2. A cost-benefit approach to epistemology
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94
Before tackling the difficulties associated with a cost-benefit approach to
epistemology, it might be valuable to note that cost-benefit considerations
are a familiar, even banal, feature of perceptual and cognitive psychology.
From early psychophysics to contemporary cognitive psychology, psychologists
often explain successes, as well as routine breakdowns, in terms
of specific allocations of attention and memory across perceptual modalities
and cognitive capacities. For example, many of our reflexes are best
understood as cognitive instantiations of a complex cost-benefit analysis.
The ducking reflex occurs whenever you see a rigid object translating
toward your head. Those who don’t duck, to quote Quine, ‘‘have a pathetic
but praiseworthy tendency to die before reproducing their kind’’
(1969, 126). This reflex has accommodated a complex payoff matrix.
When a rigid object is moving toward your head, the potentially serious
consequences of not avoiding it call for a fast and mandatory reflex. So
you duck, even when the trusted friend who threw the object tells you that
it won’t hurt you. Low risk and low benefit outcomes do not produce
comparably reliable behavior. We are skeptical that this kind of adaptationist
story will work for all of our cognitive mechanisms. But adaptationist
explanations are quite plausible for reflexes, and such explanations
tend to rely explicitly on cost-benefit considerations (e.g., Parker 1974;
Maynard Smith 1978).
Processes of greater cognitive depth also reveal tradeoffs between costs
and benefits. Consider memory. Our recall performance suffers terribly when resources get allocated to competing tasks. In the classic experiments
on divided attention, people were presented with two spoken messages.
The participants could not identify the contents of both messages, recalling
one well and only the most basic characteristics of the other (e.g., that
it changed from speech to tone, etc.). Consider a timely example. Talking
on a cellphone (either handheld or hands-free) while driving resulted in
twice as many failures to detect a simulated traffic signal and slower reactions
to those signals when they were detected (Strayer and Johnston,
2001). These effects of divided attention exert a powerful influence on our
daily activities, which often involve doing two or more things at once. In
short, strategies involving divided attention bring predictable costs. (This
point is embodied in the wise advice of a parent: ‘‘Don’t smooch while
driving—you’ll do both badly.’’) We can drive safely or talk on the cellphone.
We can read or listen to someone addressing us. The choice to do
one, the other, or both should be based on an analysis of the costs and
benefits of the various distributions of cognitive resources (Payne, Bettman,
and Johnson 1993).
Now it’s time to pay the piper. If applied epistemology involves a kind
of cost-benefit analysis, then we need to clearly identify the costs and
benefits of reasoning. But this is hard to do for three reasons. First, it is not
clear how to reduce the myriad benefits of reasoning to countable units.
Second, it is not clear how to reduce all the various costs of reasoning to
countable units. And third, it’s doubtful that we can reasonably interpret a
smooth cost-benefit curve for a reasoning strategy. Let’s consider these
issues in turn.
Before tackling the difficulties associated with a cost-benefit approach to
epistemology, it might be valuable to note that cost-benefit considerations
are a familiar, even banal, feature of perceptual and cognitive psychology.
From early psychophysics to contemporary cognitive psychology, psychologists
often explain successes, as well as routine breakdowns, in terms
of specific allocations of attention and memory across perceptual modalities
and cognitive capacities. For example, many of our reflexes are best
understood as cognitive instantiations of a complex cost-benefit analysis.
The ducking reflex occurs whenever you see a rigid object translating
toward your head. Those who don’t duck, to quote Quine, ‘‘have a pathetic
but praiseworthy tendency to die before reproducing their kind’’
(1969, 126). This reflex has accommodated a complex payoff matrix.
When a rigid object is moving toward your head, the potentially serious
consequences of not avoiding it call for a fast and mandatory reflex. So
you duck, even when the trusted friend who threw the object tells you that
it won’t hurt you. Low risk and low benefit outcomes do not produce
comparably reliable behavior. We are skeptical that this kind of adaptationist
story will work for all of our cognitive mechanisms. But adaptationist
explanations are quite plausible for reflexes, and such explanations
tend to rely explicitly on cost-benefit considerations (e.g., Parker 1974;
Maynard Smith 1978).
Processes of greater cognitive depth also reveal tradeoffs between costs
and benefits. Consider memory. Our recall performance suffers terribly when resources get allocated to competing tasks. In the classic experiments
on divided attention, people were presented with two spoken messages.
The participants could not identify the contents of both messages, recalling
one well and only the most basic characteristics of the other (e.g., that
it changed from speech to tone, etc.). Consider a timely example. Talking
on a cellphone (either handheld or hands-free) while driving resulted in
twice as many failures to detect a simulated traffic signal and slower reactions
to those signals when they were detected (Strayer and Johnston,
2001). These effects of divided attention exert a powerful influence on our
daily activities, which often involve doing two or more things at once. In
short, strategies involving divided attention bring predictable costs. (This
point is embodied in the wise advice of a parent: ‘‘Don’t smooch while
driving—you’ll do both badly.’’) We can drive safely or talk on the cellphone.
We can read or listen to someone addressing us. The choice to do
one, the other, or both should be based on an analysis of the costs and
benefits of the various distributions of cognitive resources (Payne, Bettman,
and Johnson 1993).
Now it’s time to pay the piper. If applied epistemology involves a kind
of cost-benefit analysis, then we need to clearly identify the costs and
benefits of reasoning. But this is hard to do for three reasons. First, it is not
clear how to reduce the myriad benefits of reasoning to countable units.
Second, it is not clear how to reduce all the various costs of reasoning to
countable units. And third, it’s doubtful that we can reasonably interpret a
smooth cost-benefit curve for a reasoning strategy. Let’s consider these
issues in turn.