2 The Amazing Success of Statistical Prediction Rules
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94
Judgment problems great and small are an essential part of everyday life.
What menu items will I most enjoy eating? Is this book worth reading?
Is the boss in a good mood? Will the bungee cord snap? These and other
common judgment problems share a similar structure: On the basis of
certain cues, we make judgments about some target property. I doubt the
integrity of the bungee cord (target property) on the basis of the fact that
it looks frayed and the assistants look disheveled and hungover (cues).
How we make and how we ought to make such evidence-based judgments
are interesting issues in their own right. But they are particularly pressing
because such predictions often play a central role in decisions and actions.
Because I don’t trust the cord, I don’t bungee jump off the bridge.
Making accurate judgments is important for our health and happiness,
but also for the just and effective operation of many of our social
institutions. Judgments about whether someone will become violent can
determine whether that person loses their freedom by being involuntarily
committed to a psychiatric institution. Predictions about whether a prisoner
if set free will commit violence and mayhem can determine whether
he is or is not paroled. Judgments about a student’s academic abilities play
a role in determining the quality of medical school or law school she goes
to, or even whether she gets to study law or medicine at all. Judgments
about a person’s future financial situation can determine whether they
receive loans to make large purchases; such judgments can also determine
whether they receive the most attractive loans available. And most
everyone who has ever held a job has had others pass judgments about
their trustworthiness, intelligence, punctuality, and industriousness.
It is hard to overestimate the practical significance of these sorts of
social judgments. Using reasoning strategies that lead to unreliable judgments
about such matters can have devastating consequences. Unnecessarily
unreliable judgments can lead to decisions that waste untold resources, that
unjustly deprive innocent people of their freedom, or that lead to preventable
increases in rape, assault, and murder. There is a difference between
cancer and horseshoes, between prison and a good shave. For many reasoning
problems, ‘‘close enough’’ isn’t good enough. Only the best reasoning
strategies available to us will do. Ameliorative Psychology is designed
to identify such strategies, and the primary tasks of a useful epistemology
are to articulate what makes a reasoning strategy a good one and to carry
that message abroad so that improvements can be implemented. This
chapter is the prologue to that epistemological message.
Who could possibly deny that those charged with making high-stakes
decisions should reason especially carefully about them? Consider, for example,
predictions about violent recidivism made by parole boards. Who
could deny that members of parole boards should scrupulously gather as
much relevant evidence as they can, carefully weigh the different lines of
evidence, and on this basis come to a judgment that is best supported by
the entirety of the evidence? Actually, we deny this. We contend that
it would often be much better if experts, when making high-stakes judgments,
ignored most of the evidence, did not try to weigh that evidence,
and didn’t try to make a judgment based on their long experience. Sometimes,
it would be better for the experts to hand their caseload over to a
simple formula that a smart 8-year-old could solve and then submit to the
child’s will. This is what Ameliorative Psychology counsels. (Of course,
discovering such a formula takes some expertise.)
For the past half century or so, psychologists and statisticians have
shown that people who have great experience and training at making
certain sorts of prediction are often less reliable than (often very simple)
Statistical Prediction Rules (SPRs). This is very good news, especially for
those of us who like to do hard work without having to work hard. Of
course, the philosophical literature is full of fantastic examples in which
some simple reasoning strategy that no reasonable person would accept
turns out to be perfectly reliable (e.g., ‘‘believe all Swami Beauregard’s
predictions’’). But we are not engaged here in Freak Show Philosophy.
Many SPRs are robustly successful in a wide range of real-life reasoning
problems—including some very high-stakes ones. Further, the success of
The Amazing Success of Statistical Prediction Rules 25
some SPRs seems utterly miraculous. (In fact, when we introduced one of
the more shocking SPR results described below to a well-known philosopher
of psychology who is generally sympathetic to our view, he simply
didn’t believe it.) But there are general reasons why certain kinds of SPRs
are successful. We turn now to describing their success. Later, we’ll try to
explain it.
