TO THE PRINCIPLE OF CAUSALITY.
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 41 44 46 48 49
52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66
68 69 70 71 75 76 78 79 80 81 83
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101
102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 112 113 114 115 117 118
119 120 121 122 123 124 125 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135
138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148
In the second last section
(109) we vindicated a reasoned or philosophic certitude for the
belief that " there exists, distinct from the Ego, an external
domain of reality which appears as extended or material ". The
argument was based on the evidence furnished by direct intel
lectual scrutiny of the data of conscious external sense perception.
We have likewise shown that our intellectuul concept of " other-
1 op. dt., pp. 124-5.
4*
52 THE OR Y OF A NO W LEDGE
ness-from-the Ego" or "externality," derived from those data, is
objectively and really valid (105). We are therefore now in a
position to corroborate the conclusion of our argument by con
sidering our spontaneous interpretation of sense perception in the
light of a principle, the universal validity of which has likewise
been already established (65, 66, 93) the principle of causality.
Those supporters of realism l who in the present general context rely
mainly or exclusively on the argument from causality to establish the phil
osophical certitude of our knowledge of an external world, emphasize the
universal real validity of the concept of cause ; and consider the argument
peculiarly efficacious as against idealists. 2 But even though the concept is uni
versally applicable to contingent reality, and even if the idealist admits this,
the latter has still to be convinced that there is contingent reality beyond the
domain of the subjects consciousness? or beyond the reality of the Ego if
he recognizes a real Ego as subject and cause of conscious states. And of
this we can hope to convince him, if at all, only by proving to him that the
concept of " reality-other-than-the Ego," which he possesses in common with
us, is an objectively and really valid concept. But how can we prove that
it is ? Only by pointing out that the sensuously felt character of " extended
externality " in certain of our sense data can be seen by intellect to be the
source from which the concept is derived, and to be therefore for intellect
adequate objective evidence of the real validity of the concept (104, 105).
In other words, by the same line of reasoning, by the same sort of direct in
tellectual appeal to the characteristics of conscious sense data, as we have
employed in our main argument for the mind-independent existence of a
real non-self universe (109). It is because we believe that if realism cannot
be effectively vindicated, as against idealism, by that class of consideration,
neither can it be effectively vindicated, apart from such consideration, by the
principle of causality alone (cf. 105-6), it is for that reason we now bring for
ward the argument from causality merely as corroborative, and not in the first
place.
l Cf. JEANNIERE, op. cit., pp. 224-7, 382-92 ; MERCIER, op. cii., 140, pp. 384-9.
a cy. vol. i., 35, p. 134.
3 Kant, for instance, and English phenomenists, admit the validity of causality
(as understood by them in the sense of a provisionally, or an absolutely, necessary
sequence, respectively) as applied within the whole domain of empirical conscious
ness. And even when we have proved against Kant that it is validly applied in in
ferring an ultra-conscious cause of this whole domain, the principle itself will not
enable us to determine whether this latter cause is one or manifold. We prove it
to be manifold, to be in part the real Ego, and in part a whole pluralistic system
of realities external to and other than the real Ego (all alike themselves contingent,
and therefore implying a Supreme Uncaused First Cause), not by the principle of
causality alone, but only by the collateral use of another and distinct intellectual
concept, namely, that of real distinction or real otherness, a concept whose real
validity, as marking off the " Ego- or self-reality " from " rtow-S//-realities " (and
these latter from one another), must be independently established. We have shown
this concept, as applied to the distinction between the Ego and the non-Ego, to
be really valid because grounded in characteristics of the conscious sense data from
which it is derived (101-105).
VALIDITY OF SENSE PERCEPTION 53
We have already proved, as against Kant, 1 that the Ego,
through its conscious activities, apprehends itself as a reality ;
that Descartes, in emphasizing the absolutely indisputable char
acter of our knowledge of the real self in his principle, Cogito,
ergo sum, was only re-echoing the traditional teaching of scholas
ticism from the days of St. Augustine (29, 34). Now this self
reveals itself as consciously affected by what we may call an ever-
changing panorama of apprehended data or objects, namely, the
proper and common sensibles. Our conscious perceptions of
these data are contingent events. Therefore, by virtue of the
principles of sufficient reason and causality (64, 65,) these con
scious perceptions of data or objects have an adequate cause.
But such adequate cause cannot be the self, or anything in the
self or really constituting or appertaining to the self. Therefore
there must be, beyond and really distinct from the self, a mind-
independent reality which, co-operating with the consciously per
cipient self, will adequately account for the perceptions de facto
experienced by the latter. Hence there exists, distinct from the
self, and independent of perception, a reality which we call the
external, material universe. 2
Let us consider the steps in this argument. That the Ego
has conscious perceptions whereby data or objects " externally-
appearing," "extended," "coloured," "moving," "resisting,"
"sounding," etc., are presented in consciousness, is a fact ad
mitted by even the most extreme sceptics and subjectivists : as
also is the fact that these perceptions are contingent events, in the
sense that they are not self-explaining, that they come and go,
appear and disappear, begin to be and cease to be, and so call for
explanation or demand a cause. And the objective, real validity
of the principle of causality has been already established. Next,
the adequate cause of them cannot be the self. Why ? This
needs a little reflection.
The main reason is that we feel ourselves passive in experienc
ing such perceptions. Hence Kant recognizes that the empirical
content of perception is given tons from without, that to account
for our perceptions there is and must be a reality beyond and
independent of them, and of the self as empirically revealed
1 Cf, vol. 5., 97, 99, 100. Cf. infra, 134.
a Berkeley s alternative inference" Therefore there exists, distinct from and
independent of our minds, a cause of these conscious states, which cause is the
Divine Spirit " will be examined later, 123. Cf. JEANNIERE, op. cit., pp. 401-4.
5 4 THE OR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
in consciousness (50, 51, 74). Hence, too, Fichte claims that
epistemology must take as starting-point the fact that in the
content of consciousness there is, besides the mobile, subjectively
determined portion, another portion independent of subjective
contingencies and inseparable from what he describes as the
feeling of necessity} We feel ourselves passive, impressed, under
going impressions, in sense perception. That is, though the per
ceptions are ours, though it is we that elicit or exercise the
conscious, perceptive acts, still we feel them as not being wholly
determined by ourselves in regard to what they reveal to us. As
to the specific character of the various data or objects revealed
to us in perception (i.e. " quoad specificationem "), they appear to
arise or take place in us or to present this specific character to
us, independently of ourselves ; and therefore to have, as partial
cause of their concrete happening, some reality other than the
self. Reflection will confirm this spontaneous belief.
(1) It is not merely my will that determines these percep
tions. I cannot have them by merely willing to have them.
And as to what they are, when they happen, they are inde
pendent of my will. I cannot have the perceptions which
consist in "seeing Rome," or " hearing music," or " carrying a
weight," or " tasting sugar," or " inhaling the perfume of violets "
by merely wishing to have such perceptions. And on the other
hand, when I am in the condition in which I do actually ex
perience any such perception I cannot cease to experience it
merely by wishing it to cease.
(2) Nor is it my imagination that determines such percep
tions. There is the most marked and indisputable conscious
difference between the panorama of data or objects brought into
consciousness by the play of the imagination in fancies, day
dreams, reveries, etc., between what are called " mental images "
or " phantasmata," on the one hand, and the data or objects of
sense perception, 2 or what are rightly called percepts, on the other.
