1. The virtues of flawed cost-benefit analyses
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94
In most general terms, cost-benefit analysis is a reasoning strategy that
permits us to estimate the desirability of various tradeoffs available to us.
The most familiar form of cost-benefit analysis places a dollar value on the
costs and benefits of each available option. This procedure is supposed to
allow any person or institutional body to identify the option that promises
the greatest total benefit. For example, in deciding whether to expand a
successful company’s production capacity, cost-benefit analysis would
have us compare the expected profits to be gained by expansion with current
expected profits. The objection to this standard approach to costbenefit
analysis is as obvious as it is serious: It relies on money as its only
measure of value. A deeper and more interesting objection is that there is no ‘‘neutral’’ measure of value for comparing very distinct sorts of goods.
Values are incommensurable. We cannot reduce all value to money, and
there is no realistic way to assign commensurable units of value to freedom,
happiness, personal security, or a (relatively) pristine Grand Canyon.
These objections show that it is not possible to measure the net benefits
(or costs) of different options against each other. We are sympathetic to
many of these objections to cost-benefit analysis (Anderson 1993, Sen
2000). Still, we would argue that flawed cost-benefit analyses can be very
useful and important.
A cost-benefit approach to a problem can be very useful even if it is
plagued by theoretical problems. It permits us to estimate the desirability
of various tradeoffs available to us, no matter what kind of value we place
on them. In doing so, it can be useful for helping us to avoid making decisions
that do not reflect our own values. Explicitly engaging in costbenefit
analysis, even a flawed analysis, allows us to slow down, cool off,
compare the value we assign to certain outcomes, and determine what
strategies we ought to adopt to achieve them. The primary virtue of costbenefit
analyses, even when flawed, is that they can help us to set and adjust
our priorities in ways that better reflect our values.
We can distinguish between two kinds of flawed but useful costbenefit
approaches to problems, incomplete cost-benefit analyses and
unreduced cost-benefit analyses. An incomplete cost-benefit analysis focuses
on only a subset of the values at stake in a decision. For example,
cost-benefit analyses that focus only on money as a unit of value are typically
incomplete. An unreduced cost-benefit analysis focuses on a realistic
set of values that are at stake in making a decision, but it does not attempt
to reduce those values to standard units of costs and benefits. To make our
case that these sorts of flawed cost-benefit analyses can be useful in helping
us to set and reset our priorities, let’s consider some examples.
Many companies offer their employees (sometimes quite generous)
retirement packages; but a surprising percentage of people don’t participate
in them. Many of these people would benefit from an unreduced
cost-benefit analysis of the choice of whether to invest in such a retirement
account. Such an analysis would not even attempt to reduce all the costs
and benefits of the options to a single value (like current dollars). Consider
the benefits of current spending (on, say, a larger mortgage on a larger
home) and the potential future costs of inadequate retirement funds
(lower standard of living, dependence on kin or children). While these
costs and benefits cannot be reduced to a single unit of value, we suspect
that if people thought clearly and coolly about the various options, they might be surprised to find that they would explicitly reject the values
implicit in their actual decisions.
Let’s consider an example of some radically incomplete cost-benefit
analyses that as a historical matter affected public-policy decision making
for the better: attempts to put a monetary value on human lives. In late
seventeenth-century Britain, William Petty ‘‘argued in favor of measures
to ward off or mitigate the effects of the plague on the grounds that by
spending a few thousand pounds the king might protect an investment
many times greater in the lives of his subjects’’ (Porter 1994, 214–15). By
the early part of the twentieth century, professional actuaries working for
insurance companies had taken over the business of placing monetary
values on human lives. In The Money Value of a Man (1930), Louis Dublin
and Alfred Lotka attached a dollar figure to human lives, basing their calculations
on the expected net present value of future earnings. Their analyses
explicitly recognized that they could not put a monetary figure on the
‘‘intangibles of life’’ but instead viewed humans (and in particular, men)
as just so much equipment:
Man has much in common with the industrial aids, machines, manufacturing
plants, and so forth, of which he makes use to conduct the business of
life. Like them he has a ‘‘cost of installation,’’ . . . running expenses, interest
on capital invested, and the loss of a certain proportion of children that do
not live to attain adult age, just as in manufacturing processes allowance
must be made for losses by ‘‘spoilage’’ of material that never reaches the
‘‘finished’’ stage. (1930, 44, quoted in Porter 1994, 216)
This kind of cost-benefit analysis inevitably strikes us as appallingly crass.