Judgment problems great and small are an essential part of everyday life.
What menu items will I most enjoy eating? Is this book worth reading?
Is the boss in a good mood? Will the bungee cord snap? These and other
common judgment problems share a similar structure: On the basis of
certain cues, we make judgments about some target property. I doubt the
integrity of the bungee cord (target property) on the basis of the fact that
it looks frayed and the assistants look disheveled and hungover (cues).
How we make and how we ought to make such evidence-based judgments
are interesting issues in their own right. But they are particularly pressing
because such predictions often play a central role in decisions and actions.
Because I don’t trust the cord, I don’t bungee jump off the bridge.
Making accurate judgments is important for our health and happiness,
but also for the just and effective operation of many of our social
institutions. Judgments about whether someone will become violent can
determine whether that person loses their freedom by being involuntarily
committed to a psychiatric institution. Predictions about whether a prisoner
if set free will commit violence and mayhem can determine whether
he is or is not paroled. Judgments about a student’s academic abilities play
a role in determining the quality of medical school or law school she goes
to, or even whether she gets to study law or medicine at all. Judgments
about a person’s future financial situation can determine whether they
receive loans to make large purchases; such judgments can also determine
whether they receive the most attractive loans available. And most
everyone who has ever held a job has had others pass judgments about
their trustworthiness, intelligence, punctuality, and industriousness.
It is hard to overestimate the practical significance of these sorts of
social judgments. Using reasoning strategies that lead to unreliable judgments
about such matters can have devastating consequences. Unnecessarily
unreliable judgments can lead to decisions that waste untold resources, that
unjustly deprive innocent people of their freedom, or that lead to preventable
increases in rape, assault, and murder. There is a difference between
cancer and horseshoes, between prison and a good shave. For many reasoning
problems, ‘‘close enough’’ isn’t good enough. Only the best reasoning
strategies available to us will do. Ameliorative Psychology is designed
to identify such strategies, and the primary tasks of a useful epistemology
are to articulate what makes a reasoning strategy a good one and to carry
that message abroad so that improvements can be implemented. This
chapter is the prologue to that epistemological message.
Who could possibly deny that those charged with making high-stakes
decisions should reason especially carefully about them? Consider, for example,
predictions about violent recidivism made by parole boards. Who
could deny that members of parole boards should scrupulously gather as
much relevant evidence as they can, carefully weigh the different lines of
evidence, and on this basis come to a judgment that is best supported by
the entirety of the evidence? Actually, we deny this. We contend that
it would often be much better if experts, when making high-stakes judgments,
ignored most of the evidence, did not try to weigh that evidence,
and didn’t try to make a judgment based on their long experience. Sometimes,
it would be better for the experts to hand their caseload over to a
simple formula that a smart 8-year-old could solve and then submit to the
child’s will. This is what Ameliorative Psychology counsels. (Of course,
discovering such a formula takes some expertise.)
For the past half century or so, psychologists and statisticians have
shown that people who have great experience and training at making
certain sorts of prediction are often less reliable than (often very simple)
Statistical Prediction Rules (SPRs). This is very good news, especially for
those of us who like to do hard work without having to work hard. Of
course, the philosophical literature is full of fantastic examples in which
some simple reasoning strategy that no reasonable person would accept
turns out to be perfectly reliable (e.g., ‘‘believe all Swami Beauregard’s
predictions’’). But we are not engaged here in Freak Show Philosophy.
Many SPRs are robustly successful in a wide range of real-life reasoning
problems—including some very high-stakes ones. Further, the success of
The Amazing Success of Statistical Prediction Rules 25
some SPRs seems utterly miraculous. (In fact, when we introduced one of
the more shocking SPR results described below to a well-known philosopher
of psychology who is generally sympathetic to our view, he simply
didn’t believe it.) But there are general reasons why certain kinds of SPRs
are successful. We turn now to describing their success. Later, we’ll try to
explain it.