3.3. Rare events
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94
If we accept the need for controls, then it becomes quite difficult to
provide a causal explanation for very rare or unique events. For example,
after someone commits a horrible crime, there is the inevitable spate of
‘‘explanation’’ stories in the media. These reports focus on some sordid or
unhappy aspects of the person’s background—a taste for music with violent
lyrics or violent video games, a broken home, distant parents, adolescent
alienation, or a childhood tendency to be cruel to animals. Such
themes make for a narrative that seems to culminate naturally with the
crime. These are often very good stories—memorable, dramatic, and they
satisfy our subjective sense of understanding. But do they accurately identify
the causal factors that led to the crime? After all, those who come
up with these narratives (and those of us who believe them) are seldom
constrained by any knowledge of base rates or serious empirical research
on violence.
How many of us have lived such fortunate lives that if a gaggle of
reporters were set loose on us, not one could construct a narrative on the
basis of our youth that plausibly culminated in a horrible crime (fictitious,
we trust)? In our cases, the greenest cub reporter could whip out a bloodcurdling
narrative along the lines of ‘‘quiet alienated youth goes bad’’ in a
day. As pillars of our communities, we intend to keep these stories to
ourselves. But it’s not just that lots of kids have stories uncomfortably similar to those told in the media about criminals. It’s also that we don’t
even know if those whose pasts are free of alleged ‘‘danger signs’’ really are
less prone to violence than the rest of us.
The lesson we would draw is not that narrative modes of inquiry are
irreducibly or intrinsically unsound. All of us offer narrative explanations,
particularly for people’s behavior. Rather, we would contend that storytelling
forms of inquiry are less reliable than most of us believe; and narrative
explanations deserve much less confidence than they typically get.
Without knowledge of base rates and without an accurate causal model,
we can only rely on sweet anecdote and the subjective plausibility of a
good story. On some occasions, these stories may act as useful heuristics.
But too often these stories rely on background knowledge that has not
risked the painful test of disconfirming feedback. Without awareness of
our own boundedness and frailty, then, we can only proceed with blithe
innocence, assuming that a good story is good enough. But as the literature
we have considered so far indicates, good stories come easy. True
stories are harder to find.
If we accept the need for controls, then it becomes quite difficult to
provide a causal explanation for very rare or unique events. For example,
after someone commits a horrible crime, there is the inevitable spate of
‘‘explanation’’ stories in the media. These reports focus on some sordid or
unhappy aspects of the person’s background—a taste for music with violent
lyrics or violent video games, a broken home, distant parents, adolescent
alienation, or a childhood tendency to be cruel to animals. Such
themes make for a narrative that seems to culminate naturally with the
crime. These are often very good stories—memorable, dramatic, and they
satisfy our subjective sense of understanding. But do they accurately identify
the causal factors that led to the crime? After all, those who come
up with these narratives (and those of us who believe them) are seldom
constrained by any knowledge of base rates or serious empirical research
on violence.
How many of us have lived such fortunate lives that if a gaggle of
reporters were set loose on us, not one could construct a narrative on the
basis of our youth that plausibly culminated in a horrible crime (fictitious,
we trust)? In our cases, the greenest cub reporter could whip out a bloodcurdling
narrative along the lines of ‘‘quiet alienated youth goes bad’’ in a
day. As pillars of our communities, we intend to keep these stories to
ourselves. But it’s not just that lots of kids have stories uncomfortably similar to those told in the media about criminals. It’s also that we don’t
even know if those whose pasts are free of alleged ‘‘danger signs’’ really are
less prone to violence than the rest of us.
The lesson we would draw is not that narrative modes of inquiry are
irreducibly or intrinsically unsound. All of us offer narrative explanations,
particularly for people’s behavior. Rather, we would contend that storytelling
forms of inquiry are less reliable than most of us believe; and narrative
explanations deserve much less confidence than they typically get.
Without knowledge of base rates and without an accurate causal model,
we can only rely on sweet anecdote and the subjective plausibility of a
good story. On some occasions, these stories may act as useful heuristics.
But too often these stories rely on background knowledge that has not
risked the painful test of disconfirming feedback. Without awareness of
our own boundedness and frailty, then, we can only proceed with blithe
innocence, assuming that a good story is good enough. But as the literature
we have considered so far indicates, good stories come easy. True
stories are harder to find.