Psychologists and philosophers have minutely analysed and
abundantly illustrated these differences. 3 The former class of
data are largely under the control of the will : we can direct, con-
1 Fichte s Werke, i., 419, apud MKRCIER, op. cit., p. 385. To this " feeling of
necessity " belong the feelings of" extensity " and " externality ".
Including the perception of organic states, organic pleasure or pain, etc., in the
perceiver s own body.
1 Cf. BAI.MKS, Fundamental Philosophy, Book II., chap. iv.
VALIDITY OF SENSE PERCEPTION 55
trol, modify the order in which such images present themselves ;
we can separate, combine, rearrange the images as we please ; we
can thus " produce " or " construct " new data or objects from
the remembered materials of perception ; and the power of the
" productive imagination " is only limited by the range of those
materials and its own finiteness. The latter class, the percepts,
are, as we saw, beyond the control of the will : the order in
which they succeed each other is not consciously determined by
us, but is felt to be determined by something other than the
self. Moreover, the two classes of data have been distinguished
as "faint" or "weak," and " strong " or " vivid " states, or (as
Hume named them) "ideas" and "impressions," on account of
the superior definiteness, clarity and solidity of the percepts as
compared with the images. Finally, in experiencing the latter
we are conscious that we ourselves, by our own active exercise of
imagination, zxz producing (not ex inhilo, but from the remembered
data of perception) the flow or current of mental objects ; while
in experiencing the former we are rather conscious of passively
undergoing impressions made on us by something independent of
the conscious Ego.
(3) Nor is it my thought that determines such perceptions
or originates such data or objects. By thought the individual
self or Ego elaborates logical relations, judgments, systems of
knowledge, sciences, concerning the domain of perceived data ;
but it certainly does not produce or construct this domain.
(4) But perhaps the same Ego, which consciously perceives
these data, itself constructs or produces them by an internal, in
stinctive, unconsciously operating influence of its own nature?
Well, if it did, such influence would have no other claim than its
blind, unconscious character, to be described as an "instinct".
For the forms of energy we describe as " instincts " in sentient
beings follow fixed laws and are uniform and circumscribed in
their results. But there is nothing of this in the ever-changing
panorama of percepts which constitute the world of any indivi
dual perceiver s sense experience. Psychologists can with some
success explore and formulate the laws according to which "in
stincts " operate ; but who has ever dreamt of seeking or formu
lating laws according to which the world of each individual s
sense experience unfolds itself in the order, and with the qualities,
which actually characterize it ?
(5) But, dismissing the term " instinctive," may it not finally
56 THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE
be urged that, for all we know, it may be the real Ego ifself that
in some unconscious way, and by some unknown and unknowable
laws, produces this whole panorama of sense percepts which we
spontaneously and inevitably, but so far as reflecting reason
goes, unwarrantably believe to be a domain of reality other
than, and external to, the self, unwarrantably, since on this
possible hypothesis it would be but a phase or manifestation of
the real self? Perhaps, to use the picturesque words of Huxley, 1
"For any demonstration that can be given to the contrary
effect, the collection of perceptions which makes up our con
sciousness may be an orderly phantasmagoria, generated by the
Ego unfolding its successive scenes on the background of the
abyss of nothingness ; as a firework, which is but cunningly
arranged combustibles, grows from a spark into a corruscation,
and from a corruscation into figures and words and cascades of
devouring flames, and then vanishes into the darkness of night ".
The concession Huxley had just made to realism was that
" there may be a real something which is the cause of our experi
ence ". J And this something he now declares to be a hypo
thetical and unknowable real Ego, in the sceptical spirit of
Hume. Kant, as we have seen, so far from refuting this scepticism
which was the avowed object of his Critique (46, 48) once
more declared the real Ego to be unknowable ; and straightway
illogically asserted a real distinction between the unknowable
real Ego and the equally unknowable real non-Ego.
But, assuming that the idealist admits at least a real Ego,
how are we to meet his assertion that perhaps the whole domain
of data or objects of sense perception, i.e. the seemingly external
material universe, is after all a creation of this real Ego, and
therefore not really distinct from, and external to, the latter?
Let us see what the supposition entails as a possible interpreta
tion of experience. A simple example will help us. 3 Standing
at the door and looking into the street, I consciously perceive a
succession of data or objects : men, horses, trams, cyclists, etc.,
passing. Closing and opening my eyes alternately I apprehend
different objects after each interval. My action is certainly the
cause of my seeing or not seeing (i.e. the cause quoad exercitium
actus}. But my action of opening my eyes and seeing is not the
cause of the order and diversity and variety of the perceived data
1 HUXLEY S Hume, chap, iii., p. 81, apnd RICKABY, First Principles, p. 273.
3 Ibid. 3 C/. JEANNIERE, p. cit., p. 391.
VALIDITY OF SENSE PERCEPTION 57
(i.e. the cause quoad specificationem actus). But perhaps the opera
tion of some unconscious and unknown principle of my own being,
of my own real self, is the cause of the specifically diversified suc
cessive data? If so, then, why is it that throughout the same total
experience, with no apparent change in my whole self other than
the successive closing and opening of my eyes, while some data
constantly change, viz. the passing men, horses, vehicles, etc.,
other data reappear as self -identical each time I open my eyes,
viz., the pathway, the pavement, the houses and windows op
posite, etc. ? Because, the idealist will answer, not, perhaps,
without some sense of uneasiness, there may be some uncon
scious, unknowable factor of the Ego so operating as to make
certain data merely occur, without recurring, and to make others
recur repeatedly. So this is the final assertion of the idealist
who regards the cognitive transcendence of the self, in the process
of cognition, as an impossibility : and indeed if he holds it to be
an impossibility his only alternative is that there must be such an
unconscious or subconscious factor of the real Ego as he refers to.
Now, if the idealist were to interpret this, his own final
assertion, as necessarily implying literal solipsism,- the doctrine
that himself, the individual perceiver, is the only reality, and that
the whole universe is merely a manifestation of himself to him
self, we might feel in charity bound to warn his friends of his
mental condition. But the idealists we have to meet in real life
are those who give a quite sane interpretation of their position.
Such a one will say to the realist: "The whole external uni
verse (including yourself) is for me simply my representation, just
as the whole universe (including myself), external to you, is
for you simply your representation. But because you are for me
simply part of my representation I am not so unreasonable, or
unreasoning, or discourteous, as to regard you as being on that
account one whit less real than myself. What I do contend for
is that all reality so far as it is knowable by me is simply a re
presentation in me of I-know-not-what, a something, which I
necessarily think to lie beyond or below my consciousness, but
which I cannot think to be a reality distinct from myself in so far
as I think my conscious self to be a representation of it. And
since I regard you and other men as having a mental constitution
similar to my own, I am forced to conclude that each of us must
finally regard his own conscious self, i.e. the sum-total of his
conscious representations, and all other similar selves, as
58 THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE
partial self- revelations or self-manifestations of One, Sole, Ulti
mate and Unknowable Reality, the Absolute." 1
As against this attitude, how can it be shown that the ultra-
conscious partial cause of my perceptions, the cause which accounts
for their specific contents and diversity, for the element of orderli
ness in their sequence, for the persistence with which certain
groups recur, for the character of mutual affinity which Kant had
to recognize in them and il logically referred to the unknowable
Ego-cause rather than to the unknowable non-Ego-coMSt (vol. i.,
p. 214, n. 2 ; pp. 347-52), how can it be shown that this ultra-
conscious partial cause is really distinct from, and external to, the
real Ego? Not otherwise than by such an appeal as Jeanniere
makes in the example given above to what consciousness testifies
as actually happening in sense perception. But if in such an
appeal we merely emphasize the total absence of any evidence for
identifying this ultra-conscious specifying cause of our perceptions
zuith the real Ego, the appeal is not conclusive. For the idealist,
as we saw, can still urge the possibility of such identity. To
meet this final position we must go farther and show, by such an
appeal, the presence of adequate evidence in conscious sense per
ception for the judgment whereby we assert a real distinction, a
relation of real otherness, between the real Ego and the other real
determining factor or factors of our perceptions. In other words
we must show, as has been shown above (109), by a, direct appeal
to sense consciousness, that our intellectual concept of " real-
distinction-from-the-Ego," or " real-otherness-from-the-Ego " is
objectively and validly grounded in the feeling of externality
attaching to the data of external sense perception.
