11.1 Not justification
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94
At least two well-known philosophers have called for epistemological
theories that do not focus on justification. In 1979, Alvin Goldman argued
for an approach to epistemology he called epistemics that would focus on
assessing and guiding our mental processes. While we clearly do not share
Goldman’s appreciation for our ‘‘epistemic folkways’’, his call for a ‘‘scientific
epistemology’’ has not received the response it deserves (1992). In
1990, Stephen Stich defended a pragmatic account of ‘‘cognitive evaluation’’
and it was clearly not a theory for the assessment of belief tokens,
but something very much like what we offer here: it was a theory for the
assessment of a person’s reasoning strategies. We could cite other philosophers’
work who do not focus primarily on justification (e.g., Harman
1986), but the theory we have presented in this book is very much in the
spirit of the proposals of Goldman and Stich.
What about virtue epistemology? These theories tend to focus on
providing an account of epistemic virtue rather than epistemic justification
(although many virtue theorists offer an account of epistemic justification
in terms of epistemic virtue). There are, of course, quite different
theories of virtue epistemology (e.g., Sosa 1991, Zagzebski 1996). We
admire much of Sosa’s epistemology. For example, we agree that ‘‘it is
philosopher’s arrogance to suppose mere reflection the source of all intellectual
virtue’’ (Sosa 1991a, 266). Still, we do not take virtue theories of
epistemology, as they currently stand, to be fellow travelers. Our primary
worry is that current virtue theories are not sufficiently informed by
empirical psychology. If we take an epistemic virtue to be (roughly) a
habit of mind that tends to lead to truths, it is a thoroughly empirical
question which habits of mind will do this. While virtue theorists would
agree (e.g., Sosa 1991b), we suspect that they have underestimated how
counterintuitive the ‘‘virtues’’ are likely to be. One worry is that insofar as
virtues are dispositions that are reasonably stable across contexts, there is some reason to wonder whether people exhibit virtues of this sort (see
Doris 2002 for a discussion of the moral virtues along these lines). Another
problem is that the psychological evidence is likely to show that we just
aren’t as wise about epistemic matters as we think we are. Given the
evidence presented in this book, it must be the case that we have a lot of
mistaken beliefs about what habits of mind are virtuous. In a nutshell, the
framework of virtue epistemology—roughly, that we should seek to instill
in ourselves habits of mind that tend to be reliable—is fine as far as it goes.
But to think we have a good intuitive sense of what those habits of mind
might be strikes us as optimistic.
At least two well-known philosophers have called for epistemological
theories that do not focus on justification. In 1979, Alvin Goldman argued
for an approach to epistemology he called epistemics that would focus on
assessing and guiding our mental processes. While we clearly do not share
Goldman’s appreciation for our ‘‘epistemic folkways’’, his call for a ‘‘scientific
epistemology’’ has not received the response it deserves (1992). In
1990, Stephen Stich defended a pragmatic account of ‘‘cognitive evaluation’’
and it was clearly not a theory for the assessment of belief tokens,
but something very much like what we offer here: it was a theory for the
assessment of a person’s reasoning strategies. We could cite other philosophers’
work who do not focus primarily on justification (e.g., Harman
1986), but the theory we have presented in this book is very much in the
spirit of the proposals of Goldman and Stich.
What about virtue epistemology? These theories tend to focus on
providing an account of epistemic virtue rather than epistemic justification
(although many virtue theorists offer an account of epistemic justification
in terms of epistemic virtue). There are, of course, quite different
theories of virtue epistemology (e.g., Sosa 1991, Zagzebski 1996). We
admire much of Sosa’s epistemology. For example, we agree that ‘‘it is
philosopher’s arrogance to suppose mere reflection the source of all intellectual
virtue’’ (Sosa 1991a, 266). Still, we do not take virtue theories of
epistemology, as they currently stand, to be fellow travelers. Our primary
worry is that current virtue theories are not sufficiently informed by
empirical psychology. If we take an epistemic virtue to be (roughly) a
habit of mind that tends to lead to truths, it is a thoroughly empirical
question which habits of mind will do this. While virtue theorists would
agree (e.g., Sosa 1991b), we suspect that they have underestimated how
counterintuitive the ‘‘virtues’’ are likely to be. One worry is that insofar as
virtues are dispositions that are reasonably stable across contexts, there is some reason to wonder whether people exhibit virtues of this sort (see
Doris 2002 for a discussion of the moral virtues along these lines). Another
problem is that the psychological evidence is likely to show that we just
aren’t as wise about epistemic matters as we think we are. Given the
evidence presented in this book, it must be the case that we have a lot of
mistaken beliefs about what habits of mind are virtuous. In a nutshell, the
framework of virtue epistemology—roughly, that we should seek to instill
in ourselves habits of mind that tend to be reliable—is fine as far as it goes.
But to think we have a good intuitive sense of what those habits of mind
might be strikes us as optimistic.