140. SOME RELATIVIST DIFFICULTIES.
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101
102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 112 113 114 115 117 118
119 120 121 122 123 124 125 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135
138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148
I. But now, if this
latter view be correct, would it not appear that absolutely neces
sary judgments of the ideal order give us an insight rather into
the constitution of our intellects than into the nature of reality,
just as in Kant s account of them ?
Before meeting this objection we may observe, in reference
to Kant, that according to his account they do not even give us
an insight into the constitution of our own intellects, i.e. of the
real intellect, or the real Ego, but only into our mental representa
tion of the real Ego. And secondly, even waiving that point,
his account gratuitously assumes the impossibility of discriminat
ing the subjective or formal or logical elements from the objective
or given or real elements in things intellectually known : and we
have seen (chap, xii.) the breakdown of his own attempt to trace
all the " affinities " which determine the ultimate conceptual
divisions and classifications of the categories, to subjective, formal,
a priori factors of conception. The Scholastic account, on the
contrary, vindicates for intellectual reflection the power to dis
criminate between the logical attributes and relations which its
own modes of apprehension necessarily attach to the given
reality in its interpretation of this reality, and the modes and
attributes of real being \ which it* represents to itself through
these logical relations.
And now, as to objection itself: such judgments do un
doubtedly give us an insight into the nature of our own intellects,
but an insight which we get only by reflection. Nor is it true
to say that they give in this insight rather than an insight into
the nature of the reality represented in such judgments ; for what
they give us primarily and directly e.g. such judgments as
" The whole is greater than its part," " Whatever happens has a
cause," etc., etc. is an insight into the nature of the reality
1 The possibility and sources of error, of erroneous interpretations or representa
tions of reality, will be dealt with later on.
VOL. II. 15
226 THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE
represented by the various concepts so related. And this, finally,
is what we have now to fix our attention on.
When we say that such judgments represent reality as it is,
that, therefore, reality is necessarily as thus represented, inas
much as it is represented as being necessarily such or such, that
these judgments are true not merely for all human minds but
for all conceivable intelligences, that reality must be so for all con
ceivable intelligences, what do we really mean ? Do we mean
that all conceivable intelligences, pure spiritual intelligences, or
the Divine Mind, must apprehend reality through our human
modes of abstract conception, intellectual analysis and synthesis,
relating, comparing, generalizing, predicating or judging, etc. ?
that they must have the same qualitative and quantitative con
cepts as we have? that e.g. they can apprehend what we desig
nate " material " reality only through abstract concepts derived
from sense qualities ? By no means ; for we have no proper or
positive knowledge of the modes in which such intelligences
would apprehend reality. 1 What we do mean is simply that
whatsoever intelligence apprehends reality, apprehending human
beings and human minds as part of reality, cannot so apprehend
it as to see it incompatible with, or contradictory of, its function
of being what it is represented to be by human minds in the
judgments referred to. When, for instance, we say that " two
and two must be four even for the Divine Mind " we do not at
all mean that the Divine Mind apprehends reality by comparing
abstract, quantitative concepts, but that the Divine mind sees all
reality (including human minds) to be such that the human re
presentation of an aspect of reality by the human judgment " two
and two must be four " is for the human mind the right and proper
representation of that aspect of reality: or sees the reality appre
hended by the human mind, and the human mind apprehending
it, to be such that a necessary function of reality is to appear to
the human mind as it does in such a representation. And when
we reflect on our motive for assenting to the judgment " two and
two must be four," and on what such a judgment means for us,
we realize (i) that our motive for assenting to it is not because
1 If, therefore, we consider the way in which the Divine Mind apprehends
reality we have to think of the Divine Knowledge after the analogy of human know
ledge : we have no other way in which to think of it. We know that our human
concepts represent it only analogically and negatively : rather what it is not than
what it is. But, allowing for this inadequacy of our concepts, the knowledge they
give us is true as far as it goes. C/. vol. i., 6, 71, 75.
RELATIVIST THEORIES OF KNOWLEDGE 227
our intellect is so constituted (whether by custom or habit, or as
a result of evolution, or by virtue of factors operating in an in
scrutable domain of the real self) that it is forced to apprehend
such a relation between its thought-objects, 1 but because reality,
which reveals itself through our concepts, is so constituted that
the abstract aspect of it revealed through the concept "twofl/us
two " must be really identical with the aspect which reveals it
self through the concept "four"; and (2) that its meaning is
that the reality represented by the judgment is such that it is
rightly represented in such a judgment by a mind which has the
judgment-mode of representing reality, and that by no conceivable
mind could it be (rightly) so apprehended as to conflict with its
being thus represented by the human mind.