The authors who rely principally on the argument from causality to
vindicate a reasoned certitude for our knowledge of a really external universe
1 The whole universe, then, in so far as men can know it, including men them
selves, is a universe of mental phenomena, appearances, representations, of an
Unknowable Reality in individual minds. It may be recognized as such to be
orderly, to be a cosmos, to reveal purpose, intelligence, design ; and may be therefore
interpreted as indicating that the Reality of which it is a self-evolution or mani
festation is Intelligence, Mind, Spirit. This is not far removed from the Hegelian
form of Monism. In so far as subjective idealism identifies " essc " (or, at least,
knowable being) with " pcrcipi," the only difference between it and Berkeley s " im-
materialism " is that the panorama of data consciously apprehended by the individual
mind is regarded by the former as subjectively produced by the one ultra-conscious
" Absolute Reality " (Monism), whereas in the latter it is regarded as a system of
"ideas" placed or produced by the Divine Spirit in really distinct created human
spirits or minds (Pluralism, Theism). Cf. infra, 123, 155.
VALIDITY OF SENSE PERCEPTION 59
would, we presume, admit that the proved validity of the concept of " real
otherness " is essential to their conclusion. They hold, of course, the real
validity of this concept. And if faced, for instance, with Kant s contention
that all so-called real distinctions are merely phenomenal, i.e. mental,
and therefore validly applicable only within the domain of consciously
apprehended data, they would have to show in the domain of direct con
sciousness real grounds for the validity of this concept, just as for the
concepts of substance and cause. Now it is easy to show that the concepts
of substance and cause are necessarily apprehended by intellect considering
the data of direct consciousness, and that these data necessarily imply the
real Ego as real substance and real cause. But in order to show that they
imply other real substances and real causes, the concept of real-otherness-
from-the-Ego must be likewise shown to be validly grounded in these data.
Now we can show that it is so grounded only by pointing to its obvious basis
in direct sense consciousness, viz. the felt concrete character of " extended exter
nality " in those data, as adequate intellectual evidence of its real validity, and
of its valid application in the spontaneous judgment whereby we affirm those
data or objects to constitute a domain of reality other than the real (per
ceiving) Ego. But we thereby justify philosophically this latter judgment
without appealing to causality at all : and that is why we have put this line
of argument, rather than the argument from causality, in the first place (109).
Our position is that the spontaneous judgment whereby we affirm the
external existence of extended material realities is a direct interpretation of
the concrete, intuitively apprehended character of extended externality in
certain sense data ; that we can rationally justify our certitude as to the
truth of this spontaneous judgment by intellectual reflection on that concrete
feature of the sense data, inasmuch as such reflection reveals to us the
validity of the concept of " real-otherness-from-the-^"^," which concept we
have already spontaneously utilized in that judgment ; that, granted the
validity of this concept, we can also infer as a conclusion, by reasoning from
the conceived character of these data as contingent, in the light of the
principle of causality, the judgment which we have already spontaneously
formed, and already j ustified by direct rational reflection on the immediately
and intuitively perceived concrete character of felt externality in those same
data, thus corroborating, by such inference, our already reasoned conviction ;
that, finally, our conviction that this domain of external reality persists in
existence when we are not actually perceiving it, is on a level with our
conviction that the self or Ego persists in existence when as during dream
less sleep or periods of unconsciousness we are not actually aware of the
self or Ego, i.e. both convictions have the same title to be called inferences
from the direct data of consciousness, and, both being equally immediate or
equally mediate, neither is strictly an inference from the other (97, 100, IO5). 1
I ]EANNIERE (op. cit., p. 391 n.) quotes the following extract from PIAT ([/
revenant tternel, in the Correspondant, Oct. 25, 1895, pp. 357-8) : " When I place
my hand against the wall of my room I establish conscious commerce with an
object which is not myself, whose existence is independent of my own. ... If
after a time I again place my hand against the wall I experience once more the
same phenomenon of resistance. The same a third time, and as often as I repeat
the experiment. Whence I infer that there is beyond my sensation a reality which
60 THE OR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
" There are many," writes Mercier, 1 " who refuse to admit the necessity
of an appeal to causality for certitude of the existence of an external world.
They believe that we have a direct intuition of such existence. We are
convinced that in this they are mistaken. We perceive immediately in our
acts the existence of an internal [i.e. self, ] reality. We have direct sense
intuition of external things? and, without intermediary, we form the abstract
notion of what they are [ de ce qu elles sont, apparently the notion of
them as external, extended, material, etc.; and, he should add, the
spontaneous judgment that they are such as this (complex) notion represents
them to be, with the spontaneous conviction that this judgment is true].
But it is impossible for us to affirm with certitude the existence of one or of
many extramental realities without employing the principle of causality. In
the ordinary course of life we do not advert to this inferential procedure,
it has become so familiar to us ; habit diminishes the effort of attention and,
by consequence, the consciousness of our [discursive or inferential] activity."
From all that we have said, the reader will see that we cannot agree
with this view of the matter. Just as we " perceive immediately in our acts
the existence of an internal reality," so we perceive immediately in the data
or objects of these perceptive acts an external reality : as, indeed, the author
himself asserts in the same context. Then, as to the existence of " extra-
mental " realities, such existence can be affirmed with certitude " without
employing the principle of causality," provided the extramental realities are
cognitively related, or given, or presented, to the consciously perceiving,
conceiving and judging mind, as they are in its concretely felt " external," " ex
tended " percepts, and in the concepts of "extended externality" or "other
ness " abstracted from those percepts : just as " without employing the principle
of causality " the existence of the reality which is the Ego, the existence of
the real Ego* can be affirmed with certitude provided, and because, this
real Ego is related, or given, or presented, to the mind in the intuitively
persists in its absence, a reality endowed with a principle of permanence. The
astronomer who measures the earth s orbit apprehends the planet only at certain
points in its course ; and these points he links up with lines which he has not
experienced. It is by an analogous procedure that the psychologist works up his
proof of an external universe."
It is quite true that such a process of inference enters, perhaps half un
consciously, into the formation of our conviction that the external world persists
when we are not perceiving it. But it plays precisely the same role in forming our
conviction that the real Ego persists in existence when we are not aware of it.
