4.1. Diagnosing the broken leg problem
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94
The broken leg problem arises when a reasoning strategy that has been
proven reliable on a particular class of problems is applied to a problem
that is thought (rightly or wrongly) to be outside the range of problems for
which the strategy is known to be reliable. For example, the VRAG (Violence
Risk Appraisal Guide) test for violent recidivism was developed
primarily as the result of research done on a population of violent Canadian
psychiatric patients at the Oak Ridge Division of the Penetanguishene
Mental Health Care Center (Quinsey et al. 1998, xi). When using the VRAG,
one might reasonably wonder whether it is reliable on different subpopulations,
such as non-psychiatric patients or criminals in the U.S. (In both
cases, it is.) One way to pose the broken leg problem is to ask: Under what
conditions is it reasonable to defect from a reasoning strategy that has been
shown to be reliable for a particular class of problems?
The broken leg problem is a serious and pressing issue for any theory
that embraces the findings of Ameliorative Psychology. On the one hand,
it is absurd to suppose that one should never defect from a successful SPR.
On the other hand, people have a hard time avoiding the temptations of
defection. And excessive defection undermines reliability. After all, whenever
an SPR is more reliable than human judgment and the expert and the
SPR disagree, the SPR is more likely to be correct. In the long run, reliability
is reduced if one insists upon consistently replacing more reliable
reasoning strategies with less reliable reasoning strategies.
This intuitively powerful argument has been confirmed a number of
times in the laboratory. There are a number of studies in which subjects are given SPRs and then are permitted to selectively defect from them (i.e.,
override them), sometimes after having been told that the SPR by itself has
been shown to be more reliable than experts. Typically, subjects find more
broken leg examples than there really are. As a result, the experts predict
less reliably than they would have if they’d just used the SPR (Goldberg
1968, Sawyer 1966, Leli and Filskov 1984). (Interestingly, it doesn’t usually
seem to matter whether the subjects are experts or not.) Selective defection
strategies generally have a poor track record (except when the defectors
have expertise in a theory with significant predictive success).
The broken leg problem and the failure of selective defection strategies
suggest that any epistemic theory that hopes to take full advantage of
the prescriptive power of Ameliorative Psychology must do more than put
forward and recommend reliable SPRs. It must include a psychological
theory of human judgment that can anticipate the difficulties we will have
implementing the best available reasoning strategies. It is an unfortunate
fact about humans that we are too often tempted to defect from successful
SPRs. A normative theory with prescriptive force needs to predict the ways
in which we are likely to deviate from excellent reasoning and perhaps
provide methods of preventing such unfortunate deviations. Of course, we
don’t pretend to have such a theory; accordingly, our discussion of this
matter will be tentative and programmatic. But we take this to be a prime
example of how a reason-guiding epistemology will essentially depend on,
and be informed by, a mature empirical psychology.
The broken leg problem arises when a reasoning strategy that has been
proven reliable on a particular class of problems is applied to a problem
that is thought (rightly or wrongly) to be outside the range of problems for
which the strategy is known to be reliable. For example, the VRAG (Violence
Risk Appraisal Guide) test for violent recidivism was developed
primarily as the result of research done on a population of violent Canadian
psychiatric patients at the Oak Ridge Division of the Penetanguishene
Mental Health Care Center (Quinsey et al. 1998, xi). When using the VRAG,
one might reasonably wonder whether it is reliable on different subpopulations,
such as non-psychiatric patients or criminals in the U.S. (In both
cases, it is.) One way to pose the broken leg problem is to ask: Under what
conditions is it reasonable to defect from a reasoning strategy that has been
shown to be reliable for a particular class of problems?
The broken leg problem is a serious and pressing issue for any theory
that embraces the findings of Ameliorative Psychology. On the one hand,
it is absurd to suppose that one should never defect from a successful SPR.
On the other hand, people have a hard time avoiding the temptations of
defection. And excessive defection undermines reliability. After all, whenever
an SPR is more reliable than human judgment and the expert and the
SPR disagree, the SPR is more likely to be correct. In the long run, reliability
is reduced if one insists upon consistently replacing more reliable
reasoning strategies with less reliable reasoning strategies.
This intuitively powerful argument has been confirmed a number of
times in the laboratory. There are a number of studies in which subjects are given SPRs and then are permitted to selectively defect from them (i.e.,
override them), sometimes after having been told that the SPR by itself has
been shown to be more reliable than experts. Typically, subjects find more
broken leg examples than there really are. As a result, the experts predict
less reliably than they would have if they’d just used the SPR (Goldberg
1968, Sawyer 1966, Leli and Filskov 1984). (Interestingly, it doesn’t usually
seem to matter whether the subjects are experts or not.) Selective defection
strategies generally have a poor track record (except when the defectors
have expertise in a theory with significant predictive success).
The broken leg problem and the failure of selective defection strategies
suggest that any epistemic theory that hopes to take full advantage of
the prescriptive power of Ameliorative Psychology must do more than put
forward and recommend reliable SPRs. It must include a psychological
theory of human judgment that can anticipate the difficulties we will have
implementing the best available reasoning strategies. It is an unfortunate
fact about humans that we are too often tempted to defect from successful
SPRs. A normative theory with prescriptive force needs to predict the ways
in which we are likely to deviate from excellent reasoning and perhaps
provide methods of preventing such unfortunate deviations. Of course, we
don’t pretend to have such a theory; accordingly, our discussion of this
matter will be tentative and programmatic. But we take this to be a prime
example of how a reason-guiding epistemology will essentially depend on,
and be informed by, a mature empirical psychology.