II. But it will still be urged if the human intellect were
otherwise constituted " two plus two " might after all appear
other than " four," just as sugar may, perhaps, taste not sweet
and pleasant, but bitter and unpleasant, to the palates of some
of the lower animals (43).
We reply: If by "otherwise constituted" we are to under
stand "so constituted as not to apprehend reality by means of
such abstract concepts as we have de facto" then obviously there
could be no question of such an intellect apprehending reality
by comparing the abstract concept " two plus two" with the
concept "four," and seeing a relation between them: in that
case whatever way it would understand reality it could not so
apprehend reality as to see it to be wrongly represented in a
human intellect by such a judgment. If, on the other hand,
"otherwise constituted" means simply that such an intellect
would have our human modes of conceiving and judging, and
could nevertheless judge " two //#.$ two " to be other than " four,"
then it must be denied that such a judgment is possible to such
an intellect rationally understanding the concepts in question ;
and it must furthermore be asserted that were such an intellect
1 DC facto, of course, the intellect is so constituted that (a) it has its own specific
ways of apprehending the real, e.g. by abstract conception of the given concrete, by
analysis and synthesis, judgment, reasoning, etc., -and (b) that the given reality im
pels it (by cogent objective evidence) to use its judgment-mode of apprehension by
applying a certain logical relation, -viz. affirmative predication, and not its contradic
tory, to the reality given in the two abstract thought-objects or concepts, " two plus
two" and "four". But all this is not the motive of our direct assent; it is dis
covered by reflection ; and even when discovered, this knowledge of the real nature,
processes and products of intellect does not affect the conviction that the judgment
" two and two must be four " is a representation of reality.
15 *
228 THE OR V OF KNO IV LEDGE
per impossibilc really to formulate and assent to such a judgment,
the judgment would be erroneous, would misinterpret reality.
As to the false analogy drawn from the domain of sense, its
misleading character has been already exposed (135-6). Sense
does not judge; therefore sense does not know : it is incapable
either of truth or error : it merely furnishes the materials for
knowledge. Intellect alone judges ; intellect alone can reflect :
in its interpretation of sense data it can see and allow for the
influence of the subjective, organic factor on the datum as per
ceived : it can, moreover, reflect on its own processes, on its own
modes of cognition, and on the logical attributes and relations
consequent on these modes ; and by distinguishing these from the
given and interpreted reality it can know the latter as it is, and
can see that its own knowledge is not vitiated by any intrusion of
unknowable subjective factors between itself and the known reality.
I. But now, if this
latter view be correct, would it not appear that absolutely neces
sary judgments of the ideal order give us an insight rather into
the constitution of our intellects than into the nature of reality,
just as in Kant s account of them ?
Before meeting this objection we may observe, in reference
to Kant, that according to his account they do not even give us
an insight into the constitution of our own intellects, i.e. of the
real intellect, or the real Ego, but only into our mental representa
tion of the real Ego. And secondly, even waiving that point,
his account gratuitously assumes the impossibility of discriminat
ing the subjective or formal or logical elements from the objective
or given or real elements in things intellectually known : and we
have seen (chap, xii.) the breakdown of his own attempt to trace
all the " affinities " which determine the ultimate conceptual
divisions and classifications of the categories, to subjective, formal,
a priori factors of conception. The Scholastic account, on the
contrary, vindicates for intellectual reflection the power to dis
criminate between the logical attributes and relations which its
own modes of apprehension necessarily attach to the given
reality in its interpretation of this reality, and the modes and
attributes of real being \ which it* represents to itself through
these logical relations.
And now, as to objection itself: such judgments do un
doubtedly give us an insight into the nature of our own intellects,
but an insight which we get only by reflection. Nor is it true
to say that they give in this insight rather than an insight into
the nature of the reality represented in such judgments ; for what
they give us primarily and directly e.g. such judgments as
" The whole is greater than its part," " Whatever happens has a
cause," etc., etc. is an insight into the nature of the reality
1 The possibility and sources of error, of erroneous interpretations or representa
tions of reality, will be dealt with later on.
VOL. II. 15
226 THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE
represented by the various concepts so related. And this, finally,
is what we have now to fix our attention on.
