1.5. SPRs vs. Humans: An unfair test?
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94
Before we turn to an explanation for the success of SPRs, we should
consider a common objection against the SPR findings described above.
The objection proceeds as follows: ‘‘The real reason human experts do
worse than SPRs is that they are restricted to the sort of objective information
that can be plugged into a formula. So of course this tilts the
playing field in favor of the formula. People can base their predictions on
evidence that can’t be quantified and put in a formula. By denying experts
this kind of evidence, the above tests aren’t fair. Indeed, we can be confident
that human experts will defeat SPRs when they can use a wider
range of real world, qualitative evidence.’’
There are three points to make against this argument. First, this argument
offers no actual evidence that might justify the belief that human
experts are handicapped by being unable to use qualitative evidence in the
above examples. The argument offers only a speculation. Second, it is
possible to quantitatively code virtually any kind of evidence. For example,
consider an SPR that predicts the length of hospitalization for schizophrenic
and manic-depressive patients (Dunham and Meltzer 1946). This
SPR employs a rating of the patients’ insight into their condition. Prima
facie, this is a subjective, nonquantitative variable because it relies on a
clinician’s diagnosis of a patient’s mental state. Yet clinicians are able to
quantitatively code their diagnoses of the patient’s insight into his or her
condition. The clinician’s quantitatively coded diagnosis is then used by
the SPR to make more accurate predictions than the clinician. Third, the
The Amazing Success of Statistical Prediction Rules 31
speculation that humans armed with ‘‘extra’’ qualitative evidence can
outperform SPRs has been tested and has failed repeatedly. One example
of this failure is known as the interview effect : Unstructured interviews
degrade human reliability (Bloom and Brundage 1947, DeVaul et al. 1957,
Oskamp 1965, Milstein et al. 1981). When gatekeepers (e.g., hiring and
admissions officers, parole boards, etc.) make judgments about candidates
on the basis of a dossier and an unstructured interview, their judgments
come out worse than judgments based simply on the dossier (without the
unstructured interview). So when human experts and SPRs are given the
same evidence, and then humans get more information in the form of
unstructured interviews, clinical prediction is still less reliable than SPRs.
In fact, as would be expected given the interview effect, giving humans the
‘‘extra’’ qualitative evidence actually makes it easier for SPRs to defeat the
predictions of expert humans. To be fair, however, there are cases in which
experts can defeat SPRs. We will discuss these exceptions below.
Before we turn to an explanation for the success of SPRs, we should
consider a common objection against the SPR findings described above.
The objection proceeds as follows: ‘‘The real reason human experts do
worse than SPRs is that they are restricted to the sort of objective information
that can be plugged into a formula. So of course this tilts the
playing field in favor of the formula. People can base their predictions on
evidence that can’t be quantified and put in a formula. By denying experts
this kind of evidence, the above tests aren’t fair. Indeed, we can be confident
that human experts will defeat SPRs when they can use a wider
range of real world, qualitative evidence.’’
There are three points to make against this argument. First, this argument
offers no actual evidence that might justify the belief that human
experts are handicapped by being unable to use qualitative evidence in the
above examples. The argument offers only a speculation. Second, it is
possible to quantitatively code virtually any kind of evidence. For example,
consider an SPR that predicts the length of hospitalization for schizophrenic
and manic-depressive patients (Dunham and Meltzer 1946). This
SPR employs a rating of the patients’ insight into their condition. Prima
facie, this is a subjective, nonquantitative variable because it relies on a
clinician’s diagnosis of a patient’s mental state. Yet clinicians are able to
quantitatively code their diagnoses of the patient’s insight into his or her
condition. The clinician’s quantitatively coded diagnosis is then used by
the SPR to make more accurate predictions than the clinician. Third, the
The Amazing Success of Statistical Prediction Rules 31
speculation that humans armed with ‘‘extra’’ qualitative evidence can
outperform SPRs has been tested and has failed repeatedly. One example
of this failure is known as the interview effect : Unstructured interviews
degrade human reliability (Bloom and Brundage 1947, DeVaul et al. 1957,
Oskamp 1965, Milstein et al. 1981). When gatekeepers (e.g., hiring and
admissions officers, parole boards, etc.) make judgments about candidates
on the basis of a dossier and an unstructured interview, their judgments
come out worse than judgments based simply on the dossier (without the
unstructured interview). So when human experts and SPRs are given the
same evidence, and then humans get more information in the form of
unstructured interviews, clinical prediction is still less reliable than SPRs.
In fact, as would be expected given the interview effect, giving humans the
‘‘extra’’ qualitative evidence actually makes it easier for SPRs to defeat the
predictions of expert humans. To be fair, however, there are cases in which
experts can defeat SPRs. We will discuss these exceptions below.