2. A reason-based approach to significance
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94
The fundamental difficulty in developing an account of significance is
what we might call the thick-thin problem. On the one hand, we need an
account of significance that is thick enough to forbid an ‘‘anything goes’’
attitude toward significance. For example, no matter how intrinsically
compelling one might find the problem of (say) establishing the length of
one’s left thumbnail at every five second interval, that interest, by itself,
does not make that problem particularly significant. (That’s not to say, of
course, that we can’t imagine a fanciful scenario in which close thumbnail
monitoring is a highly significant problem. But for most of us most of the
time, it’s not.) So we need an account of significance that is thick enough
to yield the result that a problem might be relatively insignificant even if
someone has a powerful subjective desire to tackle it. But on the other
hand, we need an account of significance that is thin enough to license
some dramatic interpersonal differences in what problems are significant.
For example, establishing whether the short-tailed shrew is the smallest
North American mammal with poisonous saliva might be a very significant
problem to a biologist whose professional reputation depends on her
knowledge of North American shrews. For most of the rest of us, however,
this is not an especially significant problem. So the thick-thin problem is
that the constraints on significance must allow for some substantive interpersonal
and interinstitutional differences about what problems are
significant without licensing an ‘‘anything goes’’ subjectivism.
Our view holds that the significance of a problem for S is a function of
the weight of the objective reasons S has for devoting resources to solving that
problem. This view assumes that we have objective reasons of various sorts
for action and that we can weigh these reasons against one another. We are
aware that these are bold and controversial assumptions. But given our
broadly Aristotelian approach to epistemology, we don’t think it’s possible to think fully and clearly about epistemology without also bringing in views
about other normative domains. So we will unabashedly take the assumption
that there are objective reasons for action—they stand regardless of
whether a subject recognizes them or (after reflection) accepts them as legitimate
(see Railton 1986; Boyd 1988). This reason-based account of significance
has the resources to handle the thick-thin problem. Some reasons
(such as those that arise from basic moral obligations) are universal. They
place firm restrictions on the sort of problems that can be significant. But
other reasons (such as those that arise from one’s social or professional
obligations) might be quite different for different people. These sorts of
reasons permit fairly dramatic differences in the sorts of problems that
different people might find significant.
The two most intuitively compelling kinds of objective reasons are
also the most important for our purposes. We take it that people have
objective moral reasons and objective prudential reasons for action. So
consider the reasoning problem faced by a doctor who is diagnosing
whether a patient has a serious disease on the basis of various test results.
This problem is highly significant for the doctor because she has objective
moral and prudential reasons for reasoning very carefully and well about
such a problem. These reasons are objective because they stand regardless
of whether she recognizes them or, upon reflection, accepts them. This is
particularly plausible in a case (like this one) in which the objective reasons
the doctor has for devoting resources to this problem are connected
(at least in part) to the consequences of her reasoning. Accurately diagnosing
a patient is a high-stakes proposition, both for the patient and for
the doctor. The potential costs of an inaccurate diagnosis are huge, as are
the potential benefits of an accurate diagnosis. When someone’s objective
reasons for tackling a problem are a function of the consequences of getting
or not getting an accurate result, it’s intuitively plausible that these
reasons stand even if the doctor doesn’t recognize or care about them. And
since these reasons are weighty, the problem is significant for the doctor
(not to mention her patient!).
It would be a mistake, however, to think that all the objective reasons
we could have for action involve only consequences. Individuals can have
reasons for tackling certain problems because they have pursued or accepted
the moral and professional duties (along with the attendant benefits)
of certain social or professional roles. For example, regardless of the
consequences, doctors have a duty (a moral and professional duty) to
devote resources to thinking clearly about their patients; police officers
have a duty to devote resources to thinking clearly about solving and preventing crime; university professors have a duty to devote resources to
thinking clearly about how to effectively teach their students—and some
have a duty to devote resources to thinking clearly about short-tailed
shrews or the mind-body problem.
