5. The relative paucity of SPRs
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94
Let’s grant that Ameliorative Psychology offers some wonderful SPRs. But
there just aren’t that many, compared to the number of significant reasoning
problems we face every day. If John had at his disposal all successful, tractable
SPRs, they would not help him deal with the overwhelming majority of the
significant reasoning problems in his life. Throughout this book, you attack
SAE for offering theories that do not provide useful guidance to reasoners. But
your theory fares just about as badly on this score. A handful of successful
SPRs for making judgments about a hodgepodge of issues hardly counts as
useful reasoning advice.
There are three points to make in response to this objection. First,
Ameliorative Psychology provides considerably more guidance than is
here suggested. There is more to Ameliorative Psychology than SPRs. For
example, the consider-the-opposite strategy and the various strategies for
thinking about causation (chapter 9) are potentially applicable to a very
wide range of reasoning problems. Second, this objection seems to assume
that the epistemological theory we defend, Strategic Reliabilism, is exhausted
by the practical advice offered by Ameliorative Psychology. This is
a misunderstanding. Strategic Reliabilism offers a general framework that
accounts for the epistemic quality of particular reasoning strategies. While
Strategic Reliabilism grounds the prescriptions of Ameliorative Psychology,
it is not exhausted by those prescriptions. And third, while Ameliorative
Psychology might not provide as much reason-guidance as we
might hope, it does provide more than the theories of Standard Analytic
Epistemology. The theories of SAE are almost entirely indifferent to issues
of significance and to issues of the costs and benefits of reasoning. Such
theories can perhaps advise that we should only adopt justified beliefs, and
they can explain in exquisite detail what they mean by ‘justified’. But this
hardly counts as useful advice for three reasons. (a) We doubt that SAE
embodies a reasonable method of identifying the proper goal of reasoning
(see chapter 7). (b) For most of us at most times, there are infinitely many
justified beliefs we could adopt. Without an account of significance or an
account of the costs and benefits of reasoning, the theories of SAE have no
way to advise someone to adopt one justified belief rather than any other
(see chapters 5 and 6). And (c) at best, the theories of SAE define a goal of
reasoning, they don’t provide any useful guidance about how to achieve
that goal (see chapter 9). This is reminiscent of the advice offered by one
of our Little League baseball coaches who told his players, ‘‘When I tip my
cap, that means you should hit a home run.’’ Unlike proponents of SAE,
the coach was joking.
Let’s grant that Ameliorative Psychology offers some wonderful SPRs. But
there just aren’t that many, compared to the number of significant reasoning
problems we face every day. If John had at his disposal all successful, tractable
SPRs, they would not help him deal with the overwhelming majority of the
significant reasoning problems in his life. Throughout this book, you attack
SAE for offering theories that do not provide useful guidance to reasoners. But
your theory fares just about as badly on this score. A handful of successful
SPRs for making judgments about a hodgepodge of issues hardly counts as
useful reasoning advice.
There are three points to make in response to this objection. First,
Ameliorative Psychology provides considerably more guidance than is
here suggested. There is more to Ameliorative Psychology than SPRs. For
example, the consider-the-opposite strategy and the various strategies for
thinking about causation (chapter 9) are potentially applicable to a very
wide range of reasoning problems. Second, this objection seems to assume
that the epistemological theory we defend, Strategic Reliabilism, is exhausted
by the practical advice offered by Ameliorative Psychology. This is
a misunderstanding. Strategic Reliabilism offers a general framework that
accounts for the epistemic quality of particular reasoning strategies. While
Strategic Reliabilism grounds the prescriptions of Ameliorative Psychology,
it is not exhausted by those prescriptions. And third, while Ameliorative
Psychology might not provide as much reason-guidance as we
might hope, it does provide more than the theories of Standard Analytic
Epistemology. The theories of SAE are almost entirely indifferent to issues
of significance and to issues of the costs and benefits of reasoning. Such
theories can perhaps advise that we should only adopt justified beliefs, and
they can explain in exquisite detail what they mean by ‘justified’. But this
hardly counts as useful advice for three reasons. (a) We doubt that SAE
embodies a reasonable method of identifying the proper goal of reasoning
(see chapter 7). (b) For most of us at most times, there are infinitely many
justified beliefs we could adopt. Without an account of significance or an
account of the costs and benefits of reasoning, the theories of SAE have no
way to advise someone to adopt one justified belief rather than any other
(see chapters 5 and 6). And (c) at best, the theories of SAE define a goal of
reasoning, they don’t provide any useful guidance about how to achieve
that goal (see chapter 9). This is reminiscent of the advice offered by one
of our Little League baseball coaches who told his players, ‘‘When I tip my
cap, that means you should hit a home run.’’ Unlike proponents of SAE,
the coach was joking.