2. Circularity worries
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94
You begin your epistemological investigations with empirical findings, i.e.,
some findings of Ameliorative Psychology. Any epistemological project that
begins with empirical findings raises a circularity objection. We can put it in
the form of a dilemma. Why did you begin your epistemological investigations
with these particular empirical findings? In particular, do you have good
reasons for believing them? If so, you are presupposing epistemological
principles before you begin your epistemological investigations. And this is
viciously circular. If not, if you don’t have good reasons for believing the
empirical findings on which your epistemological theory is based, then how
can you defend this book with a straight face?
Your theory, Strategic Reliabilism, raises a particularly dramatic form of
this circularity objection. Chapter 1 says that a good epistemological theory
doesn’t just mimic the findings of Ameliorative Psychology, and chapter 8
employs your theory to resolve disputes in Ameliorative Psychology. But when
you constructed your epistemological theory in the first part of the book, it
could not have been ‘‘informed’’ by the instances of Ameliorative Psychology
you argue are mistaken in chapter 8. So you must have been making decisions
about which instances of Ameliorative Psychology are good and which are
not-so-good in the construction of your theory. If so, you must have been
presupposing epistemological principles in deciding which empirical findings
to accept, and these empirical findings informed your normative theory,
which in turn justified those very empirical findings. Again, isn’t this viciously
circular?
In doing any sort of science, including physics, biology or Ameliorative
Psychology, scientists bring substantive normative assumptions to bear in
deciding what theories are good or true or worthy of pursuit. But this
point is not restricted to scientists. Anyone who provides reasons of any
kind in support of any kind of doctrine is up to their ears in substantive
epistemological assumptions. And that includes epistemologists. We
challenge the proponent of the circularity objection to show us the epistemological
theory that begins without relying on any judgment that is
informed by some kind of substantive epistemological assumption. Such
an epistemology would not begin by assuming, for example, that we have
beliefs (for that assumes that we have good reason to reject eliminativism,
the view that propositional attitudes don’t exist). It would not begin by
assuming that certain ways of reasoning about normative, epistemic
matters are superior to others (for that would require epistemological assumptions about how we ought to reason about epistemology). The circularity
objection seems to require that we begin construction of an epistemological
theory without making any normative, epistemic assumptions
whatsoever. And that’s a fool’s errand.
I’m certainly not insisting that epistemology proceed without any normative
assumptions whatsoever. Rather, our epistemological investigations should be
based on some privileged class of normative, epistemic assumptions. These are
the epistemological assumptions of a priori epistemology.
The circularity objection seems to leave us with a choice. But it is not a
choice between beginning our epistemological theorizing with substantive
epistemological assumptions or without substantive epistemological assumptions.
It is a choice between beginning our epistemological theorizing
with the epistemological assumptions of a priori epistemology (whatever
they may be) or the epistemological assumptions of science (whatever they
may be). On what grounds do we make this choice? It is certainly not
based on the relative success of a priori epistemology (or a priori philosophy
in general) over science in coming up with theories that are
fruitful and can lay some claim to being true. In fact, if we were to use any
reasonable version of the major philosophical theories of justification
(reliabilism, coherentism or foundationalism) to assess itself and our best
scientific theories, each would surely return the verdict that our best scientific
theories are far more justified than the epistemological theory. If
this is right, why not embrace the normative presuppositions of the theories
that all parties to this debate agree are superior?
But the epistemological assumptions of a priori epistemology are superior to
those of naturalistic epistemology. The reason is that the former are a subset
of the latter. Naturalists give themselves permission to reason about a priori
matters and a posteriori matters when doing epistemology; a priori epistemologists
permit only the former. Therefore, the epistemological assumptions
of a priori epistemology are safer and more likely to be true.
Even if we grant this point, why is safer better? Epistemologists have a
choice about what sorts of epistemic assumptions to adopt when doing
epistemology. We suspect that many epistemologists haven’t explicitly
made a choice about this. They have simply absorbed a tradition still
haunted by Descartes and the neurotic abhorrence of error. But error isn’t
the only enemy—or even the greatest enemy—in life, or in philosophy. Our approach does risk error by taking Ameliorative Psychology seriously.
But what is the risk of constructing an epistemological theory in happy
ignorance of such findings—findings that have a half-century’s worth of
empirical support? Two possible risks stand out. First, if our a priori theories
contradict such findings, we risk error. Second, if our a priori
theories imply nothing very specific about such findings, we risk irrelevance.
And if the proponent of a priori epistemology insists that his approach
does not carry these risks, we wonder: How on earth could he
possibly be so sure? Any choice we make about where to begin our epistemological
investigations carries risk of some kind. From our perspective,
there are moral, political and pragmatic grounds for doing what we can to
make sure that our epistemological theory is informed by our best scientific
findings about how we can reason better about significant matters
(for an interesting discussion of failures to meet this standard in moral
reasoning, see Sunstein 2003). After all, when people fail to heed the advice
offered by Ameliorative Psychology about how best to reason about diagnosing
disease or predicting violence, people die. Why build an epistemological
theory that risks endorsing or not condemning such epistemic
practices?
