8 Putting Epistemology into Practice: Normative Disputes in Psychology
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94
In previous chapters, we have introduced a number of experimental
findings that purport to demonstrate deep and systematic failures of
human reasoning. These findings include base rate neglect, covariation
illusions, the overconfidence bias, the hindsight bias, and the self-serving
bias (e.g., the Lake Wobegon Effect). These findings are associated with
the heuristics and biases (HB) program, championed in the groundbreaking
work of Kahneman and Tversky, and influential in nearly every
area of cognitive and social psychology, as well as in affiliated disciplines
(Gilovich, Griffin, and Kahneman 2002). Other examples of biases found
by proponents of the HB program include regression neglect, the conjunction
fallacy, and the fundamental attribution error (Nisbett and Ross
1980). Unlike Ameliorative Psychology, the HB program has received a
good deal of attention from philosophers (e.g., Cohen 1981, Stich 1985,
1990, Kornblith 1992, Stein 1996, Pollock and Cruz 1999).
Why do proponents of the HB program focus on people’s systematic
reasoning errors? Kahneman and Tversky offer three reasons:
First, they expose some of our intellectual limitations and suggest ways of
improving the quality of our thinking. Second, errors and biases often reveal
the psychological processes and the heuristic procedures that govern
judgment and inference. Third, mistakes and fallacies help the mapping of
human intuitions by indicating which principles of statistics or logic are
non-intuitive or counter-intuitive. (Kahneman and Tversky 1982, 494)
While Kahneman and Tversky are reasonably cautious in their overall
assessment of human reasoning, others have drawn fairly harsh pessimistic
conclusions. In an oft-quoted passage, Nisbett and Borgida (1975, 935)
claim that the reasoning errors uncovered by the HB program have ‘‘bleak
implications’’ for human rationality (see also Piattelli-Palmarini 1994).
These pessimistic conclusions have been repeatedly challenged (see, e.g.,
Cohen 1981, Lopes 1991, Gigerenzer 1991, 1996).
One line of attack against the ‘‘bleak implications’’ view of human
rationality is to argue that it is not the subjects who are making the
mistakes in solving the HB problem-tasks, it is the psychologists. Our goal
in this chapter is to consider a number of these reject-the-norm arguments
(Stein 1996, 239). A reject-the-norm argument purports to show that the
proponents of the HB program are applying the wrong inference rules,
and so the wrong norms, to the problem-tasks. As a result, people’s performance
on the HB problems is not evidence of any kind of irrationality
or poor reasoning among lay reasoners (Stein 1996, 239– 42).
Philosophers and psychologists who adopt the reject-the-norm strategy
have offered a number of different arguments for their conclusion. We
will not canvass all of these arguments here. Instead, we will focus only on
two instances of what we will call conceptual reject-the-norm arguments.
The premises of such arguments do not depend on any empirical facts
about reasoners or their situations. Consider a subject who has neglected
the base rate and so has reasoned poorly, according to proponents of the
HB program. One might argue that the subject has understood the problem
differently than was intended by the psychologists; and given that
understanding, her answer was not an error. This is an empirical rejectthe-
norm argument, since it depends essentially on how subjects as a matter
of fact understand the problem. Kahneman and Tversky have recognized
the legitimacy of this kind of empirical reject-the-norm argument.
[N]ot every response that appears to contradict an established fact or an
accepted rule is a judgmental error. The contradiction could also arise from
the subject’s misunderstanding of the question or from the investigator’s
misinterpretation of the answer. The description of a particular response as
an error of judgment therefore involves assumptions about the communication
between the experimenter and the subject. . . . The student of judgment
should avoid overly strict interpretations, which treat reasonable
answers as errors, as well as overly charitable interpretations, which attempt
to rationalize every response. (Kahneman and Tversky 1982, 493–94)
Since we have nothing particularly new to add to the empirical findings of
research on judgment and decision making, we will avoid discussion of
empirical reject-the-norm arguments. Our focus will be on those rejectthe-
norm arguments that purport to derive normative results about reasoners
tackling the HB problems without attending to the details of how
they’re actually reasoning.