This, however, does not alter the fact that without recourse to such a process in
either case we can in actual direct consciousness apprehend both the real Ego and
the real non-Ego ; and spontaneously judge both of them to be real, and really
distinct ; and by immediate reflection on the characters of the actually apprehended
conscious data convince ourselves that there is in these data adequate intellectual
evidence to justify both judgments alike.
l Op. cit., 140, p. 386. 2 Italics ours.
3 I.e. the real Ego which is not merely the sum-total or current or series of all
conscious data, but which is the substantial unifying principle of all of them ; and
which, be it remarked, is partly " extramental " in the sense that it includes the felt,
extended, material organism or body, and is therefore as such partly " extramental "
to consciousness in the same sense as the rest of the material universe is.
VALIDITY OF SENSE PERCEPTION 61
apprehended " internal-seeming " data of direct consciousness, both sensuous
and intellectual. We can of course infer, by the principle of causality, the
reality of the non-Ego which we have already both spontaneously and
reflectively asserted to exist, 1 just as we can infer the reality of the Ego by
the principle that perceptions imply a real perceiver. But the ordinary
judgments by which men assert with certitude that this, that, or the other
material thing is external to them, are not conclusions of an inference which
has become sub-conscious through custom and familiarity. Whether the
process of perception itself is not a sort of " inference " we shall see later.
But after all, it may be urged, is not the real existence of the Ego
known prior to that of the non-Ego f Proximus sum mihimttipsi. Have
we not emphasized the truth of the positive element in Descartes principle,
Cogito, ergo sum ? (100). Is not it indubitable even to one who doubts the
reality of the non-Ego f And therefore, is not knowledge of the latter some
how dependent on, and mediated by, knowledge of the former ? Let us see.
It is quite true that since knowing is a function of the Ego, knowledge
of reality other than the Ego must imply that such reality is related, presented,
given to, and made cognitively one with the Ego. But so must the Ego
itself be presented to itself in order to be known. Now let us take the only
fact which has never been doubted by any sceptic, -viz, the existence of a
"stream," or " series," or "panorama "of "perceptions," "presentations,"
" representations," " conscious states," " objects or data of awareness " call
them what you will. If we limit the term "mental" to these "perceived
entities," and call them "the Ego" then of course the most extreme sceptic
will admit that the existence of the Ego is indubitably known. But was this
what Descartes meant by the Ego, or what we mean by it ? No ; but the
real perceiver, thinker, knower (30, 31). And when he claimed certitude for
the judgment that such a reality really exists, he was assuming (and rightly) the
validity of certain intellectual concepts, those, namely, of substance and
cause or agent. But was such a judgment really indubitable ? Well, Kant,
for one, held it to be groundless, pointing out that the only Ego of which
we are certain is the " mental," " phenomenal " Ego, which consists in the
panorama of representations, and that the ./5^0-substance, the ><?-cause or
agent (which he of course recognized to be what people ordinarily mean by
the "real" Ego], being " extramental" or " noumenal," i.e. not being any or
all of the " phenomena," is necessary unknowable. And prior to Kant, the
pan-phenomenism of Hume had likewise doubted the knowableness of the
real Ego which Descartes declared to be indubitably known because in
dubitably given in and with the " representations ". And so it is given ;
only that the reasoned intellectual assertion of it implies the real validity of
the concepts of substance and cause or agent. Reasoned intellectual certi
tude of the existence of the real Ego is, therefore, not wholly beyond the
possibility of at least an unreasonable and de facto unwarranted doubt.
Now let us look at the relation of our certitude of a real non-Ego to
the really indubitable stream of representations. And let us ask ourselves
is doubt about this certitude really more possible or plausible, really less
arbitrary and unwarranted, than the corresponding doubt about our certitude
1 On the ground of the proved validity of our concept of real externality or real
otherness.
62 THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE
in regard to the real Ego. It is hard to see how it can be so. We will not
ask is the ordinary man really one whit less certain of the existence of an ex
ternal universe than he is of his own existence. For of course he is not, but
this is spontaneous certitude. Let us rather ask does the stream of conscious
data furnish equally valid and equally immediate ground for the reasoned
assertion that a real non-Ego exists, as it does for the reasoned assertion that
a real Ego exists ? The reader must answer this for himself. To us it seems
that the answer must be in the affirmative. The spontaneous judgment that
a real Ego exists, employs as valid the concepts of substance and cause ; and
reflection justifies the assumption of their validity by seeing them to be
grounded in, and implied by, the stream of events called perceptions, repre
sentations, etc. So, too, the spontaneous judgment that a real non-Ego exists,
employs as valid the concepts of substance * and real otherness or real extern
ality, and reflection likewise justifies the assumption of their validity, that of
the concept cf real externality by seeing this concept to be grounded in
and implied by the concrete, felt feature of externality in certain of the con
tents of the stream or panorama of perceptions, and that of the concept of
substance as in the former case.
It seems to us, therefore, that the rationally indubitable character of out-
spontaneous judgment that "there exists a real Ego (which is not merely the
stream of representations but the living subject or substance that has or ex
periences them)," does not warrant us in pronouncing as any less indubitable,
or more liable to rational doubt, the spontaneous judgment that "there exists
1 And also the concept of extension, if the spontaneous judgment be taken to be
as it really is " An extended non-Ego or external reality exists ". Does this
spontaneous judgment also imply as valid the concept of cause ? We think that
de facto it does not. If you ask the ordinary man why he is certain that you your
self are really external to him, his answer will not be, " Because I have certain
sense impressions of which not I myself, but you, must be the cause"; rather his
answer will be, " Because I see you ". We think, moreover, that the spontaneous
judgment can be rationally justified by the reflection which will show the concept
of " real externality " to be a valid concept. No doubt the consciously apprehended
character of external sense perception as a process in which we feel ourselves pas
sive, impressed, influenced, acted on, is one of the sources of the concept of cause;
and this concept may be, and perhaps often is, unconsciously operative in our spon
taneous interpretations of the data of external sense perception. But nevertheless it
is not the concept of causality, but the concept of real otherness or real externality,
that gives the spontaneous judgment its specific meaning as an assertion that
" External reality exists " ; and moreover the proved validity of this concept is so
essential to the justification of the spontaneous judgment that without it the concept
of causality would, as we have seen, be unable to justify this judgment. The two
concretely felt characteristics of the whole conscious content of external sense per
ceptions, viz. the feeling of subjective passivity, or of their being specifically
determined independently of the self as conscious, i.e. of the self as concomitantly
revealed in the perceiving acts, and secondly the feeling of extended externality of
the perceived objects, are themselves consciously distinct data. The former feel
ing is present even in conscious states identified with the Ego or subject as sentient,
e.g. in perceptions of organic conditions, organic pleasures and pains. It is, there
fore, not on the intellectual evidence furnished by that feature of our conscious per
cepts, but rather on the intellectual evidence furnished by the sense feature of
externality, that our spontaneous judgment of real externality must primarily rely
for its rational justification.
VALIDITY OF SENSE PERCEPTION 63
a real non-Ego (which is not identical with this stream of conscious percep
tion-processes but has a real being that is independent of its being perceived
in these processes) " ; nor does it warrant us in denying that the latter judg
ment can be rationally justified by the same sort of immediate appeal to the
direct data of consciousness whereby we justify the former judgment, or in
contending that it can be justified only mediately by an appeal to the principle
of causality.
