1. The role of significance in Strategic Reliabilism
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94
It is easy to despair of coming up with a notion of significance that might
be useful for epistemology. Take a reasoner in a context who is trying to
figure out what is the most significant problem she faces. Will a general
theory of significance provide useful information about this case? If it is an
easy case, the answer will be so obvious that a theory of significance will be
superfluous. If she is concentrating very hard on the mind-body problem
while driving up to a railroad crossing with the sound of a train in the distance,
we don’t need any fancy theories to tell us which problem is more
significant. In many hard cases, the answer will be nonobvious because the
reasoner doesn’t know enough about the idiosyncratic details of his situation
to know which problem is the most significant. For example, a
reasoner’s boss might ask him to develop a business plan; it might not be
clear whether he should be developing what he thinks is the best plan or
whether he should be developing what he thinks his boss thinks is the best
plan. In this case, no theory of significance is going to be useful because
what the reasoner lacks isn’t a sense of what problems are generally significant.
The reasoner lacks knowledge about what his boss really wants, and
that knowledge won’t be provided by a theory of significance. We might
despair because no significance-based epistemology is going to be able to
provide advice that is specific to a reasoner’s particular situation that is
both nonobvious and definitive. So one might reasonably conclude that
while significance is an important notion, there is nothing much useful for
an epistemological theory to say about it.
We endorse the premises of the above argument: Issues of significance
arise in particular cases. And an epistemological theory that includes an
account of significance will not be able to be applied directly and fruitfully
to many particular cases. In other words, we should not expect a recipe
book that will allow a reasoner to identify beforehand all and only the
significant problems that confront her. It does not follow, however, that
epistemology need not concern itself with significance. Let’s step back and
investigate the role significance ought to play in a normative epistemology.
The primary aim of epistemology, from our perspective, is to provide
useful, general advice about reasoning. Such advice is inevitably going to
depend on fairly general judgments of epistemic significance. These judgments
will typically involve claims about what kinds of problems are likely
to be significant for reasoners in general. For example, in their day-to-day
lives, people often rely on causal reasoning. We can avoid pain and misery
if we can accurately predict the causal outcomes of various actions—our
own, those of others, and those of nature. That’s not to say that every
reasoning problem that calls for causal reasoning is significant. But many
of the significant problems that people generally face involve causal reasoning.
As a result, a significance-based epistemology can recommend that we be prepared to expend a fair amount of time and energy improving our
reasoning about causal matters. This general truth about significance also
has important implications for the practice of epistemology. In filling out
the practical, prescriptive content of a significance-based epistemology, we
can focus our attention on uncovering biases to which people are most
prone in reasoning about significant matters. We can then offer well-tested
correctives to those biases, or we can suggest new, replacement strategies
for reasoning about those matters.
It is easy to despair of coming up with a notion of significance that might
be useful for epistemology. Take a reasoner in a context who is trying to
figure out what is the most significant problem she faces. Will a general
theory of significance provide useful information about this case? If it is an
easy case, the answer will be so obvious that a theory of significance will be
superfluous. If she is concentrating very hard on the mind-body problem
while driving up to a railroad crossing with the sound of a train in the distance,
we don’t need any fancy theories to tell us which problem is more
significant. In many hard cases, the answer will be nonobvious because the
reasoner doesn’t know enough about the idiosyncratic details of his situation
to know which problem is the most significant. For example, a
reasoner’s boss might ask him to develop a business plan; it might not be
clear whether he should be developing what he thinks is the best plan or
whether he should be developing what he thinks his boss thinks is the best
plan. In this case, no theory of significance is going to be useful because
what the reasoner lacks isn’t a sense of what problems are generally significant.
The reasoner lacks knowledge about what his boss really wants, and
that knowledge won’t be provided by a theory of significance. We might
despair because no significance-based epistemology is going to be able to
provide advice that is specific to a reasoner’s particular situation that is
both nonobvious and definitive. So one might reasonably conclude that
while significance is an important notion, there is nothing much useful for
an epistemological theory to say about it.
We endorse the premises of the above argument: Issues of significance
arise in particular cases. And an epistemological theory that includes an
account of significance will not be able to be applied directly and fruitfully
to many particular cases. In other words, we should not expect a recipe
book that will allow a reasoner to identify beforehand all and only the
significant problems that confront her. It does not follow, however, that
epistemology need not concern itself with significance. Let’s step back and
investigate the role significance ought to play in a normative epistemology.
The primary aim of epistemology, from our perspective, is to provide
useful, general advice about reasoning. Such advice is inevitably going to
depend on fairly general judgments of epistemic significance. These judgments
will typically involve claims about what kinds of problems are likely
to be significant for reasoners in general. For example, in their day-to-day
lives, people often rely on causal reasoning. We can avoid pain and misery
if we can accurately predict the causal outcomes of various actions—our
own, those of others, and those of nature. That’s not to say that every
reasoning problem that calls for causal reasoning is significant. But many
of the significant problems that people generally face involve causal reasoning.
As a result, a significance-based epistemology can recommend that we be prepared to expend a fair amount of time and energy improving our
reasoning about causal matters. This general truth about significance also
has important implications for the practice of epistemology. In filling out
the practical, prescriptive content of a significance-based epistemology, we
can focus our attention on uncovering biases to which people are most
prone in reasoning about significant matters. We can then offer well-tested
correctives to those biases, or we can suggest new, replacement strategies
for reasoning about those matters.