In previous chapters, we have introduced a number of experimental
findings that purport to demonstrate deep and systematic failures of
human reasoning. These findings include base rate neglect, covariation
illusions, the overconfidence bias, the hindsight bias, and the self-serving
bias (e.g., the Lake Wobegon Effect). These findings are associated with
the heuristics and biases (HB) program, championed in the groundbreaking
work of Kahneman and Tversky, and influential in nearly every
area of cognitive and social psychology, as well as in affiliated disciplines
(Gilovich, Griffin, and Kahneman 2002). Other examples of biases found
by proponents of the HB program include regression neglect, the conjunction
fallacy, and the fundamental attribution error (Nisbett and Ross
1980). Unlike Ameliorative Psychology, the HB program has received a
good deal of attention from philosophers (e.g., Cohen 1981, Stich 1985,
1990, Kornblith 1992, Stein 1996, Pollock and Cruz 1999).
Why do proponents of the HB program focus on people’s systematic
reasoning errors? Kahneman and Tversky offer three reasons:
First, they expose some of our intellectual limitations and suggest ways of
improving the quality of our thinking. Second, errors and biases often reveal
the psychological processes and the heuristic procedures that govern
judgment and inference. Third, mistakes and fallacies help the mapping of
human intuitions by indicating which principles of statistics or logic are
non-intuitive or counter-intuitive. (Kahneman and Tversky 1982, 494)
While Kahneman and Tversky are reasonably cautious in their overall
assessment of human reasoning, others have drawn fairly harsh pessimistic
conclusions. In an oft-quoted passage, Nisbett and Borgida (1975, 935)
claim that the reasoning errors uncovered by the HB program have ‘‘bleak
implications’’ for human rationality (see also Piattelli-Palmarini 1994).
These pessimistic conclusions have been repeatedly challenged (see, e.g.,
Cohen 1981, Lopes 1991, Gigerenzer 1991, 1996).
One line of attack against the ‘‘bleak implications’’ view of human
rationality is to argue that it is not the subjects who are making the
mistakes in solving the HB problem-tasks, it is the psychologists. Our goal
in this chapter is to consider a number of these reject-the-norm arguments
(Stein 1996, 239). A reject-the-norm argument purports to show that the
proponents of the HB program are applying the wrong inference rules,
and so the wrong norms, to the problem-tasks. As a result, people’s performance
on the HB problems is not evidence of any kind of irrationality
or poor reasoning among lay reasoners (Stein 1996, 239– 42).
Philosophers and psychologists who adopt the reject-the-norm strategy
have offered a number of different arguments for their conclusion. We
will not canvass all of these arguments here. Instead, we will focus only on
two instances of what we will call conceptual reject-the-norm arguments.
The premises of such arguments do not depend on any empirical facts
about reasoners or their situations. Consider a subject who has neglected
the base rate and so has reasoned poorly, according to proponents of the
HB program. One might argue that the subject has understood the problem
differently than was intended by the psychologists; and given that
understanding, her answer was not an error. This is an empirical rejectthe-
norm argument, since it depends essentially on how subjects as a matter
of fact understand the problem. Kahneman and Tversky have recognized
the legitimacy of this kind of empirical reject-the-norm argument.
[N]ot every response that appears to contradict an established fact or an
accepted rule is a judgmental error. The contradiction could also arise from
the subject’s misunderstanding of the question or from the investigator’s
misinterpretation of the answer. The description of a particular response as
an error of judgment therefore involves assumptions about the communication
between the experimenter and the subject. . . . The student of judgment
should avoid overly strict interpretations, which treat reasonable
answers as errors, as well as overly charitable interpretations, which attempt
to rationalize every response. (Kahneman and Tversky 1982, 493–94)
Since we have nothing particularly new to add to the empirical findings of
research on judgment and decision making, we will avoid discussion of
empirical reject-the-norm arguments. Our focus will be on those rejectthe-
norm arguments that purport to derive normative results about reasoners
tackling the HB problems without attending to the details of how
they’re actually reasoning.