170. OUTLINE OF PRAGMATISM AND HUMANISM.
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101
102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 111 112 113 114 115 116 117 118
119 120 121 122 123 124 125 126 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135
136 137 138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148
Among
the philosophies which, since Kant s time, have employed the
" speculative " reason for its own dethronement, the latest fashion
is undoubtedly that known as Pragmatism or Humanism.
Though of quite recent origin it has to its credit a very ex
tensive output of literature, 1 on the Continent, in England, and
in America its locus originis. Its principal exponents are, in
America, C. S. Peirce, W. James, and J. Dewey ; in England,
F. C. S. Schiller ; in France, Bergson {psychological direction),
Boutroux (critical direction of Poincare and Milhaud), Le Roy
(combining both directions in the "new philosophy") and
Wilbois ; and in Italy, Papini.
It is frankly anti-intellectualist, advocating as the sole test of
truth the practical test of utility in a very broad sense. It is
therefore voluntarist inasmuch as the "utility" of a judgment,
its " bonum utile" is not immediately an object of intellect but of
will. It has not, however, sprung from any preoccupation or
concern with the defence of moral and religious beliefs, but rather
from a teleological consideration of the function and purpose of
thought and knowledge in man, a consideration itself prompted
by the influence of the evolution concept in biological science. 2
For Pragmatism all truth is essentially relative, provisional,
transformable (142, 143).
It was first propounded by C. S. Peirce as a method of ending
the sterile controversies with which the speculative reason is ever
impeding the real progress of the human mind. The sense of
any proposition, and hence its truth or falsity, must be judged
by the mental habit it induces, the effect it has in action, its
pragmatic or working value : hence the title Pragmatism. The
truth or knowledge-value of a proposition is not at all any insight
it is supposed to give us into things, but simply its relation of
utility to human life. 3
1 For adequate bibliography, cf. JEANNIEKE, of. cit., pp. 269-71, whose treat
ment in the main we have followed.
2 Cf. NOEL, Art. in the Revue neo-scolastique, 1911, p. 46.
3 Such a view involves, of course, the abolition of Metaphysics in its traditional
sense of a speculative study of the real. Hence the severity of Pragmatist strictures
on Metaphysics, and the anxiety of Pragmatists to discourage such research. Here
VOL. II. 33
354 THE OK Y OF KNO W LEDGE
James develops this notion and applies it to religious beliefs,
especially in his Varieties of Religious Experience. All human
functions, not excluding the intellectual function of cognition
or belief, are essentially subservient to practical interests, to life,
conduct, behaviour. Assent is essentially teleological, purposive,
ordained to action. Religious beliefs, like all beliefs, have their
truth-value in the degree of their utility to human existence.
This doctrine he seeks to confirm by the consideration that (<?) dc
facto the cognitive function reveals nothing for certain, as witness
the contradictions of the metaphysicians who use reason in the
attempt to lay bare reality by exploring evidence, and that
(/>) de jure concepts can disclose nothing certain about reality
(cf. Bergson). Hence Pragmatism is more than a method : it is
a doctrine, a theory of knowledge. For it teaches that the truth
of a judgment does not consist in its giving us any insight into
what things really are, but in its working value, in its utility as
prompting and leading to action that is beneficial or helpful to
human progress. Similarly, Dewey holds all cognition to involve
a feeling of expectation or anticipation : by the satisfaction (or
otherwise) of which, in the event, the truth-value of the cognition
is determined.
Schiller enlarged this doctrine into a system called Human
ism, applying it to every department of human speculation and
action. When we reflect on the relation between these two
functions of man, between what intellect conceives by way of
theory or theories on the data of experience, and what it dictates
to us to do, or how to live in and through this experience, we
find four possible interpretations of this relation : (i) Intellect in
its practical dictate is a lower and derivative form of the intel
lect as speculative (a view ascribed by Schiller to Plato) ; (2)
they are mutually irreducible, but the speculative is the higher
(Aristotle} ; (3) they are mutually irreducible, but the practical
holds the primacy (Kant} ; (4) the speculative is a lower and
derivative form of the practical (Humanist Pragmatism}. For
Humanism, then, the truth of a proposition would be its utility
to man : and man would thus be the measure of truth. 1
is a typical illustration : " Metaphysics has hitherto been a piece of amusement for
idle minds, a sort of game at chess ; and the ratio essendi of Pragmatism is to make
a clean sweep of the propositions of ontology, nearly all of which are senseless
rubbish, where words are defined by words and so on without ever reaching any
real concept". The Monist, April, 1905, p. 171, apud JEANNIERE, op. cit., p. 273 n.
1 Cf. The Humanism of Protagoras, in Mind, April, 191 1.
PRAGMATISM 355
It is not, however, utility to the individual that is the test,
but utility to society, to men generally. Look at the general
results of any belief on human progress ; that is the test : Ex
fructibus eorum cognoscetis eos. A proposition is not true merely
because to act on it would suit some individual utility : " it could
not gain currency as effectively true, unless it somehow afforded
satisfaction socially". 1 But social utility can evolve and change.