But besides figuring out how much life insurance to sell people, these
analyses were also typically put to political use:
None of these calculations . . . was part of a formal assessment of costs and
benefits. They were intended not to guide policy in detail, but to soften
slightly those famously hardheaded administrators and businessmen who
were reluctant to invest dollars, pounds, and francs in what would come to
be known as human capital. The sentimental and self-regarding emotions
could be left out because the numbers were already large enough to draw
attention, and that was their only real purpose . . . [W]hile these formulas
may not have been very accurate, they were surprisingly precise. . . . This was
almost indispensable if calculation was to figure significantly in decisions
vulnerable to public criticism. (Porter, 217)
The cost-benefit analyses suggested that the preventable suffering and
death of poor laborers was bad for business. We might view it as wearily predictable that it was profit that spurred captains of industry to support
the public works projects that prevented the deaths of many of our
ancestors. And one would be right to object that the cost-benefit approach
is no guarantor of a positive outcome. The morally right policies were
implemented because of contingent facts about the profit structure of local
industrial economies rather than because of the intrinsic moral worth of
human laborers. But while we may be appalled that ethical considerations
did not move the captains of industry quicker, we can be glad that costbenefit
considerations kept them from moving slower still.
The cost-benefit analyses that convinced ‘‘hardheaded administrators
and businessmen’’ that they were underestimating the monetary value of
their ‘‘human capital’’ was radically incomplete. It focused only on economic
considerations. But the right course of action was so clearly right
that any number of different cost-benefit analyses—even those informed
by values we might find crass or repugnant—delivered the correct result.
When the world is obliging in this way, incomplete cost-benefit analyses
can lead us to effectively revise our priorities and actions.
Flawed cost-benefit analyses are useful because they dramatize the
opportunity costs of a favored course of action. For example, after airplane
crashes, there are often voices pressing for greater air safety regulations.
While such regulations might make air travel safer, they might also have the
effect of making travel more dangerous. That’s because the increased regulations
may increase the price of flying and so lead more people to drive—
which is a more dangerous form of transportation (Sunstein 2000, 1073).
(Further, given its relative safety, making air travel a tiny bit safer may well
be less cost effective than, say, repaving the Pennsylvania Turnpike.) Now it
may be that we are willing to accept a greater number of total traffic injuries
and fatalities in exchange for slightly safer (and more expensive) air travel.
But by engaging in cost-benefit analysis—even one that only considers the
rather crass value of money spent per death prevented—we can recognize
that the decision to make air travel slightly safer has this effect. Even a
flawed cost-benefit analysis can help us to expose the aims and values
implicit in our decisions; and this exposure can lead us to change, challenge,
or clarify our values and priorities. Perhaps we so dread the terrifying
nature of airplane deaths that we are willing to accept an increased probability
of injury or death for a decreased probability of a terror-filled death.
But only by exposing this value underlying our decision can we even begin
to question it. Even a flawed cost-benefit analysis can help us set priorities
and effectively marshal our scarce resources so as to improve our decision
making (Sunstein 2000).
As citizens of a democracy, we have an interest in how members of
governmental safety boards (e.g., OSHA, EPA, etc.) decide how to allocate
scarce resources to improve occupational and other federal safety standards.
In making such decisions, it is useful to know that (according to the
Consumer Product Safety Commission) banning unvented space heaters
is among the cheapest ways to save lives, costing $100,000 per prevented
death. Limiting exposure to asbestos in the workplace is considerably
more expensive, at 8.3 million dollars per prevented death (OSHA). And
the cost of listing wood-preserving chemicals as hazardous waste is estimated
by the EPA to be 5.7 trillion dollars per prevented death (Sunstein,
2000). By being clear about what measures are likely to save the greatest
number of people (or minimize the number of people getting sick), we can
better make decisions that accurately reflect our values.