When we say that such judgments represent reality as it is,
that, therefore, reality is necessarily as thus represented, inas
much as it is represented as being necessarily such or such, that
these judgments are true not merely for all human minds but
for all conceivable intelligences, that reality must be so for all con
ceivable intelligences, what do we really mean ? Do we mean
that all conceivable intelligences, pure spiritual intelligences, or
the Divine Mind, must apprehend reality through our human
modes of abstract conception, intellectual analysis and synthesis,
relating, comparing, generalizing, predicating or judging, etc. ?
that they must have the same qualitative and quantitative con
cepts as we have? that e.g. they can apprehend what we desig
nate " material " reality only through abstract concepts derived
from sense qualities ? By no means ; for we have no proper or
positive knowledge of the modes in which such intelligences
would apprehend reality. 1 What we do mean is simply that
whatsoever intelligence apprehends reality, apprehending human
beings and human minds as part of reality, cannot so apprehend
it as to see it incompatible with, or contradictory of, its function
of being what it is represented to be by human minds in the
judgments referred to. When, for instance, we say that " two
and two must be four even for the Divine Mind " we do not at
all mean that the Divine Mind apprehends reality by comparing
abstract, quantitative concepts, but that the Divine mind sees all
reality (including human minds) to be such that the human re
presentation of an aspect of reality by the human judgment " two
and two must be four " is for the human mind the right and proper
representation of that aspect of reality: or sees the reality appre
hended by the human mind, and the human mind apprehending
it, to be such that a necessary function of reality is to appear to
the human mind as it does in such a representation. And when
we reflect on our motive for assenting to the judgment " two and
two must be four," and on what such a judgment means for us,
we realize (i) that our motive for assenting to it is not because
1 If, therefore, we consider the way in which the Divine Mind apprehends
reality we have to think of the Divine Knowledge after the analogy of human know
ledge : we have no other way in which to think of it. We know that our human
concepts represent it only analogically and negatively : rather what it is not than
what it is. But, allowing for this inadequacy of our concepts, the knowledge they
give us is true as far as it goes. C/. vol. i., 6, 71, 75.
RELATIVIST THEORIES OF KNOWLEDGE 227
our intellect is so constituted (whether by custom or habit, or as
a result of evolution, or by virtue of factors operating in an in
scrutable domain of the real self) that it is forced to apprehend
such a relation between its thought-objects, 1 but because reality,
which reveals itself through our concepts, is so constituted that
the abstract aspect of it revealed through the concept "twofl/us
two " must be really identical with the aspect which reveals it
self through the concept "four"; and (2) that its meaning is
that the reality represented by the judgment is such that it is
rightly represented in such a judgment by a mind which has the
judgment-mode of representing reality, and that by no conceivable
mind could it be (rightly) so apprehended as to conflict with its
being thus represented by the human mind.
II. But it will still be urged if the human intellect were
otherwise constituted " two plus two " might after all appear
other than " four," just as sugar may, perhaps, taste not sweet
and pleasant, but bitter and unpleasant, to the palates of some
of the lower animals (43).
We reply: If by "otherwise constituted" we are to under
stand "so constituted as not to apprehend reality by means of
such abstract concepts as we have de facto" then obviously there
could be no question of such an intellect apprehending reality
by comparing the abstract concept " two plus two" with the
concept "four," and seeing a relation between them: in that
case whatever way it would understand reality it could not so
apprehend reality as to see it to be wrongly represented in a
human intellect by such a judgment. If, on the other hand,
"otherwise constituted" means simply that such an intellect
would have our human modes of conceiving and judging, and
could nevertheless judge " two //#.$ two " to be other than " four,"
then it must be denied that such a judgment is possible to such
an intellect rationally understanding the concepts in question ;
and it must furthermore be asserted that were such an intellect
1 DC facto, of course, the intellect is so constituted that (a) it has its own specific
ways of apprehending the real, e.g. by abstract conception of the given concrete, by
analysis and synthesis, judgment, reasoning, etc., -and (b) that the given reality im
pels it (by cogent objective evidence) to use its judgment-mode of apprehension by
applying a certain logical relation, -viz. affirmative predication, and not its contradic
tory, to the reality given in the two abstract thought-objects or concepts, " two plus
two" and "four". But all this is not the motive of our direct assent; it is dis
covered by reflection ; and even when discovered, this knowledge of the real nature,
processes and products of intellect does not affect the conviction that the judgment
" two and two must be four " is a representation of reality.
15 *
228 THE OR V OF KNO IV LEDGE
per impossibilc really to formulate and assent to such a judgment,
the judgment would be erroneous, would misinterpret reality.
As to the false analogy drawn from the domain of sense, its
misleading character has been already exposed (135-6). Sense
does not judge; therefore sense does not know : it is incapable
either of truth or error : it merely furnishes the materials for
knowledge. Intellect alone judges ; intellect alone can reflect :
in its interpretation of sense data it can see and allow for the
influence of the subjective, organic factor on the datum as per
ceived : it can, moreover, reflect on its own processes, on its own
modes of cognition, and on the logical attributes and relations
consequent on these modes ; and by distinguishing these from the
given and interpreted reality it can know the latter as it is, and
can see that its own knowledge is not vitiated by any intrusion of
unknowable subjective factors between itself and the known reality.