CHAPTER XVI.
PERCEPTION OF SENSE QUALITIES.
In the second last section
(109) we vindicated a reasoned or philosophic certitude for the
belief that " there exists, distinct from the Ego, an external
domain of reality which appears as extended or material ". The
argument was based on the evidence furnished by direct intel
lectual scrutiny of the data of conscious external sense perception.
We have likewise shown that our intellectuul concept of " other-
1 op. dt., pp. 124-5.
4*
52 THE OR Y OF A NO W LEDGE
ness-from-the Ego" or "externality," derived from those data, is
objectively and really valid (105). We are therefore now in a
position to corroborate the conclusion of our argument by con
sidering our spontaneous interpretation of sense perception in the
light of a principle, the universal validity of which has likewise
been already established (65, 66, 93) the principle of causality.
Those supporters of realism l who in the present general context rely
mainly or exclusively on the argument from causality to establish the phil
osophical certitude of our knowledge of an external world, emphasize the
universal real validity of the concept of cause ; and consider the argument
peculiarly efficacious as against idealists. 2 But even though the concept is uni
versally applicable to contingent reality, and even if the idealist admits this,
the latter has still to be convinced that there is contingent reality beyond the
domain of the subjects consciousness? or beyond the reality of the Ego if
he recognizes a real Ego as subject and cause of conscious states. And of
this we can hope to convince him, if at all, only by proving to him that the
concept of " reality-other-than-the Ego," which he possesses in common with
us, is an objectively and really valid concept. But how can we prove that
it is ? Only by pointing out that the sensuously felt character of " extended
externality " in certain of our sense data can be seen by intellect to be the
source from which the concept is derived, and to be therefore for intellect
adequate objective evidence of the real validity of the concept (104, 105).
In other words, by the same line of reasoning, by the same sort of direct in
tellectual appeal to the characteristics of conscious sense data, as we have
employed in our main argument for the mind-independent existence of a
real non-self universe (109). It is because we believe that if realism cannot
be effectively vindicated, as against idealism, by that class of consideration,
neither can it be effectively vindicated, apart from such consideration, by the
principle of causality alone (cf. 105-6), it is for that reason we now bring for
ward the argument from causality merely as corroborative, and not in the first
place.
l Cf. JEANNIERE, op. cit., pp. 224-7, 382-92 ; MERCIER, op. cii., 140, pp. 384-9.
a cy. vol. i., 35, p. 134.
3 Kant, for instance, and English phenomenists, admit the validity of causality
(as understood by them in the sense of a provisionally, or an absolutely, necessary
sequence, respectively) as applied within the whole domain of empirical conscious
ness. And even when we have proved against Kant that it is validly applied in in
ferring an ultra-conscious cause of this whole domain, the principle itself will not
enable us to determine whether this latter cause is one or manifold. We prove it
to be manifold, to be in part the real Ego, and in part a whole pluralistic system
of realities external to and other than the real Ego (all alike themselves contingent,
and therefore implying a Supreme Uncaused First Cause), not by the principle of
causality alone, but only by the collateral use of another and distinct intellectual
concept, namely, that of real distinction or real otherness, a concept whose real
validity, as marking off the " Ego- or self-reality " from " rtow-S//-realities " (and
these latter from one another), must be independently established. We have shown
this concept, as applied to the distinction between the Ego and the non-Ego, to
be really valid because grounded in characteristics of the conscious sense data from
which it is derived (101-105).
VALIDITY OF SENSE PERCEPTION 53
We have already proved, as against Kant, 1 that the Ego,
through its conscious activities, apprehends itself as a reality ;
that Descartes, in emphasizing the absolutely indisputable char
acter of our knowledge of the real self in his principle, Cogito,
ergo sum, was only re-echoing the traditional teaching of scholas
ticism from the days of St. Augustine (29, 34). Now this self
reveals itself as consciously affected by what we may call an ever-
changing panorama of apprehended data or objects, namely, the
proper and common sensibles. Our conscious perceptions of
these data are contingent events. Therefore, by virtue of the
principles of sufficient reason and causality (64, 65,) these con
scious perceptions of data or objects have an adequate cause.
But such adequate cause cannot be the self, or anything in the
self or really constituting or appertaining to the self. Therefore
there must be, beyond and really distinct from the self, a mind-
independent reality which, co-operating with the consciously per
cipient self, will adequately account for the perceptions de facto
experienced by the latter. Hence there exists, distinct from the
self, and independent of perception, a reality which we call the
external, material universe. 2
Let us consider the steps in this argument. That the Ego
has conscious perceptions whereby data or objects " externally-
appearing," "extended," "coloured," "moving," "resisting,"
"sounding," etc., are presented in consciousness, is a fact ad
mitted by even the most extreme sceptics and subjectivists : as
also is the fact that these perceptions are contingent events, in the
sense that they are not self-explaining, that they come and go,
appear and disappear, begin to be and cease to be, and so call for
explanation or demand a cause. And the objective, real validity
of the principle of causality has been already established. Next,
the adequate cause of them cannot be the self. Why ? This
needs a little reflection.
The main reason is that we feel ourselves passive in experienc
ing such perceptions. Hence Kant recognizes that the empirical
content of perception is given tons from without, that to account
for our perceptions there is and must be a reality beyond and
independent of them, and of the self as empirically revealed
1 Cf, vol. 5., 97, 99, 100. Cf. infra, 134.
a Berkeley s alternative inference" Therefore there exists, distinct from and
independent of our minds, a cause of these conscious states, which cause is the
Divine Spirit " will be examined later, 123. Cf. JEANNIERE, op. cit., pp. 401-4.
5 4 THE OR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
in consciousness (50, 51, 74). Hence, too, Fichte claims that
epistemology must take as starting-point the fact that in the
content of consciousness there is, besides the mobile, subjectively
determined portion, another portion independent of subjective
contingencies and inseparable from what he describes as the
feeling of necessity} We feel ourselves passive, impressed, under
going impressions, in sense perception. That is, though the per
ceptions are ours, though it is we that elicit or exercise the
conscious, perceptive acts, still we feel them as not being wholly
determined by ourselves in regard to what they reveal to us. As
to the specific character of the various data or objects revealed
to us in perception (i.e. " quoad specificationem "), they appear to
arise or take place in us or to present this specific character to
us, independently of ourselves ; and therefore to have, as partial
cause of their concrete happening, some reality other than the
self. Reflection will confirm this spontaneous belief.
(1) It is not merely my will that determines these percep
tions. I cannot have them by merely willing to have them.
And as to what they are, when they happen, they are inde
pendent of my will. I cannot have the perceptions which
consist in "seeing Rome," or " hearing music," or " carrying a
weight," or " tasting sugar," or " inhaling the perfume of violets "
by merely wishing to have such perceptions. And on the other
hand, when I am in the condition in which I do actually ex
perience any such perception I cannot cease to experience it
merely by wishing it to cease.
(2) Nor is it my imagination that determines such percep
tions. There is the most marked and indisputable conscious
difference between the panorama of data or objects brought into
consciousness by the play of the imagination in fancies, day
dreams, reveries, etc., between what are called " mental images "
or " phantasmata," on the one hand, and the data or objects of
sense perception, 2 or what are rightly called percepts, on the other.