Objective reasons include more than moral, prudential, or social-role
sorts of reasons. For example, people can have legitimate (and objective)
epistemic reasons for tackling a certain problem. We take it that discovering
the truth about the basic physical or social structure of the world is
intrinsically valuable. So even if we can’t be sure that it will lead to any
practical results, the physicists at CERN and Fermilab have epistemic
reasons (beyond their prudential reasons) for spending cognitive resources
on trying to discover the Higgs boson.
Let’s consider three worries about this reason-based account of significance.
The first worry concerns insignificant problems. For those of us
who have no legitimate reasons and no personal interest in constantly
monitoring our fingernail length or the number of Goodyear Blimps in
our field of vision, our view is that such problems are insignificant. But the
thick-thin problem arises when we ask: What about the subject who is
interested in tackling such navel-gazing reasoning problems? Doesn’t this
interest, by itself, give the subject some objective reason to tackle the problem?
Yes. We can grant the following general principle: If S desires to do X,
that gives S some (objective) reason to do X. But notice, this principle is
silent about the strength of this objective reason. On the assumption that S
has no other reasons—moral, prudential, epistemic, aesthetic, etc.—to
pursue this problem, it would seem that this problem, while not completely
insignificant, is of very, very little significance. If S is devoting
resources to monitoring his fingernail length rather than (say) the safety
of his child, this is a pathology that goes well beyond concerns with
poor reasoning. But on our view, devoting resources to a barely significant
problem instead of a significant problem is a case of poor reasoning—and
possibly worse.
A second worry about our view concerns ‘‘lost cause’’ problems. Consider
the problem of whether the current health care system in the U.S. is
just and efficient. Given our health care system’s barriers to participatory
influence, it might be that an individual has no power to change or help
change the system. Is this apparently ‘‘lost cause’’ a significant problem for
the person? If the person is interested in the problem, then (as in the
navel-gazing cases) that makes the problem at least a little bit significant.
But on what grounds might it be more than barely significant? One might
have prudential reasons to think about the health care system in order to understand it well enough to make good use of it. But let’s suppose this
consideration isn’t relevant to the reasoner. There are still two classes of
objective reason that could make ‘‘lost cause’’ problems significant. First,
we have a civic or political duty to be well informed on important topics
of the day (i.e., topics that are important to people’s well-being). How
does this duty work? The only way positive change can occur in a democracy
is if those with minority opinions don’t give up when they don’t
foresee beneficial changes coming in the short term. But the possibility of
positive change also requires that those who aren’t informed on important
subjects pay attention to them. This seems to us to be the basis of the civic
or political duty that makes thinking about the moral status of our society’s
institutions significant—even when we have vanishingly small
prospects for changing them. Another set of objective reasons that might
ground the significance of these ‘‘lost causes’’ involves considerations of
virtue. Following up on our generally Aristotelian approach to epistemology,
it seems plausible to suppose that there is a nonaccidental connection
between being an excellent reasoner and an excellent person. We
venture to guess (and we take this to be a testable assumption) that
spending resources thinking seriously about whether one’s society is just is
a feature of an excellent character and a flourishing life. Indeed, it’s not
too much of an overstatement to say that Western philosophy originated,
in the person of Socrates, in precisely this kind of serious reflection on
‘‘lost causes.’’
The third worry about our view concerns ‘‘negatively’’ significant
reasoning problems. Reasoners may have objective reasons for not devoting
resources to particular sorts of problem. For example, we suspect that
a psychologically healthy person will not regularly calculate and recalculate
what are his narrow self-interests—particularly if such constant recalculation
alienates him from activities he finds satisfying and casts his friends
as potential competitors. We take it that this can be a ‘‘negatively’’ significant
reasoning problem. This is a separate category from significant
and insignificant problems. ‘‘Negatively’’ significant problems are those for
which one has positive reason (not based on opportunity costs) to avoid.
