosophila (fruit fl y) HOX genetic
sequences produces mutated and monstrous results—antennae grow out
of abdomens, appendages grow out of heads, or basic parts are missing
(Nüsslein-Volhard & Wieschaus, 1980). The visual system is no exception
to this rule, as researchers have been able to adjust gene sequences related
to the visual systems of Drosophila, fi sh, amphibians, mice, and hedgehogs
(Chitnis, 1999; Maconochioe, Nonchev, Morrison, & Krumlauf, 1996;
Belloni et al., 1996; Goddard et al., 1996).
The important point to realize is that the experimenter’s adjustments to
the genetic code are directly analogous to the natural mutations that occur
on a regular basis in the reproductive lives of organisms. During cell division
and reproduction, genes go about their functioning in their own
chemical environments of the cell. What takes place in those environments
directly affects genetic formation in terms of mutant alleles (alternate
forms of a particular gene). When neurons differentiate, there are
natural genetic mutations that constantly occur because of chemical infl uences
upon chromosomal chains. In fact, if it were not for the regular
occurrence of mutant alleles, every living thing would look exactly like everything
else (Mayr, 1976; Eldredge, 2001). The processes associated with
mutant allele formation—rife with internal environmental pressures—
account for the phenotypic diversity of living things. In the next chapter,
before tracing the evolution of the brain and visual system, I talk more
about genetic mutations in relation to the environments of organisms.
Another example illustrating the effect of internal environmental pressures
upon the visual system has to do with neurulation, the successful
positioning of the various kinds of neurons in their appropriate spots
throughout certain developmental stages. Formation of the neural tube,
some three weeks after conception in humans, depends on a fairly precise
sequence of changes in the shape of individual cells, as well as the connections
of cells to one another. Timing is a factor in the process, since
neurulation must be coordinated with the ectoderm (outer layer of cells)
and mesoderm (middle layer of cells) of the neural tube. At the molecular level, neurulation is dependent upon specifi c sequences of gene expression
that are affected, to a large degree, by the positions and local chemical
environment of the cell. For example, a defi ciency of folate—a chemical
found to be important in the healthy development of the neural tube—
may cause a malformation of the retina, which develops out of the ectoderm.
This is one reason why doctors will ask women to take certain doses
of folate during pregnancy.
A fi nal example that illustrates the effect of internal environmental pressures
upon the visual system has to do with the neurotrophic theory, that is,
the idea that neurons compete for space in their own environment of the
brain (Reichardt & Fariñas, 1997). It is well-known that the developing
nervous system overproduces connections in great excess during development.
Through programmed cell death, as well as through a competition
for space, neuronal connections are pruned away as the nervous system
continues to develop. Hubel & Wiesel (1962, 1968) coined the term binocular
rivalry, which has to do with the inputs from both eyes in layer IV
competing for space (Myerson, Miezin, & Allman, 1981; Lumer, 2000).
Interestingly enough, this internal environmental confl ict is necessary for
the appropriate development and functioning of the nervous system (Craig
& Lichtman, 2001; cf. Lumer, Friston, & Rees, 1998; Zhang, Tao, Holt,
Harris, & Poo, 1998). Other forms of visual competition have been documented
(e.g., Antonini & Stryker, 1993; Blake & Logothetis, 2002; DiLollo
et al., 2000). Also cats, rats, and birds that have had their eyes occluded or
removed in early development show evidence of synaptic competition for
the unused visual space (Shatz & Stryker, 1978; Antononi & Stryker, 1993).
It is important to note that overproduction and competition were the fi rst
two observations Darwin (1859) made concerning species in general that
led to his formation of evolutionary theory.
There is a time frame in the development of the nervous system known
as a critical period. During this critical period, it is important for the nervous
system to receive information from the external world so as to aid in
appropriate neuronal maturation and synapse formation. As Zigmond
et al. (1999, p. 637) make clear: “During a critical period, the pathway
awaits specifi c instructional information, encoded by impulse activity, to
continue developing normally. This information causes the pathway to
commit irreversibly to one of a number of possible patterns of connectivity.
If appropriate experience is not gained during the critical period, the
pathway never attains the ability to process information in a normal
fashion and, as a result, perception or behavior is permanently impaired.”
It is widely agreed that a combination of natural genetic factors (nature) as well as environmental stimuli (nurture) are necessary for normal, healthy
nervous system development. Notably, even though it is the genetic blueprint
that acts as the formal guideline by which differentiated neurons
move into position in development, there can be material factors in the
environment of the neuron—like some kind of lesion or another mutated
neuron—that prevent the neuron from achieving its blueprinted designation.