Psychologists and philosophers have minutely analysed and
abundantly illustrated these differences. 3 The former class of
data are largely under the control of the will : we can direct, con-
1 Fichte s Werke, i., 419, apud MKRCIER, op. cit., p. 385. To this " feeling of
necessity " belong the feelings of" extensity " and " externality ".
Including the perception of organic states, organic pleasure or pain, etc., in the
perceiver s own body.
1 Cf. BAI.MKS, Fundamental Philosophy, Book II., chap. iv.
VALIDITY OF SENSE PERCEPTION 55
trol, modify the order in which such images present themselves ;
we can separate, combine, rearrange the images as we please ; we
can thus " produce " or " construct " new data or objects from
the remembered materials of perception ; and the power of the
" productive imagination " is only limited by the range of those
materials and its own finiteness. The latter class, the percepts,
are, as we saw, beyond the control of the will : the order in
which they succeed each other is not consciously determined by
us, but is felt to be determined by something other than the
self. Moreover, the two classes of data have been distinguished
as "faint" or "weak," and " strong " or " vivid " states, or (as
Hume named them) "ideas" and "impressions," on account of
the superior definiteness, clarity and solidity of the percepts as
compared with the images. Finally, in experiencing the latter
we are conscious that we ourselves, by our own active exercise of
imagination, zxz producing (not ex inhilo, but from the remembered
data of perception) the flow or current of mental objects ; while
in experiencing the former we are rather conscious of passively
undergoing impressions made on us by something independent of
the conscious Ego.
(3) Nor is it my thought that determines such perceptions
or originates such data or objects. By thought the individual
self or Ego elaborates logical relations, judgments, systems of
knowledge, sciences, concerning the domain of perceived data ;
but it certainly does not produce or construct this domain.
(4) But perhaps the same Ego, which consciously perceives
these data, itself constructs or produces them by an internal, in
stinctive, unconsciously operating influence of its own nature?
Well, if it did, such influence would have no other claim than its
blind, unconscious character, to be described as an "instinct".
For the forms of energy we describe as " instincts " in sentient
beings follow fixed laws and are uniform and circumscribed in
their results. But there is nothing of this in the ever-changing
panorama of percepts which constitute the world of any indivi
dual perceiver s sense experience. Psychologists can with some
success explore and formulate the laws according to which "in
stincts " operate ; but who has ever dreamt of seeking or formu
lating laws according to which the world of each individual s
sense experience unfolds itself in the order, and with the qualities,
which actually characterize it ?
(5) But, dismissing the term " instinctive," may it not finally
56 THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE
be urged that, for all we know, it may be the real Ego ifself that
in some unconscious way, and by some unknown and unknowable
laws, produces this whole panorama of sense percepts which we
spontaneously and inevitably, but so far as reflecting reason
goes, unwarrantably believe to be a domain of reality other
than, and external to, the self, unwarrantably, since on this
possible hypothesis it would be but a phase or manifestation of
the real self? Perhaps, to use the picturesque words of Huxley, 1
"For any demonstration that can be given to the contrary
effect, the collection of perceptions which makes up our con
sciousness may be an orderly phantasmagoria, generated by the
Ego unfolding its successive scenes on the background of the
abyss of nothingness ; as a firework, which is but cunningly
arranged combustibles, grows from a spark into a corruscation,
and from a corruscation into figures and words and cascades of
devouring flames, and then vanishes into the darkness of night ".
The concession Huxley had just made to realism was that
" there may be a real something which is the cause of our experi
ence ". J And this something he now declares to be a hypo
thetical and unknowable real Ego, in the sceptical spirit of
Hume. Kant, as we have seen, so far from refuting this scepticism
which was the avowed object of his Critique (46, 48) once
more declared the real Ego to be unknowable ; and straightway
illogically asserted a real distinction between the unknowable
real Ego and the equally unknowable real non-Ego.
But, assuming that the idealist admits at least a real Ego,
how are we to meet his assertion that perhaps the whole domain
of data or objects of sense perception, i.e. the seemingly external
material universe, is after all a creation of this real Ego, and
therefore not really distinct from, and external to, the latter?
Let us see what the supposition entails as a possible interpreta
tion of experience. A simple example will help us. 3 Standing
at the door and looking into the street, I consciously perceive a
succession of data or objects : men, horses, trams, cyclists, etc.,
passing. Closing and opening my eyes alternately I apprehend
different objects after each interval. My action is certainly the
cause of my seeing or not seeing (i.e. the cause quoad exercitium
actus}. But my action of opening my eyes and seeing is not the
cause of the order and diversity and variety of the perceived data
1 HUXLEY S Hume, chap, iii., p. 81, apnd RICKABY, First Principles, p. 273.
3 Ibid. 3 C/. JEANNIERE, p. cit., p. 391.
VALIDITY OF SENSE PERCEPTION 57
(i.e. the cause quoad specificationem actus). But perhaps the opera
tion of some unconscious and unknown principle of my own being,
of my own real self, is the cause of the specifically diversified suc
cessive data? If so, then, why is it that throughout the same total
experience, with no apparent change in my whole self other than
the successive closing and opening of my eyes, while some data
constantly change, viz. the passing men, horses, vehicles, etc.,
other data reappear as self -identical each time I open my eyes,
viz., the pathway, the pavement, the houses and windows op
posite, etc. ? Because, the idealist will answer, not, perhaps,
without some sense of uneasiness, there may be some uncon
scious, unknowable factor of the Ego so operating as to make
certain data merely occur, without recurring, and to make others
recur repeatedly. So this is the final assertion of the idealist
who regards the cognitive transcendence of the self, in the process
of cognition, as an impossibility : and indeed if he holds it to be
an impossibility his only alternative is that there must be such an
unconscious or subconscious factor of the real Ego as he refers to.
Now, if the idealist were to interpret this, his own final
assertion, as necessarily implying literal solipsism,- the doctrine
that himself, the individual perceiver, is the only reality, and that
the whole universe is merely a manifestation of himself to him
self, we might feel in charity bound to warn his friends of his
mental condition. But the idealists we have to meet in real life
are those who give a quite sane interpretation of their position.
Such a one will say to the realist: "The whole external uni
verse (including yourself) is for me simply my representation, just
as the whole universe (including myself), external to you, is
for you simply your representation. But because you are for me
simply part of my representation I am not so unreasonable, or
unreasoning, or discourteous, as to regard you as being on that
account one whit less real than myself. What I do contend for
is that all reality so far as it is knowable by me is simply a re
presentation in me of I-know-not-what, a something, which I
necessarily think to lie beyond or below my consciousness, but
which I cannot think to be a reality distinct from myself in so far
as I think my conscious self to be a representation of it. And
since I regard you and other men as having a mental constitution
similar to my own, I am forced to conclude that each of us must
finally regard his own conscious self, i.e. the sum-total of his
conscious representations, and all other similar selves, as
58 THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE
partial self- revelations or self-manifestations of One, Sole, Ulti
mate and Unknowable Reality, the Absolute." 1
As against this attitude, how can it be shown that the ultra-
conscious partial cause of my perceptions, the cause which accounts
for their specific contents and diversity, for the element of orderli
ness in their sequence, for the persistence with which certain
groups recur, for the character of mutual affinity which Kant had
to recognize in them and il logically referred to the unknowable
Ego-cause rather than to the unknowable non-Ego-coMSt (vol. i.,
p. 214, n. 2 ; pp. 347-52), how can it be shown that this ultra-
conscious partial cause is really distinct from, and external to, the
real Ego? Not otherwise than by such an appeal as Jeanniere
makes in the example given above to what consciousness testifies
as actually happening in sense perception. But if in such an
appeal we merely emphasize the total absence of any evidence for
identifying this ultra-conscious specifying cause of our perceptions
zuith the real Ego, the appeal is not conclusive. For the idealist,
as we saw, can still urge the possibility of such identity. To
meet this final position we must go farther and show, by such an
appeal, the presence of adequate evidence in conscious sense per
ception for the judgment whereby we assert a real distinction, a
relation of real otherness, between the real Ego and the other real
determining factor or factors of our perceptions. In other words
we must show, as has been shown above (109), by a, direct appeal
to sense consciousness, that our intellectual concept of " real-
distinction-from-the-Ego," or " real-otherness-from-the-Ego " is
objectively and validly grounded in the feeling of externality
attaching to the data of external sense perception.