We have discussed (in chapter 3) some of the counterintuitive findings of
‘‘hedonic psychology.’’ These findings suggest that focusing cognitive
resources on certain kinds of problem are likely to lead to frustration and
loss of happiness. To take one perhaps unsurprising example, people who
pursue money in the belief that it will increase their happiness express
greater frustration than their peers (Myers 2000). We suspect (although
we have only anecdotal evidence for this hypothesis) that ‘‘philosophy graduate student disease’’ (the constant monitoring of one’s actual or
perceived ‘‘smartness’’ status) involves the devotion of resources to a negatively
significant problem.
Our general account of epistemic significance resides, ultimately, in
judgments about what conduces to human well-being. If we view humans
as part of the natural order, then the conditions that contribute to human
well-being are open to scientific investigation. Some might worry that
these conditions are too variable to be studied systematically and generalized
about scientifically. There is, however, reason for optimism. While
the conditions of human well-being may be tied to norms that differ
across individuals and across cultures, the challenges of generalizing across
varied groups and individuals have been surmounted in other sciences,
such as developmental and evolutionary biology. There is ample empirical
evidence that the basic conditions of human well-being involve health,
deep social attachments, personal security, and the pursuit of significant
projects (Diener and Seligman 2002; Myers 2000). Just as certain personality
types engage in activities that make them less happy, there are
economic, social, and political institutions that have a systematic and
adjustable influence on people’s happiness (Diener 2000; Diener and Oishi
2000; Frey and Stutzer 2002; Lane 2000). For example, income, unemployment,
and inflation all have marked and sustained influences on happiness
(Frey and Stutzer 2002). Interestingly, all three partly result from institutional
planning—of tax policy, monetary policy, and available services—
and so can be regulated to a certain extent by government action. To
continue the theme, certain objective economic conditions, such as destitution,
are incompatible with well-being (Dasgupta 1993). These empirical
findings about the conditions that influence happiness and welfare set
limits on what can count as a significant problem. Some of the most
significant problems we face concern how to renovate maladaptive social
institutions that undermine our happiness and well-being, and how to
implement new social, political, and economic institutions and procedures
that are most likely to promote well-being and control the sources of
avoidable unhappiness.
The fundamental difficulty in developing an account of significance is
what we might call the thick-thin problem. On the one hand, we need an
account of significance that is thick enough to forbid an ‘‘anything goes’’
attitude toward significance. For example, no matter how intrinsically
compelling one might find the problem of (say) establishing the length of
one’s left thumbnail at every five second interval, that interest, by itself,
does not make that problem particularly significant. (That’s not to say, of
course, that we can’t imagine a fanciful scenario in which close thumbnail
monitoring is a highly significant problem. But for most of us most of the
time, it’s not.) So we need an account of significance that is thick enough
to yield the result that a problem might be relatively insignificant even if
someone has a powerful subjective desire to tackle it. But on the other
hand, we need an account of significance that is thin enough to license
some dramatic interpersonal differences in what problems are significant.
For example, establishing whether the short-tailed shrew is the smallest
North American mammal with poisonous saliva might be a very significant
problem to a biologist whose professional reputation depends on her
knowledge of North American shrews. For most of the rest of us, however,
this is not an especially significant problem. So the thick-thin problem is
that the constraints on significance must allow for some substantive interpersonal
and interinstitutional differences about what problems are
significant without licensing an ‘‘anything goes’’ subjectivism.
Our view holds that the significance of a problem for S is a function of
the weight of the objective reasons S has for devoting resources to solving that
problem. This view assumes that we have objective reasons of various sorts
for action and that we can weigh these reasons against one another. We are
aware that these are bold and controversial assumptions. But given our
broadly Aristotelian approach to epistemology, we don’t think it’s possible to think fully and clearly about epistemology without also bringing in views
about other normative domains. So we will unabashedly take the assumption
that there are objective reasons for action—they stand regardless of
whether a subject recognizes them or (after reflection) accepts them as legitimate
(see Railton 1986; Boyd 1988). This reason-based account of significance
has the resources to handle the thick-thin problem. Some reasons
(such as those that arise from basic moral obligations) are universal. They
place firm restrictions on the sort of problems that can be significant. But
other reasons (such as those that arise from one’s social or professional
obligations) might be quite different for different people. These sorts of
reasons permit fairly dramatic differences in the sorts of problems that
different people might find significant.