In most general terms, cost-benefit analysis is a reasoning strategy that
permits us to estimate the desirability of various tradeoffs available to us.
The most familiar form of cost-benefit analysis places a dollar value on the
costs and benefits of each available option. This procedure is supposed to
allow any person or institutional body to identify the option that promises
the greatest total benefit. For example, in deciding whether to expand a
successful company’s production capacity, cost-benefit analysis would
have us compare the expected profits to be gained by expansion with current
expected profits. The objection to this standard approach to costbenefit
analysis is as obvious as it is serious: It relies on money as its only
measure of value. A deeper and more interesting objection is that there is no ‘‘neutral’’ measure of value for comparing very distinct sorts of goods.
Values are incommensurable. We cannot reduce all value to money, and
there is no realistic way to assign commensurable units of value to freedom,
happiness, personal security, or a (relatively) pristine Grand Canyon.
These objections show that it is not possible to measure the net benefits
(or costs) of different options against each other. We are sympathetic to
many of these objections to cost-benefit analysis (Anderson 1993, Sen
2000). Still, we would argue that flawed cost-benefit analyses can be very
useful and important.
A cost-benefit approach to a problem can be very useful even if it is
plagued by theoretical problems. It permits us to estimate the desirability
of various tradeoffs available to us, no matter what kind of value we place
on them. In doing so, it can be useful for helping us to avoid making decisions
that do not reflect our own values. Explicitly engaging in costbenefit
analysis, even a flawed analysis, allows us to slow down, cool off,
compare the value we assign to certain outcomes, and determine what
strategies we ought to adopt to achieve them. The primary virtue of costbenefit
analyses, even when flawed, is that they can help us to set and adjust
our priorities in ways that better reflect our values.
We can distinguish between two kinds of flawed but useful costbenefit
approaches to problems, incomplete cost-benefit analyses and
unreduced cost-benefit analyses. An incomplete cost-benefit analysis focuses
on only a subset of the values at stake in a decision. For example,
cost-benefit analyses that focus only on money as a unit of value are typically
incomplete. An unreduced cost-benefit analysis focuses on a realistic
set of values that are at stake in making a decision, but it does not attempt
to reduce those values to standard units of costs and benefits. To make our
case that these sorts of flawed cost-benefit analyses can be useful in helping
us to set and reset our priorities, let’s consider some examples.
Many companies offer their employees (sometimes quite generous)
retirement packages; but a surprising percentage of people don’t participate
in them. Many of these people would benefit from an unreduced
cost-benefit analysis of the choice of whether to invest in such a retirement
account. Such an analysis would not even attempt to reduce all the costs
and benefits of the options to a single value (like current dollars). Consider
the benefits of current spending (on, say, a larger mortgage on a larger
home) and the potential future costs of inadequate retirement funds
(lower standard of living, dependence on kin or children). While these
costs and benefits cannot be reduced to a single unit of value, we suspect
that if people thought clearly and coolly about the various options, they might be surprised to find that they would explicitly reject the values
implicit in their actual decisions.
Let’s consider an example of some radically incomplete cost-benefit
analyses that as a historical matter affected public-policy decision making
for the better: attempts to put a monetary value on human lives. In late
seventeenth-century Britain, William Petty ‘‘argued in favor of measures
to ward off or mitigate the effects of the plague on the grounds that by
spending a few thousand pounds the king might protect an investment
many times greater in the lives of his subjects’’ (Porter 1994, 214–15). By
the early part of the twentieth century, professional actuaries working for
insurance companies had taken over the business of placing monetary
values on human lives. In The Money Value of a Man (1930), Louis Dublin
and Alfred Lotka attached a dollar figure to human lives, basing their calculations
on the expected net present value of future earnings. Their analyses
explicitly recognized that they could not put a monetary figure on the
‘‘intangibles of life’’ but instead viewed humans (and in particular, men)
as just so much equipment:
Man has much in common with the industrial aids, machines, manufacturing
plants, and so forth, of which he makes use to conduct the business of
life. Like them he has a ‘‘cost of installation,’’ . . . running expenses, interest
on capital invested, and the loss of a certain proportion of children that do
not live to attain adult age, just as in manufacturing processes allowance
must be made for losses by ‘‘spoilage’’ of material that never reaches the
‘‘finished’’ stage. (1930, 44, quoted in Porter 1994, 216)
This kind of cost-benefit analysis inevitably strikes us as appallingly crass.
