2. Standard Analytic Epistemology: Throwing stones in glass houses
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94
The descriptive core of SAE is a theory that captures the considered epistemic
judgments of philosophers. Some proponents of SAE believe that
those judgments are best captured by a coherentist theory, others believe
that they are best captured by a foundationalist theory, others believe that
they are best captured by a reliabilist theory, etc. The obvious challenge
for these theories is: How are they to extract normative consequences from
a descriptive theory? While we intend to argue that the prospects for the
theories of SAE overcoming the naturalist challenge are not good, we do
not contend that the theories of SAE cannot overcome it. We recognize
that there may be a way we have not properly identified for proponents of
SAE to respond successfully to the naturalist challenge. However, proponents
of SAE have wielded arguments against naturalistic epistemology
The Troubles with Standard Analytic Epistemology 109
that can be readily adapted to show that their own preferred theories
cannot be normative. We emphasize again that we do not endorse these
arguments. Our point here is that proponents of SAE have for too long
been throwing stones at naturalistic epistemology from glass houses.
Michael Williams argues that the normative nature of epistemology
makes it impossible to fully ‘‘naturalize’’ it:
[Epistemic claims] depend on meeting certain norms or standards which
define, not what you do do, but what you must or ought to do. To characterize
someone’s claim as expressing or not expressing knowledge is to pass
judgment on it. Epistemic judgments are thus a particular kind of valuejudgment.
It is far from obvious that investigations with such a strongly
normative component can be fully ‘naturalized.’ (Williams 2001, 11)
Williams’s argument applies equally to the theories of SAE: As we have
just argued, when it comes to epistemic judgments, the theories of SAE
define what we ‘‘do do’’ not what we ‘‘must or ought to do.’’ They don’t tell
us how to reason or believe; they merely tell us how we do make epistemic
judgments (and by ‘‘we,’’ we mean the tiny fraction of the world’s population
who has studied SAE).
According to Richard Feldman, psychology and philosophy must at
best co-exist because psychology can’t ask or answer the relevant normative
questions:
The original epistemological questions seem to be perfectly good questions,
well worthy of our attention. It is difficult to see, then, why the availability
of this other field of study [psychology], concerning how we reason, is a
suitable replacement for the evaluative questions that are at the heart of
epistemology. (Feldman 2003, 168)
Feldman’s point can be made against the theories of SAE: ‘‘It is difficult to
see, then, why the availability of this other field of study’’ (namely, SAE,
which aims to describe how some people make evaluative judgments) ‘‘is a
suitable replacement for the evaluative questions that are at the heart of
epistemology.’’ The proponent of SAE is replacing normative questions
about how to evaluate reason and belief with descriptive questions about
how proponents of SAE evaluate reason and belief. To suppose that
answers to the descriptive questions are also answers to the normative
questions is to take a big leap.
Lawrence BonJour argues that any epistemology subsumed by psychology
does not have the resources to evaluate, positively or negatively, beliefs about alleged occult phenomena of various sorts, such as astrological
or phrenological beliefs. For just as naturalized epistemology can say nothing
positive about the justification of science or common sense, and is thus
impotent in the face of skepticism, so also it can say nothing distinctively
negative about the justification of these less reputable sorts of belief.
(BonJour 2002, 244)
We can once again turn the tables on the proponent of SAE. A theory that
accurately describes how a certain group of people make certain evaluative
judgments ‘‘can say nothing positive about the justification of science or
common sense, and is thus impotent in the face of skepticism, so also it
can say nothing distinctively negative about the justification of ’’ occult,
astrological, or phrenological beliefs. Of course, such a theory might tell us
how some people evaluate those beliefs. But that’s not the same as actually
evaluating those beliefs.
In a similar vein, Alvin Plantinga notes that Quinean naturalism in
epistemology cannot be normative:
[T]he most extreme version of naturalism in epistemology eschews normativity
altogether, seeking to replace traditional epistemology (with its concern
with justification, rationality, reasonability, and their normative colleagues)
by descriptive psychology; this seems to be Quine’s suggestion. [fn deleted]
(Plantinga 1993, 45)
By now, we’re confident our argumentative strategy is wearing thin, but
here it is anyway: SAE ‘‘eschews normativity altogether, seeking to replace
traditional epistemology (with its concern with justification, rationality, reasonability,
and their normative colleagues) by descriptive psychology’’—
a psychology that describes how certain people make certain sorts of
judgments.
Proponents of SAE have argued for decades that radically naturalistic
theories of epistemology cannot succeed because they cannot be normative.
Our aim has been to turn the tables on proponents of SAE. We distance
ourselves from these arguments. Merely pointing out that a theory faces the
problem of bridging the is-ought divide does not by itself damn that theory.
And this is a good thing for proponents of SAE. We all start our normative
musings with psychology. Proponents of SAE start by describing a certain
group’s epistemological judgments, and we start with what we have called
Ameliorative Psychology. (We argue that the former is probably very bad
psychology, but that is not essential to the case we’re building here.) When
it comes to bridging the is-ought gap, everybody has work to do.
