3. The structure of a healthy epistemological tradition
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94
On our approach to epistemology, a healthy epistemological tradition
must have three vigorous and interrelated components: theoretical, practical,
and social. The practical or applied component of epistemology is
an extension of what people do every day. Everyone who has ever thought
about how to tackle a particular reasoning problem has engaged in applied
epistemology. As is standard with an applied venture, some people do it
better than others. Ameliorative Psychology is the science of applied epistemology.
Much of the point of Ameliorative Psychology is to provide
advice that will help people reason better about the world.
The second component of a healthy epistemological tradition is theory.
We take theory and application to be mutually informing and supporting.
Theory is extracted from practice. One of the goals—and one of
the tests—of a theory of reasoning excellence is that it should be faithful to
the practice of Ameliorative Psychology. When conjoined with the descriptive
results of Ameliorative Psychology, the correct epistemological
theory should yield the recommendations of Ameliorative Psychology. One
of our primary goals in this book is to offer a theory that accurately depicts
the normative machinery that guides the prescriptions of Ameliorative
Psychology. But theory should do more than mimic. It should explain what
makes some reasoning strategies epistemically better than others; it should
also play a role in a full explanation for why good reasoning tends to lead to
good outcomes. (To see how our theory addresses these explanatory
challenges, see Appendix, section 8.) Further, a theory of reasoning excellence
should be able to be applied back to Ameliorative Psychology.
Practice informs theory; but good theory repays the kindness. When a
disagreement erupts in the applied domain, and that disagreement is at
bottom a theoretical one, a good theory should be able to clarify and, in
some cases at least, resolve the issues. In chapter 8, we will apply our theory
of reasoning excellence in an effort to resolve two disputes that have arisen
in Ameliorative Psychology.
We have suggested that the theoretical part of a healthy epistemological
tradition will be firmly connected to its applied components. As we
have already suggested, by this yardstick, the standard analytic approach to
epistemology does not seem to be a healthy tradition. As far as we have
been able to tell, the theoretical musings of analytic epistemologists have
not led to very much, if any, useful guidance about how people should
reason. We will argue eventually that this prescriptive impotence is a
natural consequence of the methods of Standard Analytic Epistemology. If
this is right, it is a shame. It is the normative, reason-guiding promise of
epistemology that makes it so much more than intellectual sport.
While a healthy epistemological tradition will provide useful reasoning
guidance, good advice we keep to ourselves is no advice at all. Ameliorative
Psychology is the science of applied epistemology, and theoretical epistemology
is theoretical Ameliorative Psychology (i.e., a theoretical science).
As with any science, it is important to think about what it would take for it
to be a well-ordered social system (Kitcher 2001). An important aspect of
epistemology’s social presence is how it communicates its practical recommendations
to the wider public. We don’t have any detailed picture
of what a socially well-ordered epistemology would look like. But we are
confident that it would have at least two features. First, in order to achieve
its ameliorative potential, epistemology should be organized so that it provides
a way to effectively communicate its established findings, particularly
its practical content, to a wide audience. Second, in order to minimize the
risk of promulgating harmful or mistaken findings, epistemology should
be organized so that whatever findings are communicated widely will have
passed rigorous examination and empirical testing.
On our approach to epistemology, a healthy epistemological tradition
must have three vigorous and interrelated components: theoretical, practical,
and social. The practical or applied component of epistemology is
an extension of what people do every day. Everyone who has ever thought
about how to tackle a particular reasoning problem has engaged in applied
epistemology. As is standard with an applied venture, some people do it
better than others. Ameliorative Psychology is the science of applied epistemology.
Much of the point of Ameliorative Psychology is to provide
advice that will help people reason better about the world.
The second component of a healthy epistemological tradition is theory.
We take theory and application to be mutually informing and supporting.
Theory is extracted from practice. One of the goals—and one of
the tests—of a theory of reasoning excellence is that it should be faithful to
the practice of Ameliorative Psychology. When conjoined with the descriptive
results of Ameliorative Psychology, the correct epistemological
theory should yield the recommendations of Ameliorative Psychology. One
of our primary goals in this book is to offer a theory that accurately depicts
the normative machinery that guides the prescriptions of Ameliorative
Psychology. But theory should do more than mimic. It should explain what
makes some reasoning strategies epistemically better than others; it should
also play a role in a full explanation for why good reasoning tends to lead to
good outcomes. (To see how our theory addresses these explanatory
challenges, see Appendix, section 8.) Further, a theory of reasoning excellence
should be able to be applied back to Ameliorative Psychology.
Practice informs theory; but good theory repays the kindness. When a
disagreement erupts in the applied domain, and that disagreement is at
bottom a theoretical one, a good theory should be able to clarify and, in
some cases at least, resolve the issues. In chapter 8, we will apply our theory
of reasoning excellence in an effort to resolve two disputes that have arisen
in Ameliorative Psychology.
We have suggested that the theoretical part of a healthy epistemological
tradition will be firmly connected to its applied components. As we
have already suggested, by this yardstick, the standard analytic approach to
epistemology does not seem to be a healthy tradition. As far as we have
been able to tell, the theoretical musings of analytic epistemologists have
not led to very much, if any, useful guidance about how people should
reason. We will argue eventually that this prescriptive impotence is a
natural consequence of the methods of Standard Analytic Epistemology. If
this is right, it is a shame. It is the normative, reason-guiding promise of
epistemology that makes it so much more than intellectual sport.
While a healthy epistemological tradition will provide useful reasoning
guidance, good advice we keep to ourselves is no advice at all. Ameliorative
Psychology is the science of applied epistemology, and theoretical epistemology
is theoretical Ameliorative Psychology (i.e., a theoretical science).
As with any science, it is important to think about what it would take for it
to be a well-ordered social system (Kitcher 2001). An important aspect of
epistemology’s social presence is how it communicates its practical recommendations
to the wider public. We don’t have any detailed picture
of what a socially well-ordered epistemology would look like. But we are
confident that it would have at least two features. First, in order to achieve
its ameliorative potential, epistemology should be organized so that it provides
a way to effectively communicate its established findings, particularly
its practical content, to a wide audience. Second, in order to minimize the
risk of promulgating harmful or mistaken findings, epistemology should
be organized so that whatever findings are communicated widely will have
passed rigorous examination and empirical testing.