Let’s end our thoughts about the circularity objection by considering
why the objection is supposed to be damning. The problem, presumably,
is that the epistemological assumptions the naturalist begins with will
ultimately be vindicated by the naturalist’s epistemological theory. In this
way, the naturalist’s epistemology is self-justifying and so viciously circular.
There are three points to make about the viciousness contention.
First, it can be made equally well against any epistemological method or
theory, no matter how pristinely a priori. After all, the a priori epistemologist
must begin her investigations with epistemological assumptions
of some sort. Presumably, these assumptions will be vindicated by her
epistemological theory. So a priori epistemologies are just as viciously
circular as naturalistic epistemologies. Second, it is hard to see how the
viciousness claim can be reasonably made with any confidence (including
the viciousness claim we just made against a priori epistemology). After
all, no one has a clear and compelling account of what epistemological
assumptions are being presupposed by epistemologists, naturalists or otherwise.
Without knowing this, how can anyone be sure that the prescriptions
coming out of such theories will be the same as those that went in?
And how can anyone be sure that the prescriptions coming out of such
theories will vindicate those that went in? Third, suppose that Strategic
Reliabilism really does end up vindicating the epistemological assumptions of science. Would that mean that the naturalistic method was vicious? Not
unless there was something necessary or inevitable about this outcome. But
let’s stop to consider what it would be for Strategic Reliabilism to vindicate
every epistemological assumption of all of our best scientific theories.
This would mean that the methods and substance of every scientific theory
and discipline presuppose epistemological principles that yield prescriptive
judgments that are identical to those of Strategic Reliabilism. As we’ve
already admitted, we have no idea whether this sort of vindication is in the
offing (although we have serious reservations). But we are most eager to
see this case made by the proponent of the circularity objection. We are
confident that after articulating the epistemological assumptions of (say)
nuclear physics, cognitive psychology and evolutionary biology, and then
determining if these assumptions are vindicated by Strategic Reliabilism,
our overwhelmed philosopher will grant that there is nothing inevitable
about the outcome. And let’s suppose that after decades of work, the
proponent of the circularity objection finds—to everyone’s surprise—that
Strategic Reliabilism does vindicate all the epistemological assumptions of
our best science. Given that this result was not inevitable, we would have
no need to take this as an objection. We could simply conclude that science
makes even more terrific epistemological presuppositions than we thought.
You begin your epistemological investigations with empirical findings, i.e.,
some findings of Ameliorative Psychology. Any epistemological project that
begins with empirical findings raises a circularity objection. We can put it in
the form of a dilemma. Why did you begin your epistemological investigations
with these particular empirical findings? In particular, do you have good
reasons for believing them? If so, you are presupposing epistemological
principles before you begin your epistemological investigations. And this is
viciously circular. If not, if you don’t have good reasons for believing the
empirical findings on which your epistemological theory is based, then how
can you defend this book with a straight face?
Your theory, Strategic Reliabilism, raises a particularly dramatic form of
this circularity objection. Chapter 1 says that a good epistemological theory
doesn’t just mimic the findings of Ameliorative Psychology, and chapter 8
employs your theory to resolve disputes in Ameliorative Psychology. But when
you constructed your epistemological theory in the first part of the book, it
could not have been ‘‘informed’’ by the instances of Ameliorative Psychology
you argue are mistaken in chapter 8. So you must have been making decisions
about which instances of Ameliorative Psychology are good and which are
not-so-good in the construction of your theory. If so, you must have been
presupposing epistemological principles in deciding which empirical findings
to accept, and these empirical findings informed your normative theory,
which in turn justified those very empirical findings. Again, isn’t this viciously
circular?
In doing any sort of science, including physics, biology or Ameliorative
Psychology, scientists bring substantive normative assumptions to bear in
deciding what theories are good or true or worthy of pursuit. But this
point is not restricted to scientists. Anyone who provides reasons of any
kind in support of any kind of doctrine is up to their ears in substantive
epistemological assumptions. And that includes epistemologists. We
challenge the proponent of the circularity objection to show us the epistemological
theory that begins without relying on any judgment that is
informed by some kind of substantive epistemological assumption. Such
an epistemology would not begin by assuming, for example, that we have
beliefs (for that assumes that we have good reason to reject eliminativism,
the view that propositional attitudes don’t exist). It would not begin by
assuming that certain ways of reasoning about normative, epistemic
matters are superior to others (for that would require epistemological assumptions about how we ought to reason about epistemology). The circularity
objection seems to require that we begin construction of an epistemological
theory without making any normative, epistemic assumptions
whatsoever. And that’s a fool’s errand.
I’m certainly not insisting that epistemology proceed without any normative
assumptions whatsoever. Rather, our epistemological investigations should be
based on some privileged class of normative, epistemic assumptions. These are
the epistemological assumptions of a priori epistemology.