The authors who rely principally on the argument from causality to
vindicate a reasoned certitude for our knowledge of a really external universe
1 The whole universe, then, in so far as men can know it, including men them
selves, is a universe of mental phenomena, appearances, representations, of an
Unknowable Reality in individual minds. It may be recognized as such to be
orderly, to be a cosmos, to reveal purpose, intelligence, design ; and may be therefore
interpreted as indicating that the Reality of which it is a self-evolution or mani
festation is Intelligence, Mind, Spirit. This is not far removed from the Hegelian
form of Monism. In so far as subjective idealism identifies " essc " (or, at least,
knowable being) with " pcrcipi," the only difference between it and Berkeley s " im-
materialism " is that the panorama of data consciously apprehended by the individual
mind is regarded by the former as subjectively produced by the one ultra-conscious
" Absolute Reality " (Monism), whereas in the latter it is regarded as a system of
"ideas" placed or produced by the Divine Spirit in really distinct created human
spirits or minds (Pluralism, Theism). Cf. infra, 123, 155.
VALIDITY OF SENSE PERCEPTION 59
would, we presume, admit that the proved validity of the concept of " real
otherness " is essential to their conclusion. They hold, of course, the real
validity of this concept. And if faced, for instance, with Kant s contention
that all so-called real distinctions are merely phenomenal, i.e. mental,
and therefore validly applicable only within the domain of consciously
apprehended data, they would have to show in the domain of direct con
sciousness real grounds for the validity of this concept, just as for the
concepts of substance and cause. Now it is easy to show that the concepts
of substance and cause are necessarily apprehended by intellect considering
the data of direct consciousness, and that these data necessarily imply the
real Ego as real substance and real cause. But in order to show that they
imply other real substances and real causes, the concept of real-otherness-
from-the-Ego must be likewise shown to be validly grounded in these data.
Now we can show that it is so grounded only by pointing to its obvious basis
in direct sense consciousness, viz. the felt concrete character of " extended exter
nality " in those data, as adequate intellectual evidence of its real validity, and
of its valid application in the spontaneous judgment whereby we affirm those
data or objects to constitute a domain of reality other than the real (per
ceiving) Ego. But we thereby justify philosophically this latter judgment
without appealing to causality at all : and that is why we have put this line
of argument, rather than the argument from causality, in the first place (109).
Our position is that the spontaneous judgment whereby we affirm the
external existence of extended material realities is a direct interpretation of
the concrete, intuitively apprehended character of extended externality in
certain sense data ; that we can rationally justify our certitude as to the
truth of this spontaneous judgment by intellectual reflection on that concrete
feature of the sense data, inasmuch as such reflection reveals to us the
validity of the concept of " real-otherness-from-the-^"^," which concept we
have already spontaneously utilized in that judgment ; that, granted the
validity of this concept, we can also infer as a conclusion, by reasoning from
the conceived character of these data as contingent, in the light of the
principle of causality, the judgment which we have already spontaneously
formed, and already j ustified by direct rational reflection on the immediately
and intuitively perceived concrete character of felt externality in those same
data, thus corroborating, by such inference, our already reasoned conviction ;
that, finally, our conviction that this domain of external reality persists in
existence when we are not actually perceiving it, is on a level with our
conviction that the self or Ego persists in existence when as during dream
less sleep or periods of unconsciousness we are not actually aware of the
self or Ego, i.e. both convictions have the same title to be called inferences
from the direct data of consciousness, and, both being equally immediate or
equally mediate, neither is strictly an inference from the other (97, 100, IO5). 1
I ]EANNIERE (op. cit., p. 391 n.) quotes the following extract from PIAT ([/
revenant tternel, in the Correspondant, Oct. 25, 1895, pp. 357-8) : " When I place
my hand against the wall of my room I establish conscious commerce with an
object which is not myself, whose existence is independent of my own. ... If
after a time I again place my hand against the wall I experience once more the
same phenomenon of resistance. The same a third time, and as often as I repeat
the experiment. Whence I infer that there is beyond my sensation a reality which
60 THE OR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
" There are many," writes Mercier, 1 " who refuse to admit the necessity
of an appeal to causality for certitude of the existence of an external world.
They believe that we have a direct intuition of such existence. We are
convinced that in this they are mistaken. We perceive immediately in our
acts the existence of an internal [i.e. self, ] reality. We have direct sense
intuition of external things? and, without intermediary, we form the abstract
notion of what they are [ de ce qu elles sont, apparently the notion of
them as external, extended, material, etc.; and, he should add, the
spontaneous judgment that they are such as this (complex) notion represents
them to be, with the spontaneous conviction that this judgment is true].
But it is impossible for us to affirm with certitude the existence of one or of
many extramental realities without employing the principle of causality. In
the ordinary course of life we do not advert to this inferential procedure,
it has become so familiar to us ; habit diminishes the effort of attention and,
by consequence, the consciousness of our [discursive or inferential] activity."
From all that we have said, the reader will see that we cannot agree
with this view of the matter. Just as we " perceive immediately in our acts
the existence of an internal reality," so we perceive immediately in the data
or objects of these perceptive acts an external reality : as, indeed, the author
himself asserts in the same context. Then, as to the existence of " extra-
mental " realities, such existence can be affirmed with certitude " without
employing the principle of causality," provided the extramental realities are
cognitively related, or given, or presented, to the consciously perceiving,
conceiving and judging mind, as they are in its concretely felt " external," " ex
tended " percepts, and in the concepts of "extended externality" or "other
ness " abstracted from those percepts : just as " without employing the principle
of causality " the existence of the reality which is the Ego, the existence of
the real Ego* can be affirmed with certitude provided, and because, this
real Ego is related, or given, or presented, to the mind in the intuitively
persists in its absence, a reality endowed with a principle of permanence. The
astronomer who measures the earth s orbit apprehends the planet only at certain
points in its course ; and these points he links up with lines which he has not
experienced. It is by an analogous procedure that the psychologist works up his
proof of an external universe."
It is quite true that such a process of inference enters, perhaps half un
consciously, into the formation of our conviction that the external world persists
when we are not perceiving it. But it plays precisely the same role in forming our
conviction that the real Ego persists in existence when we are not aware of it.