It is not only the environment of the neuron but also the external
environment of the organism that affect the development of the nervous
system. For example, Bear et al. (2001) note that a lack of appropriate
nutrition, socializing, and sensory stimulation can contribute to the malformation
of dendritic spines, a key factor in mental handicaps.
The sensory pathways from one brain region to the next are organized
in such a way that neighboring groups of neurons maintain the spatial
relationship of sensory receptors in the periphery of the body. In fact, the
olfactory, visual, and somatosensory systems share the common feature of
topographic mappings of sensory surfaces, as well as parallel processing,
cortical modules, multiple cortical representations, and synaptic relays in
the dorsal thalamus. Topographical organization is an important way of
conveying information about the world to the nervous system. In essence,
the sensory pathways in the brain topographically refl ect the spatial relationships
of the environment (Kandel et al., 2000; Kosslyn, Thompson,
Kim, & Alpert, 1995). What this suggests is that the environment determines,
to a great extent, what we cognize. This has caused Sekuler & Blake (2002, p.
26) to claim that the “information picked up by the senses is not merely
a series of unrelated, incoherent data. Instead, sensory information closely
conforms to predictable, structured patterns. These patterns arise from the
very nature of the physical world itself, the world our senses have evolved
in.” Sekuler & Blake (2002, p. 168) also claim: “Organization in perception
mirrors the organization of real objects as they actually exist. The correspondence
between perceptual experience and the objects represented in
that experience is not accidental. After all, the visual system did evolve for
a purpose, namely to inform one about the objects with which one needs
to interact.”
The Gestalt psychologists noted that the visual system has built-in
mechanisms whereby the visual scene is grouped according to the following
principles: closure, the tendency of the visual system to ignore
small breaks or gaps in objects; good continuation, the tendency to group
straight or smoothly curving lines together; similarity, the tendency
to group objects of similar texture and shape together; and proximity,
the tendency to group objects that are near to one another together. Numerous studies have ratifi ed these principles as refl ective of the visual
system (Wertheimer, 1912, 1923; Brunswik & Kamiya, 1953; Kanizsa,
1976, 1979; Peterhans & von der Heydt, 1991; Gray, 1999; Sekuler &
Blake, 2002). These mechanisms can work only if the environment actually
displays the features on which the visual system is capitalizing.
There must be these kinds of regularities out there in the world, or else
it seems these principles would not be able to be delineated. Over 100
years ago, James (1890, p. 4) noted that mind and world “have evolved
together, and in consequence are something of a mutual fi t,” and the
Gestalt principles underscore this mutual fi t. Further, in reference to the
second chapter, where I dealt with metaphysical and epistemological
forms of emergence, this apparent mutual fi t of mind and world underscores
the argument from miracles. One might argue that it would certainly
be miraculous for the Gestalt psychologists to delineate their
principles if there were not this mutual fi t between mind and some
actually existing environment in which the mind fi nds itself.
It also has been shown that neuronal size and complexity—as well
as numbers of glial cells—increase in the cerebral cortices of animals
exposed to so-called enriched environments, that is, environments where
there are large cages and a variety of different objects that arouse curiosity
and stimulate exploratory activity (Diamond, 1988; Diamond &
Hopson, 1989; Mattson, Sorensen, Zimmer, & Johansson, 1997; Receveur
& Vossen, 1998). In these environments, it is important that animals
be exposed to objects having a wide variety of shapes, colors, and sizes
because there seems to be a close correlation between seeing these kinds
of objects and brain development. From such data, we can infer that
experiences in environments are refl ected to some degree in the structure
of our brains.
Add to this the most recent data suggesting that regions of the brain can
be trained, through mental and physical exercises, to pick up tasks from
other regions. The evidence for this comes from stroke patients who regain
the ability to speak, musicians who relearn how to play an instrument
after nerve damage, and cerebral palsy patients who learn to perform
activities long thought impossible to perform (Holloway, 2003; van Praag,
Kempermann, & Gage, 2000; Schwartz & Begley, 2002). Not only does this
suggest that certain brain processes are highly malleable and fl exible
(Malenka & Siegelbaum, 2001; Singer, 1995) but it again points to the fact
that the external environment exerts a causal infl uence upon the brain
and visual system. As we will see in the next chapter, the implications of
synapse strengthening from environmental stimuli, as well as the ability
The Visual System 89
of neuronal processes to perform alternate functions, are integral to an
evolutionary account of conscious visual processing and creative problem
solving in humans.