The two most intuitively compelling kinds of objective reasons are
also the most important for our purposes. We take it that people have
objective moral reasons and objective prudential reasons for action. So
consider the reasoning problem faced by a doctor who is diagnosing
whether a patient has a serious disease on the basis of various test results.
This problem is highly significant for the doctor because she has objective
moral and prudential reasons for reasoning very carefully and well about
such a problem. These reasons are objective because they stand regardless
of whether she recognizes them or, upon reflection, accepts them. This is
particularly plausible in a case (like this one) in which the objective reasons
the doctor has for devoting resources to this problem are connected
(at least in part) to the consequences of her reasoning. Accurately diagnosing
a patient is a high-stakes proposition, both for the patient and for
the doctor. The potential costs of an inaccurate diagnosis are huge, as are
the potential benefits of an accurate diagnosis. When someone’s objective
reasons for tackling a problem are a function of the consequences of getting
or not getting an accurate result, it’s intuitively plausible that these
reasons stand even if the doctor doesn’t recognize or care about them. And
since these reasons are weighty, the problem is significant for the doctor
(not to mention her patient!).
It would be a mistake, however, to think that all the objective reasons
we could have for action involve only consequences. Individuals can have
reasons for tackling certain problems because they have pursued or accepted
the moral and professional duties (along with the attendant benefits)
of certain social or professional roles. For example, regardless of the
consequences, doctors have a duty (a moral and professional duty) to
devote resources to thinking clearly about their patients; police officers
have a duty to devote resources to thinking clearly about solving and preventing crime; university professors have a duty to devote resources to
thinking clearly about how to effectively teach their students—and some
have a duty to devote resources to thinking clearly about short-tailed
shrews or the mind-body problem.
Objective reasons include more than moral, prudential, or social-role
sorts of reasons. For example, people can have legitimate (and objective)
epistemic reasons for tackling a certain problem. We take it that discovering
the truth about the basic physical or social structure of the world is
intrinsically valuable. So even if we can’t be sure that it will lead to any
practical results, the physicists at CERN and Fermilab have epistemic
reasons (beyond their prudential reasons) for spending cognitive resources
on trying to discover the Higgs boson.
Let’s consider three worries about this reason-based account of significance.
The first worry concerns insignificant problems. For those of us
who have no legitimate reasons and no personal interest in constantly
monitoring our fingernail length or the number of Goodyear Blimps in
our field of vision, our view is that such problems are insignificant. But the
thick-thin problem arises when we ask: What about the subject who is
interested in tackling such navel-gazing reasoning problems? Doesn’t this
interest, by itself, give the subject some objective reason to tackle the problem?
Yes. We can grant the following general principle: If S desires to do X,
that gives S some (objective) reason to do X. But notice, this principle is
silent about the strength of this objective reason. On the assumption that S
has no other reasons—moral, prudential, epistemic, aesthetic, etc.—to
pursue this problem, it would seem that this problem, while not completely
insignificant, is of very, very little significance. If S is devoting
resources to monitoring his fingernail length rather than (say) the safety
of his child, this is a pathology that goes well beyond concerns with
poor reasoning. But on our view, devoting resources to a barely significant
problem instead of a significant problem is a case of poor reasoning—and
possibly worse.
A second worry about our view concerns ‘‘lost cause’’ problems. Consider
the problem of whether the current health care system in the U.S. is
just and efficient. Given our health care system’s barriers to participatory
influence, it might be that an individual has no power to change or help
change the system. Is this apparently ‘‘lost cause’’ a significant problem for
the person? If the person is interested in the problem, then (as in the
navel-gazing cases) that makes the problem at least a little bit significant.