But besides figuring out how much life insurance to sell people, these
analyses were also typically put to political use:
None of these calculations . . . was part of a formal assessment of costs and
benefits. They were intended not to guide policy in detail, but to soften
slightly those famously hardheaded administrators and businessmen who
were reluctant to invest dollars, pounds, and francs in what would come to
be known as human capital. The sentimental and self-regarding emotions
could be left out because the numbers were already large enough to draw
attention, and that was their only real purpose . . . [W]hile these formulas
may not have been very accurate, they were surprisingly precise. . . . This was
almost indispensable if calculation was to figure significantly in decisions
vulnerable to public criticism. (Porter, 217)
The cost-benefit analyses suggested that the preventable suffering and
death of poor laborers was bad for business. We might view it as wearily predictable that it was profit that spurred captains of industry to support
the public works projects that prevented the deaths of many of our
ancestors. And one would be right to object that the cost-benefit approach
is no guarantor of a positive outcome. The morally right policies were
implemented because of contingent facts about the profit structure of local
industrial economies rather than because of the intrinsic moral worth of
human laborers. But while we may be appalled that ethical considerations
did not move the captains of industry quicker, we can be glad that costbenefit
considerations kept them from moving slower still.
The cost-benefit analyses that convinced ‘‘hardheaded administrators
and businessmen’’ that they were underestimating the monetary value of
their ‘‘human capital’’ was radically incomplete. It focused only on economic
considerations. But the right course of action was so clearly right
that any number of different cost-benefit analyses—even those informed
by values we might find crass or repugnant—delivered the correct result.
When the world is obliging in this way, incomplete cost-benefit analyses
can lead us to effectively revise our priorities and actions.
Flawed cost-benefit analyses are useful because they dramatize the
opportunity costs of a favored course of action. For example, after airplane
crashes, there are often voices pressing for greater air safety regulations.
While such regulations might make air travel safer, they might also have the
effect of making travel more dangerous. That’s because the increased regulations
may increase the price of flying and so lead more people to drive—
which is a more dangerous form of transportation (Sunstein 2000, 1073).
(Further, given its relative safety, making air travel a tiny bit safer may well
be less cost effective than, say, repaving the Pennsylvania Turnpike.) Now it
may be that we are willing to accept a greater number of total traffic injuries
and fatalities in exchange for slightly safer (and more expensive) air travel.
But by engaging in cost-benefit analysis—even one that only considers the
rather crass value of money spent per death prevented—we can recognize
that the decision to make air travel slightly safer has this effect. Even a
flawed cost-benefit analysis can help us to expose the aims and values
implicit in our decisions; and this exposure can lead us to change, challenge,
or clarify our values and priorities. Perhaps we so dread the terrifying
nature of airplane deaths that we are willing to accept an increased probability
of injury or death for a decreased probability of a terror-filled death.
But only by exposing this value underlying our decision can we even begin
to question it. Even a flawed cost-benefit analysis can help us set priorities
and effectively marshal our scarce resources so as to improve our decision
making (Sunstein 2000).
As citizens of a democracy, we have an interest in how members of
governmental safety boards (e.g., OSHA, EPA, etc.) decide how to allocate
scarce resources to improve occupational and other federal safety standards.
In making such decisions, it is useful to know that (according to the
Consumer Product Safety Commission) banning unvented space heaters
is among the cheapest ways to save lives, costing $100,000 per prevented
death. Limiting exposure to asbestos in the workplace is considerably
more expensive, at 8.3 million dollars per prevented death (OSHA). And
the cost of listing wood-preserving chemicals as hazardous waste is estimated
by the EPA to be 5.7 trillion dollars per prevented death (Sunstein,
2000). By being clear about what measures are likely to save the greatest
number of people (or minimize the number of people getting sick), we can
better make decisions that accurately reflect our values.