This, however, does not alter the fact that without recourse to such a process in
either case we can in actual direct consciousness apprehend both the real Ego and
the real non-Ego ; and spontaneously judge both of them to be real, and really
distinct ; and by immediate reflection on the characters of the actually apprehended
conscious data convince ourselves that there is in these data adequate intellectual
evidence to justify both judgments alike.
l Op. cit., 140, p. 386. 2 Italics ours.
3 I.e. the real Ego which is not merely the sum-total or current or series of all
conscious data, but which is the substantial unifying principle of all of them ; and
which, be it remarked, is partly " extramental " in the sense that it includes the felt,
extended, material organism or body, and is therefore as such partly " extramental "
to consciousness in the same sense as the rest of the material universe is.
VALIDITY OF SENSE PERCEPTION 61
apprehended " internal-seeming " data of direct consciousness, both sensuous
and intellectual. We can of course infer, by the principle of causality, the
reality of the non-Ego which we have already both spontaneously and
reflectively asserted to exist, 1 just as we can infer the reality of the Ego by
the principle that perceptions imply a real perceiver. But the ordinary
judgments by which men assert with certitude that this, that, or the other
material thing is external to them, are not conclusions of an inference which
has become sub-conscious through custom and familiarity. Whether the
process of perception itself is not a sort of " inference " we shall see later.
But after all, it may be urged, is not the real existence of the Ego
known prior to that of the non-Ego f Proximus sum mihimttipsi. Have
we not emphasized the truth of the positive element in Descartes principle,
Cogito, ergo sum ? (100). Is not it indubitable even to one who doubts the
reality of the non-Ego f And therefore, is not knowledge of the latter some
how dependent on, and mediated by, knowledge of the former ? Let us see.
It is quite true that since knowing is a function of the Ego, knowledge
of reality other than the Ego must imply that such reality is related, presented,
given to, and made cognitively one with the Ego. But so must the Ego
itself be presented to itself in order to be known. Now let us take the only
fact which has never been doubted by any sceptic, -viz, the existence of a
"stream," or " series," or "panorama "of "perceptions," "presentations,"
" representations," " conscious states," " objects or data of awareness " call
them what you will. If we limit the term "mental" to these "perceived
entities," and call them "the Ego" then of course the most extreme sceptic
will admit that the existence of the Ego is indubitably known. But was this
what Descartes meant by the Ego, or what we mean by it ? No ; but the
real perceiver, thinker, knower (30, 31). And when he claimed certitude for
the judgment that such a reality really exists, he was assuming (and rightly) the
validity of certain intellectual concepts, those, namely, of substance and
cause or agent. But was such a judgment really indubitable ? Well, Kant,
for one, held it to be groundless, pointing out that the only Ego of which
we are certain is the " mental," " phenomenal " Ego, which consists in the
panorama of representations, and that the ./5^0-substance, the ><?-cause or
agent (which he of course recognized to be what people ordinarily mean by
the "real" Ego], being " extramental" or " noumenal," i.e. not being any or
all of the " phenomena," is necessary unknowable. And prior to Kant, the
pan-phenomenism of Hume had likewise doubted the knowableness of the
real Ego which Descartes declared to be indubitably known because in
dubitably given in and with the " representations ". And so it is given ;
only that the reasoned intellectual assertion of it implies the real validity of
the concepts of substance and cause or agent. Reasoned intellectual certi
tude of the existence of the real Ego is, therefore, not wholly beyond the
possibility of at least an unreasonable and de facto unwarranted doubt.
Now let us look at the relation of our certitude of a real non-Ego to
the really indubitable stream of representations. And let us ask ourselves
is doubt about this certitude really more possible or plausible, really less
arbitrary and unwarranted, than the corresponding doubt about our certitude
1 On the ground of the proved validity of our concept of real externality or real
otherness.
62 THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE
in regard to the real Ego. It is hard to see how it can be so. We will not
ask is the ordinary man really one whit less certain of the existence of an ex
ternal universe than he is of his own existence. For of course he is not, but
this is spontaneous certitude. Let us rather ask does the stream of conscious
data furnish equally valid and equally immediate ground for the reasoned
assertion that a real non-Ego exists, as it does for the reasoned assertion that
a real Ego exists ? The reader must answer this for himself. To us it seems
that the answer must be in the affirmative. The spontaneous judgment that
a real Ego exists, employs as valid the concepts of substance and cause ; and
reflection justifies the assumption of their validity by seeing them to be
grounded in, and implied by, the stream of events called perceptions, repre
sentations, etc. So, too, the spontaneous judgment that a real non-Ego exists,
employs as valid the concepts of substance * and real otherness or real extern
ality, and reflection likewise justifies the assumption of their validity, that of
the concept cf real externality by seeing this concept to be grounded in
and implied by the concrete, felt feature of externality in certain of the con
tents of the stream or panorama of perceptions, and that of the concept of
substance as in the former case.
It seems to us, therefore, that the rationally indubitable character of out-
spontaneous judgment that "there exists a real Ego (which is not merely the
stream of representations but the living subject or substance that has or ex
periences them)," does not warrant us in pronouncing as any less indubitable,
or more liable to rational doubt, the spontaneous judgment that "there exists
1 And also the concept of extension, if the spontaneous judgment be taken to be
as it really is " An extended non-Ego or external reality exists ". Does this
spontaneous judgment also imply as valid the concept of cause ? We think that
de facto it does not. If you ask the ordinary man why he is certain that you your
self are really external to him, his answer will not be, " Because I have certain
sense impressions of which not I myself, but you, must be the cause"; rather his
answer will be, " Because I see you ". We think, moreover, that the spontaneous
judgment can be rationally justified by the reflection which will show the concept
of " real externality " to be a valid concept. No doubt the consciously apprehended
character of external sense perception as a process in which we feel ourselves pas
sive, impressed, influenced, acted on, is one of the sources of the concept of cause;
and this concept may be, and perhaps often is, unconsciously operative in our spon
taneous interpretations of the data of external sense perception. But nevertheless it
is not the concept of causality, but the concept of real otherness or real externality,
that gives the spontaneous judgment its specific meaning as an assertion that
" External reality exists " ; and moreover the proved validity of this concept is so
essential to the justification of the spontaneous judgment that without it the concept
of causality would, as we have seen, be unable to justify this judgment. The two
concretely felt characteristics of the whole conscious content of external sense per
ceptions, viz. the feeling of subjective passivity, or of their being specifically
determined independently of the self as conscious, i.e. of the self as concomitantly
revealed in the perceiving acts, and secondly the feeling of extended externality of
the perceived objects, are themselves consciously distinct data. The former feel
ing is present even in conscious states identified with the Ego or subject as sentient,
e.g. in perceptions of organic conditions, organic pleasures and pains. It is, there
fore, not on the intellectual evidence furnished by that feature of our conscious per
cepts, but rather on the intellectual evidence furnished by the sense feature of
externality, that our spontaneous judgment of real externality must primarily rely
for its rational justification.
VALIDITY OF SENSE PERCEPTION 63
a real non-Ego (which is not identical with this stream of conscious percep
tion-processes but has a real being that is independent of its being perceived
in these processes) " ; nor does it warrant us in denying that the latter judg
ment can be rationally justified by the same sort of immediate appeal to the
direct data of consciousness whereby we justify the former judgment, or in
contending that it can be justified only mediately by an appeal to the principle
of causality.
CHAPTER XVI.
PERCEPTION OF SENSE QUALITIES.