5. Conclusion
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94
According to Strategic Reliabilism, the quality of a reasoning strategy is a
function of its expected costs and benefits as well as those of its competitors.
But which of two reasoning strategies has a better cost-benefit ratio for a
particular reasoner is an empirical question. From the perspective of
Strategic Reliabilism, when one assesses positively someone’s reasoning, he
must present evidence that these individuals have availed themselves of the
best strategies of which they are cognitively capable. Of course, conceptual
reject-the-norm arguments don’t do this. They conclude that proponents
of the HB program are mistaken in their negative evaluations of their
subjects’ reasoning (or of the reasoning that leads to the modal answer
given by subjects). But these arguments do not appeal to the contingent,
empirical factors that are relevant to the proper assessment of the quality
of a reasoning strategy. Therefore, conceptual reject-the-norm arguments
are incapable of making the case that our actual reasoning strategies are
epistemically excellent.
It’s useful to note that any argument—whether purely conceptual or
not—that aims to show that our actual reasoning strategies are epistemically
excellent is doomed. There are two reasons for this. First, the
conclusion is known to be false. Ameliorative Psychology offers us a
number of reasoning strategies that are superior to the ones most of us
actually use. Second, suppose the conclusion weren’t known to be false.
Suppose that as far as we know, our actual reasoning strategies are the best
available. It would still be extraordinarily unlikely that there aren’t better strategies out there, just waiting to be discovered. So an argument can’t be
sound if it purports to show that when it comes to our reasoning we don’t
need no stinkin’ badgerers.
There is a way for reject-the-norm arguments to avoid these objections.
They can change the subject. They can employ or define an epistemic
notion such that our actual reasoning strategies are unbeatable
according to that notion. We suspect that something like this is going on
with the conceptual reject-the-norm arguments of Gigerenzer and Cohen.
But as long as these arguments don’t touch upon the quality of subjects’
reasoning—the focus of Strategic Reliabilism—there is no reason for proponents
of the HB program to worry. They can grant that a reject-thenorm
argument shows that there is some Pickwickian sense in which
subjects are ‘‘rational’’ or not making an ‘‘error,’’ and then point out that
on this view, one can be ‘‘rational’’ and ‘‘error-free’’ while regularly engaging
in atrocious reasoning, reasoning that (among other things) predictably
leads to massively suboptimal outcomes. There is, admittedly, an
esthetic drawback to taking this line against reject-the-norm arguments: It
requires the use of an annoying number of scare quotes. The substantive
lesson to draw, however, is that unbridled, a priori optimism about our
cognitive capacities inevitably leads to normative evaluations that either
are meant to be prescriptive and are in practice absurd or are empty of
prescriptive force.
We have argued that two conceptual reject-the-norm arguments fail;
and we have also argued that any conceptual reject-the-norm argument
must fail. It doesn’t follow, however, that every normative assessment
made by proponents of the HB program is correct. When it comes to
assessing the quality of a particular reasoning strategy, there is no substitute
for attending to the costs and benefits of that strategy and its
competitors. What does Strategic Reliabilism say about the reasoning
strategies that proponents of the HB program claim result in biases (e.g.,
base rate neglect)? We turn to this issue in the next chapter.
According to Strategic Reliabilism, the quality of a reasoning strategy is a
function of its expected costs and benefits as well as those of its competitors.
But which of two reasoning strategies has a better cost-benefit ratio for a
particular reasoner is an empirical question. From the perspective of
Strategic Reliabilism, when one assesses positively someone’s reasoning, he
must present evidence that these individuals have availed themselves of the
best strategies of which they are cognitively capable. Of course, conceptual
reject-the-norm arguments don’t do this. They conclude that proponents
of the HB program are mistaken in their negative evaluations of their
subjects’ reasoning (or of the reasoning that leads to the modal answer
given by subjects). But these arguments do not appeal to the contingent,
empirical factors that are relevant to the proper assessment of the quality
of a reasoning strategy. Therefore, conceptual reject-the-norm arguments
are incapable of making the case that our actual reasoning strategies are
epistemically excellent.
It’s useful to note that any argument—whether purely conceptual or
not—that aims to show that our actual reasoning strategies are epistemically
excellent is doomed. There are two reasons for this. First, the
conclusion is known to be false. Ameliorative Psychology offers us a
number of reasoning strategies that are superior to the ones most of us
actually use. Second, suppose the conclusion weren’t known to be false.
Suppose that as far as we know, our actual reasoning strategies are the best
available. It would still be extraordinarily unlikely that there aren’t better strategies out there, just waiting to be discovered. So an argument can’t be
sound if it purports to show that when it comes to our reasoning we don’t
need no stinkin’ badgerers.
There is a way for reject-the-norm arguments to avoid these objections.
They can change the subject. They can employ or define an epistemic
notion such that our actual reasoning strategies are unbeatable
according to that notion. We suspect that something like this is going on
with the conceptual reject-the-norm arguments of Gigerenzer and Cohen.
But as long as these arguments don’t touch upon the quality of subjects’
reasoning—the focus of Strategic Reliabilism—there is no reason for proponents
of the HB program to worry. They can grant that a reject-thenorm
argument shows that there is some Pickwickian sense in which
subjects are ‘‘rational’’ or not making an ‘‘error,’’ and then point out that
on this view, one can be ‘‘rational’’ and ‘‘error-free’’ while regularly engaging
in atrocious reasoning, reasoning that (among other things) predictably
leads to massively suboptimal outcomes. There is, admittedly, an
esthetic drawback to taking this line against reject-the-norm arguments: It
requires the use of an annoying number of scare quotes. The substantive
lesson to draw, however, is that unbridled, a priori optimism about our
cognitive capacities inevitably leads to normative evaluations that either
are meant to be prescriptive and are in practice absurd or are empty of
prescriptive force.
We have argued that two conceptual reject-the-norm arguments fail;
and we have also argued that any conceptual reject-the-norm argument
must fail. It doesn’t follow, however, that every normative assessment
made by proponents of the HB program is correct. When it comes to
assessing the quality of a particular reasoning strategy, there is no substitute
for attending to the costs and benefits of that strategy and its
competitors. What does Strategic Reliabilism say about the reasoning
strategies that proponents of the HB program claim result in biases (e.g.,
base rate neglect)? We turn to this issue in the next chapter.