The Troubles with Standard Analytic Epistemology 111
The descriptive core of SAE is a theory that captures the considered epistemic
judgments of philosophers. Some proponents of SAE believe that
those judgments are best captured by a coherentist theory, others believe
that they are best captured by a foundationalist theory, others believe that
they are best captured by a reliabilist theory, etc. The obvious challenge
for these theories is: How are they to extract normative consequences from
a descriptive theory? While we intend to argue that the prospects for the
theories of SAE overcoming the naturalist challenge are not good, we do
not contend that the theories of SAE cannot overcome it. We recognize
that there may be a way we have not properly identified for proponents of
SAE to respond successfully to the naturalist challenge. However, proponents
of SAE have wielded arguments against naturalistic epistemology
The Troubles with Standard Analytic Epistemology 109
that can be readily adapted to show that their own preferred theories
cannot be normative. We emphasize again that we do not endorse these
arguments. Our point here is that proponents of SAE have for too long
been throwing stones at naturalistic epistemology from glass houses.
Michael Williams argues that the normative nature of epistemology
makes it impossible to fully ‘‘naturalize’’ it:
[Epistemic claims] depend on meeting certain norms or standards which
define, not what you do do, but what you must or ought to do. To characterize
someone’s claim as expressing or not expressing knowledge is to pass
judgment on it. Epistemic judgments are thus a particular kind of valuejudgment.
It is far from obvious that investigations with such a strongly
normative component can be fully ‘naturalized.’ (Williams 2001, 11)
Williams’s argument applies equally to the theories of SAE: As we have
just argued, when it comes to epistemic judgments, the theories of SAE
define what we ‘‘do do’’ not what we ‘‘must or ought to do.’’ They don’t tell
us how to reason or believe; they merely tell us how we do make epistemic
judgments (and by ‘‘we,’’ we mean the tiny fraction of the world’s population
who has studied SAE).
According to Richard Feldman, psychology and philosophy must at
best co-exist because psychology can’t ask or answer the relevant normative
questions:
The original epistemological questions seem to be perfectly good questions,
well worthy of our attention. It is difficult to see, then, why the availability
of this other field of study [psychology], concerning how we reason, is a
suitable replacement for the evaluative questions that are at the heart of
epistemology. (Feldman 2003, 168)
Feldman’s point can be made against the theories of SAE: ‘‘It is difficult to
see, then, why the availability of this other field of study’’ (namely, SAE,
which aims to describe how some people make evaluative judgments) ‘‘is a
suitable replacement for the evaluative questions that are at the heart of
epistemology.’’ The proponent of SAE is replacing normative questions
about how to evaluate reason and belief with descriptive questions about
how proponents of SAE evaluate reason and belief. To suppose that
answers to the descriptive questions are also answers to the normative
questions is to take a big leap.
Lawrence BonJour argues that any epistemology subsumed by psychology
does not have the resources to evaluate, positively or negatively, beliefs about alleged occult phenomena of various sorts, such as astrological
or phrenological beliefs. For just as naturalized epistemology can say nothing
positive about the justification of science or common sense, and is thus
impotent in the face of skepticism, so also it can say nothing distinctively
negative about the justification of these less reputable sorts of belief.
(BonJour 2002, 244)
We can once again turn the tables on the proponent of SAE. A theory that
accurately describes how a certain group of people make certain evaluative
judgments ‘‘can say nothing positive about the justification of science or
common sense, and is thus impotent in the face of skepticism, so also it
can say nothing distinctively negative about the justification of ’’ occult,
astrological, or phrenological beliefs. Of course, such a theory might tell us
how some people evaluate those beliefs. But that’s not the same as actually
evaluating those beliefs.
In a similar vein, Alvin Plantinga notes that Quinean naturalism in
epistemology cannot be normative:
[T]he most extreme version of naturalism in epistemology eschews normativity
altogether, seeking to replace traditional epistemology (with its concern
with justification, rationality, reasonability, and their normative colleagues)
by descriptive psychology; this seems to be Quine’s suggestion. [fn deleted]
(Plantinga 1993, 45)
By now, we’re confident our argumentative strategy is wearing thin, but
here it is anyway: SAE ‘‘eschews normativity altogether, seeking to replace
traditional epistemology (with its concern with justification, rationality, reasonability,
and their normative colleagues) by descriptive psychology’’—
a psychology that describes how certain people make certain sorts of
judgments.
Proponents of SAE have argued for decades that radically naturalistic
theories of epistemology cannot succeed because they cannot be normative.
Our aim has been to turn the tables on proponents of SAE. We distance
ourselves from these arguments. Merely pointing out that a theory faces the
problem of bridging the is-ought divide does not by itself damn that theory.
And this is a good thing for proponents of SAE. We all start our normative
musings with psychology. Proponents of SAE start by describing a certain
group’s epistemological judgments, and we start with what we have called
Ameliorative Psychology. (We argue that the former is probably very bad
psychology, but that is not essential to the case we’re building here.) When
it comes to bridging the is-ought gap, everybody has work to do.
The Troubles with Standard Analytic Epistemology 111