In this chapter, I built upon work of the previous chapters and showed
how the processes associated with vision in mammals comprise a hierarchically
organized system exhibiting the same kinds of properties of information
exchange, selectivity, and integration found in organisms in general.
I distinguished four levels of visual processing in animals: a noncognitive
visual processing, two cognitive/psychological forms of visual processing,
and a conscious cognitive visual processing that occurs at the highest level
of the visual hierarchy. Since in this project I am concerned mostly with
the progression from cognitive visual processing to conscious cognitive
visual processing, the relationship of these processes to one another, and,
ultimately, how conscious cognitive visual processing evolved from cognitive
visual processing, I showed that the visual systems of mammals function
so as to produce visual cognition.
Visual cognition is the phenomenal representation of some object in the
animal’s visual fi eld that is the result of the integration of modular visual
information received from that object in association with iconic memory,
attention, and the synchronous fi ring of neurons in the areas of the brain
relevant to the processing of the visual percept. Special attention was paid
to visual modularity, which refers to the fact that the visual system is made
up of distinctly functioning and interacting modules or areas having
evolved to respond to certain features of an object in typical environments,
and visual integration, which refers to a neurobiological process or set of
processes that bind together the relevant information gleaned from visual
modules/areas into a coherent cognitive representation of some object,
enabling an animal to negotiate typical environments. In the next
chapter—which is really the heart of the book—I trace the evolution of
the visual system from organisms that developed a light/dark sensitivity
area to humans who are capable of the complex activities involved in scenario
visualization, one form of conscious cognitive visual processing.
In the fi rst chapter, it was made clear that organisms exchange information
with environments, that these environments can comprise interactions
within the organism as well as interactions with the external world
of the organism, and that environmental pressures can be described in
terms of information that is exchanged within the organism and/or
between environment and organism. Such exchanges with environments
also affect the visual system. This is the last section of this chapter, and
it acts as an important segue into the next chapter where I deal with
the evolution of the visual system. This is so for two reasons: it is the
internal environment of the cell related to genetic mutations in cell differentiation
where evolution principally takes place, and, it is the external
environment of the organism as a whole that acts as the condition for
the possibility of the evolution of the visual system and scenario visualization.
In this section, I describe fi rst how the internal environment of the organism’s processes and subsystems has an effect upon the visual
system. Then, I describe the effects of the external environment upon
the visual system.
The following examples all illustrate that the workings and interactions
of the brain act as internal environmental pressures that affect the processes
and functioning of the visual system. First of all, with the discovery
of HOX genes it has been shown that much of an organism’s phenotypic
characteristics are under direct genetic control. For example, moving
around, replacing, or taking out certain Drosophila (fruit fl y) HOX genetic
sequences produces mutated and monstrous results—antennae grow out
of abdomens, appendages grow out of heads, or basic parts are missing
(Nüsslein-Volhard & Wieschaus, 1980). The visual system is no exception
to this rule, as researchers have been able to adjust gene sequences related
to the visual systems of Drosophila, fi sh, amphibians, mice, and hedgehogs
(Chitnis, 1999; Maconochioe, Nonchev, Morrison, & Krumlauf, 1996;
Belloni et al., 1996; Goddard et al., 1996).
The important point to realize is that the experimenter’s adjustments to
the genetic code are directly analogous to the natural mutations that occur
on a regular basis in the reproductive lives of organisms. During cell division
and reproduction, genes go about their functioning in their own
chemical environments of the cell. What takes place in those environments
directly affects genetic formation in terms of mutant alleles (alternate
forms of a particular gene). When neurons differentiate, there are
natural genetic mutations that constantly occur because of chemical infl uences
upon chromosomal chains. In fact, if it were not for the regular
occurrence of mutant alleles, every living thing would look exactly like everything
else (Mayr, 1976; Eldredge, 2001). The processes associated with
mutant allele formation—rife with internal environmental pressures—
account for the phenotypic diversity of living things. In the next chapter,
before tracing the evolution of the brain and visual system, I talk more
about genetic mutations in relation to the environments of organisms.