The circularity objection seems to leave us with a choice. But it is not a
choice between beginning our epistemological theorizing with substantive
epistemological assumptions or without substantive epistemological assumptions.
It is a choice between beginning our epistemological theorizing
with the epistemological assumptions of a priori epistemology (whatever
they may be) or the epistemological assumptions of science (whatever they
may be). On what grounds do we make this choice? It is certainly not
based on the relative success of a priori epistemology (or a priori philosophy
in general) over science in coming up with theories that are
fruitful and can lay some claim to being true. In fact, if we were to use any
reasonable version of the major philosophical theories of justification
(reliabilism, coherentism or foundationalism) to assess itself and our best
scientific theories, each would surely return the verdict that our best scientific
theories are far more justified than the epistemological theory. If
this is right, why not embrace the normative presuppositions of the theories
that all parties to this debate agree are superior?
But the epistemological assumptions of a priori epistemology are superior to
those of naturalistic epistemology. The reason is that the former are a subset
of the latter. Naturalists give themselves permission to reason about a priori
matters and a posteriori matters when doing epistemology; a priori epistemologists
permit only the former. Therefore, the epistemological assumptions
of a priori epistemology are safer and more likely to be true.
Even if we grant this point, why is safer better? Epistemologists have a
choice about what sorts of epistemic assumptions to adopt when doing
epistemology. We suspect that many epistemologists haven’t explicitly
made a choice about this. They have simply absorbed a tradition still
haunted by Descartes and the neurotic abhorrence of error. But error isn’t
the only enemy—or even the greatest enemy—in life, or in philosophy. Our approach does risk error by taking Ameliorative Psychology seriously.
But what is the risk of constructing an epistemological theory in happy
ignorance of such findings—findings that have a half-century’s worth of
empirical support? Two possible risks stand out. First, if our a priori theories
contradict such findings, we risk error. Second, if our a priori
theories imply nothing very specific about such findings, we risk irrelevance.
And if the proponent of a priori epistemology insists that his approach
does not carry these risks, we wonder: How on earth could he
possibly be so sure? Any choice we make about where to begin our epistemological
investigations carries risk of some kind. From our perspective,
there are moral, political and pragmatic grounds for doing what we can to
make sure that our epistemological theory is informed by our best scientific
findings about how we can reason better about significant matters
(for an interesting discussion of failures to meet this standard in moral
reasoning, see Sunstein 2003). After all, when people fail to heed the advice
offered by Ameliorative Psychology about how best to reason about diagnosing
disease or predicting violence, people die. Why build an epistemological
theory that risks endorsing or not condemning such epistemic
practices?
Let’s end our thoughts about the circularity objection by considering
why the objection is supposed to be damning. The problem, presumably,
is that the epistemological assumptions the naturalist begins with will
ultimately be vindicated by the naturalist’s epistemological theory. In this
way, the naturalist’s epistemology is self-justifying and so viciously circular.
There are three points to make about the viciousness contention.
First, it can be made equally well against any epistemological method or
theory, no matter how pristinely a priori. After all, the a priori epistemologist
must begin her investigations with epistemological assumptions
of some sort. Presumably, these assumptions will be vindicated by her
epistemological theory. So a priori epistemologies are just as viciously
circular as naturalistic epistemologies. Second, it is hard to see how the
viciousness claim can be reasonably made with any confidence (including
the viciousness claim we just made against a priori epistemology). After
all, no one has a clear and compelling account of what epistemological
assumptions are being presupposed by epistemologists, naturalists or otherwise.
Without knowing this, how can anyone be sure that the prescriptions
coming out of such theories will be the same as those that went in?
And how can anyone be sure that the prescriptions coming out of such
theories will vindicate those that went in? Third, suppose that Strategic
Reliabilism really does end up vindicating the epistemological assumptions of science. Would that mean that the naturalistic method was vicious? Not
unless there was something necessary or inevitable about this outcome. But
let’s stop to consider what it would be for Strategic Reliabilism to vindicate
every epistemological assumption of all of our best scientific theories.
This would mean that the methods and substance of every scientific theory
and discipline presuppose epistemological principles that yield prescriptive
judgments that are identical to those of Strategic Reliabilism. As we’ve
already admitted, we have no idea whether this sort of vindication is in the
offing (although we have serious reservations). But we are most eager to
see this case made by the proponent of the circularity objection. We are
confident that after articulating the epistemological assumptions of (say)
nuclear physics, cognitive psychology and evolutionary biology, and then
determining if these assumptions are vindicated by Strategic Reliabilism,
our overwhelmed philosopher will grant that there is nothing inevitable
about the outcome. And let’s suppose that after decades of work, the
proponent of the circularity objection finds—to everyone’s surprise—that
Strategic Reliabilism does vindicate all the epistemological assumptions of
our best science. Given that this result was not inevitable, we would have
no need to take this as an objection. We could simply conclude that science
makes even more terrific epistemological presuppositions than we thought.