But on what grounds might it be more than barely significant? One might
have prudential reasons to think about the health care system in order to understand it well enough to make good use of it. But let’s suppose this
consideration isn’t relevant to the reasoner. There are still two classes of
objective reason that could make ‘‘lost cause’’ problems significant. First,
we have a civic or political duty to be well informed on important topics
of the day (i.e., topics that are important to people’s well-being). How
does this duty work? The only way positive change can occur in a democracy
is if those with minority opinions don’t give up when they don’t
foresee beneficial changes coming in the short term. But the possibility of
positive change also requires that those who aren’t informed on important
subjects pay attention to them. This seems to us to be the basis of the civic
or political duty that makes thinking about the moral status of our society’s
institutions significant—even when we have vanishingly small
prospects for changing them. Another set of objective reasons that might
ground the significance of these ‘‘lost causes’’ involves considerations of
virtue. Following up on our generally Aristotelian approach to epistemology,
it seems plausible to suppose that there is a nonaccidental connection
between being an excellent reasoner and an excellent person. We
venture to guess (and we take this to be a testable assumption) that
spending resources thinking seriously about whether one’s society is just is
a feature of an excellent character and a flourishing life. Indeed, it’s not
too much of an overstatement to say that Western philosophy originated,
in the person of Socrates, in precisely this kind of serious reflection on
‘‘lost causes.’’
The third worry about our view concerns ‘‘negatively’’ significant
reasoning problems. Reasoners may have objective reasons for not devoting
resources to particular sorts of problem. For example, we suspect that
a psychologically healthy person will not regularly calculate and recalculate
what are his narrow self-interests—particularly if such constant recalculation
alienates him from activities he finds satisfying and casts his friends
as potential competitors. We take it that this can be a ‘‘negatively’’ significant
reasoning problem. This is a separate category from significant
and insignificant problems. ‘‘Negatively’’ significant problems are those for
which one has positive reason (not based on opportunity costs) to avoid.
We have discussed (in chapter 3) some of the counterintuitive findings of
‘‘hedonic psychology.’’ These findings suggest that focusing cognitive
resources on certain kinds of problem are likely to lead to frustration and
loss of happiness. To take one perhaps unsurprising example, people who
pursue money in the belief that it will increase their happiness express
greater frustration than their peers (Myers 2000). We suspect (although
we have only anecdotal evidence for this hypothesis) that ‘‘philosophy graduate student disease’’ (the constant monitoring of one’s actual or
perceived ‘‘smartness’’ status) involves the devotion of resources to a negatively
significant problem.
Our general account of epistemic significance resides, ultimately, in
judgments about what conduces to human well-being. If we view humans
as part of the natural order, then the conditions that contribute to human
well-being are open to scientific investigation. Some might worry that
these conditions are too variable to be studied systematically and generalized
about scientifically. There is, however, reason for optimism. While
the conditions of human well-being may be tied to norms that differ
across individuals and across cultures, the challenges of generalizing across
varied groups and individuals have been surmounted in other sciences,
such as developmental and evolutionary biology. There is ample empirical
evidence that the basic conditions of human well-being involve health,
deep social attachments, personal security, and the pursuit of significant
projects (Diener and Seligman 2002; Myers 2000). Just as certain personality
types engage in activities that make them less happy, there are
economic, social, and political institutions that have a systematic and
adjustable influence on people’s happiness (Diener 2000; Diener and Oishi
2000; Frey and Stutzer 2002; Lane 2000). For example, income, unemployment,
and inflation all have marked and sustained influences on happiness
(Frey and Stutzer 2002). Interestingly, all three partly result from institutional
planning—of tax policy, monetary policy, and available services—
and so can be regulated to a certain extent by government action. To
continue the theme, certain objective economic conditions, such as destitution,
are incompatible with well-being (Dasgupta 1993). These empirical
findings about the conditions that influence happiness and welfare set
limits on what can count as a significant problem. Some of the most
significant problems we face concern how to renovate maladaptive social
institutions that undermine our happiness and well-being, and how to
implement new social, political, and economic institutions and procedures
that are most likely to promote well-being and control the sources of
avoidable unhappiness.