Another example illustrating the effect of internal environmental pressures
upon the visual system has to do with neurulation, the successful
positioning of the various kinds of neurons in their appropriate spots
throughout certain developmental stages. Formation of the neural tube,
some three weeks after conception in humans, depends on a fairly precise
sequence of changes in the shape of individual cells, as well as the connections
of cells to one another. Timing is a factor in the process, since
neurulation must be coordinated with the ectoderm (outer layer of cells)
and mesoderm (middle layer of cells) of the neural tube. At the molecular level, neurulation is dependent upon specifi c sequences of gene expression
that are affected, to a large degree, by the positions and local chemical
environment of the cell. For example, a defi ciency of folate—a chemical
found to be important in the healthy development of the neural tube—
may cause a malformation of the retina, which develops out of the ectoderm.
This is one reason why doctors will ask women to take certain doses
of folate during pregnancy.
A fi nal example that illustrates the effect of internal environmental pressures
upon the visual system has to do with the neurotrophic theory, that is,
the idea that neurons compete for space in their own environment of the
brain (Reichardt & Fariñas, 1997). It is well-known that the developing
nervous system overproduces connections in great excess during development.
Through programmed cell death, as well as through a competition
for space, neuronal connections are pruned away as the nervous system
continues to develop. Hubel & Wiesel (1962, 1968) coined the term binocular
rivalry, which has to do with the inputs from both eyes in layer IV
competing for space (Myerson, Miezin, & Allman, 1981; Lumer, 2000).
Interestingly enough, this internal environmental confl ict is necessary for
the appropriate development and functioning of the nervous system (Craig
& Lichtman, 2001; cf. Lumer, Friston, & Rees, 1998; Zhang, Tao, Holt,
Harris, & Poo, 1998). Other forms of visual competition have been documented
(e.g., Antonini & Stryker, 1993; Blake & Logothetis, 2002; DiLollo
et al., 2000). Also cats, rats, and birds that have had their eyes occluded or
removed in early development show evidence of synaptic competition for
the unused visual space (Shatz & Stryker, 1978; Antononi & Stryker, 1993).
It is important to note that overproduction and competition were the fi rst
two observations Darwin (1859) made concerning species in general that
led to his formation of evolutionary theory.
There is a time frame in the development of the nervous system known
as a critical period. During this critical period, it is important for the nervous
system to receive information from the external world so as to aid in
appropriate neuronal maturation and synapse formation. As Zigmond
et al. (1999, p. 637) make clear: “During a critical period, the pathway
awaits specifi c instructional information, encoded by impulse activity, to
continue developing normally. This information causes the pathway to
commit irreversibly to one of a number of possible patterns of connectivity.
If appropriate experience is not gained during the critical period, the
pathway never attains the ability to process information in a normal
fashion and, as a result, perception or behavior is permanently impaired.”
It is widely agreed that a combination of natural genetic factors (nature) as well as environmental stimuli (nurture) are necessary for normal, healthy
nervous system development. Notably, even though it is the genetic blueprint
that acts as the formal guideline by which differentiated neurons
move into position in development, there can be material factors in the
environment of the neuron—like some kind of lesion or another mutated
neuron—that prevent the neuron from achieving its blueprinted designation.
It is not only the environment of the neuron but also the external
environment of the organism that affect the development of the nervous
system. For example, Bear et al. (2001) note that a lack of appropriate
nutrition, socializing, and sensory stimulation can contribute to the malformation
of dendritic spines, a key factor in mental handicaps.
The sensory pathways from one brain region to the next are organized
in such a way that neighboring groups of neurons maintain the spatial
relationship of sensory receptors in the periphery of the body. In fact, the
olfactory, visual, and somatosensory systems share the common feature of
topographic mappings of sensory surfaces, as well as parallel processing,
cortical modules, multiple cortical representations, and synaptic relays in
the dorsal thalamus. Topographical organization is an important way of
conveying information about the world to the nervous system. In essence,
the sensory pathways in the brain topographically refl ect the spatial relationships
of the environment (Kandel et al., 2000; Kosslyn, Thompson,
Kim, & Alpert, 1995). What this suggests is that the environment determines,
to a great extent, what we cognize. This has caused Sekuler & Blake (2002, p.
26) to claim that the “information picked up by the senses is not merely
a series of unrelated, incoherent data. Instead, sensory information closely
conforms to predictable, structured patterns. These patterns arise from the
very nature of the physical world itself, the world our senses have evolved
in.” Sekuler & Blake (2002, p. 168) also claim: “Organization in perception
mirrors the organization of real objects as they actually exist. The correspondence
between perceptual experience and the objects represented in
that experience is not accidental. After all, the visual system did evolve for
a purpose, namely to inform one about the objects with which one needs
to interact.”
The Gestalt psychologists noted that the visual system has built-in
mechanisms whereby the visual scene is grouped according to the following
principles: closure, the tendency of the visual system to ignore
small breaks or gaps in objects; good continuation, the tendency to group
straight or smoothly curving lines together; similarity, the tendency
to group objects of similar texture and shape together; and proximity,
the tendency to group objects that are near to one another together. Numerous studies have ratifi ed these principles as refl ective of the visual
system (Wertheimer, 1912, 1923; Brunswik & Kamiya, 1953; Kanizsa,
1976, 1979; Peterhans & von der Heydt, 1991; Gray, 1999; Sekuler &
Blake, 2002). These mechanisms can work only if the environment actually
displays the features on which the visual system is capitalizing.
There must be these kinds of regularities out there in the world, or else
it seems these principles would not be able to be delineated. Over 100
years ago, James (1890, p. 4) noted that mind and world “have evolved
together, and in consequence are something of a mutual fi t,” and the
Gestalt principles underscore this mutual fi t. Further, in reference to the
second chapter, where I dealt with metaphysical and epistemological
forms of emergence, this apparent mutual fi t of mind and world underscores
the argument from miracles. One might argue that it would certainly
be miraculous for the Gestalt psychologists to delineate their
principles if there were not this mutual fi t between mind and some
actually existing environment in which the mind fi nds itself.
It also has been shown that neuronal size and complexity—as well
as numbers of glial cells—increase in the cerebral cortices of animals
exposed to so-called enriched environments, that is, environments where
there are large cages and a variety of different objects that arouse curiosity
and stimulate exploratory activity (Diamond, 1988; Diamond &
Hopson, 1989; Mattson, Sorensen, Zimmer, & Johansson, 1997; Receveur
& Vossen, 1998). In these environments, it is important that animals
be exposed to objects having a wide variety of shapes, colors, and sizes
because there seems to be a close correlation between seeing these kinds
of objects and brain development. From such data, we can infer that
experiences in environments are refl ected to some degree in the structure
of our brains.
Add to this the most recent data suggesting that regions of the brain can
be trained, through mental and physical exercises, to pick up tasks from
other regions. The evidence for this comes from stroke patients who regain
the ability to speak, musicians who relearn how to play an instrument
after nerve damage, and cerebral palsy patients who learn to perform
activities long thought impossible to perform (Holloway, 2003; van Praag,
Kempermann, & Gage, 2000; Schwartz & Begley, 2002). Not only does this
suggest that certain brain processes are highly malleable and fl exible
(Malenka & Siegelbaum, 2001; Singer, 1995) but it again points to the fact
that the external environment exerts a causal infl uence upon the brain
and visual system. As we will see in the next chapter, the implications of
synapse strengthening from environmental stimuli, as well as the ability
The Visual System 89
of neuronal processes to perform alternate functions, are integral to an
evolutionary account of conscious visual processing and creative problem
solving in humans.
In this chapter, I built upon work of the previous chapters and showed
how the processes associated with vision in mammals comprise a hierarchically
organized system exhibiting the same kinds of properties of information
exchange, selectivity, and integration found in organisms in general.
I distinguished four levels of visual processing in animals: a noncognitive
visual processing, two cognitive/psychological forms of visual processing,
and a conscious cognitive visual processing that occurs at the highest level
of the visual hierarchy. Since in this project I am concerned mostly with
the progression from cognitive visual processing to conscious cognitive
visual processing, the relationship of these processes to one another, and,
ultimately, how conscious cognitive visual processing evolved from cognitive
visual processing, I showed that the visual systems of mammals function
so as to produce visual cognition.
Visual cognition is the phenomenal representation of some object in the
animal’s visual fi eld that is the result of the integration of modular visual
information received from that object in association with iconic memory,
attention, and the synchronous fi ring of neurons in the areas of the brain
relevant to the processing of the visual percept. Special attention was paid
to visual modularity, which refers to the fact that the visual system is made
up of distinctly functioning and interacting modules or areas having
evolved to respond to certain features of an object in typical environments,
and visual integration, which refers to a neurobiological process or set of
processes that bind together the relevant information gleaned from visual
modules/areas into a coherent cognitive representation of some object,
enabling an animal to negotiate typical environments. In the next
chapter—which is really the heart of the book—I trace the evolution of
the visual system from organisms that developed a light/dark sensitivity
area to humans who are capable of the complex activities involved in scenario
visualization, one form of conscious cognitive visual processing.