A belief that " suited " men generally at one time may cease to
serve them any longer ; may indeed disserve them and be re
pudiated. Hence the belief was true, but has become false "
(142, 144). In defence of this view of truth and its criterion
Schiller seeks to show (i) that the intellectualist conception of
truth as mental insight into reality, or cognitive assimilation of
reality, issues in contradictions and cannot account for error ;
(2) that no proposition can have any significance as true or false
unless in relation to the practical issues involved in believing it :
by these alone can its truth-claim be tested, and only in relation
to these is such claim at all intelligible; 3 (3) that psychological
analysis proves man to be always, in all his thinking and judging
functions, influenced by affective motives or interests prompted
by biologically evolved tendencies and impulses of an instinctively
utilitarian order. 4
In France, Boutroux, Milhaud, Poincare, and in Germany,
Simmel, Mach, Hertz, Ostwald, etc., among others, had pro
claimed that the theoretical science attained by reason is but a
system of contingent, conventional conceptions formulated by
reason for the convenience of our practical manipulation or utili-
1 SCHILLER, Error, p. 10, apud JEANNIERE, op. cit., p. 276, n. 3.
2 " Truth and error . . . are continuous, as history shows. Either may de
velop out of the other, and both are rooted in the same problems of knowing, which
are ultimately problems of living. The truths of one generation become the
errors of the next, when it has achieved more valuable and efficient modes of
interpreting and manipulating the apparent facts, which the new truths are
continuously transforming. And conversely, what is now scouted as error may
hereafter become the fruitful parent of a long progeny of truths." Error, p. n,
apud JEANNIERE, p. 277, n. i.
3 Every true or false proposition is relevant to an intention. Error is never
accepted as such, but always presents itself as a. truth-claim : " Truth-claims that
have worked badly are those condemned as errors ; those which have worked
well are those accepted as truths ". Error, apud JEANNIERE, op. cit., p. 276 n.
4 " Purpose, interest, desire, emotion, satisfaction, are more essential to thinking
than steam is to a steam-engine. . . . Without these psychological conditions,
thinking disappears, and with it presumably Logic. The Rationalistic Conception
of Truth (Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 1909, p. 83), apud JEANNIERE,
I.e., n. 2.
23*
3 ,6 THEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
zation of experience: symbolizing results and anticipations of
experience but not attaining to the real. Then Bergson, in his
Matiere et Memoire (1897), Essai sur lesdonnees iinmcdiates de la
conscience (1889), and L Evolution Crfatrice (1907), gradually for
mulated the view that intellectual cognition gives us, in its ab
stract, isolated, fixed and static thought-objects, only evanescent
and kaleidoscopic glances at a reality which is essentially dynamic,
continuous and fluent (86) ; that this intellectual mode of cogni
tion is exclusively practical in its purpose and function, evolved
in order to enable us to adapt our action to our environment, and
not at all to inform us as to what reality really is; that the
mistake of intellectual ism has been to interpret this essentially
practical function as a representation that attains to reality itself ;
that in so far as we attain to reality at all, we do so not by
intellect, but by an active, sympathetic identification of ourselves
with the dynamic process or fieri of our immediate vital experi
ence ; that this immediate vital experience of reality as a dynamic
process (elan vital} or evolution that is sui generis, at once thought
and action (la Pensee-Action, les I dees-Forces]^ may be described
as intuitional, as a vital intuition (at once conscious, volitional,
affective, dynamic), in opposition to the static, abstract, intel
lectual, logical, conceptual and judicial processes which were
wrongly supposed to give us a genuine speculative insight into
reality, whereas they are only practical aids to the vital process
wherein we attain to reality by feeling and living it.
Le Roy combined the conception of scientific laws as mere
practical inventions of the intellect, with Bergson s intuition
theory, to form a " new philosophy " in which the test of practical
vital experience would supplant that of intellectual evidence in
the discerning of truth. The "truths" or laws arrived at by
speculation are not representative of the real : they are simply
aids to the concrete, complex, vital process in which alone reality
is attained, not by contemplating it but by living it. 1 That is
1 " Vivre une verite consiste & en faire un object de vie interieure auquel on
croit, dont on se nourrit, que Ton pratique et que Ton aime au point d unifer en lui
toute son ame : cst vraic dcfimiivement ce qui re siste 1 epreuve d une tclle vie. . . .
" Au fond le seul critere c est la vie. Est Evident d abord tout cc qui est vecu a
chaque instant par nous : images, affections, sentiments, idees ou actes, pris en eux-
metnes et en tant que fails. Est ensuite Evident par le progres de la pensee, tout ce
qui . . . rdsiste a I dpreuve de I: 1 , pratique, peut etre assimile par nous, convert!
en notre substance, integre a notre moi, organise avec 1 ensemble de notre vie.
Ainsi 1 evidence appartient a ce qui se montre capable dc durde. Rien n est Evident
de soi, mais tout peut ledevenir." Unposltivismc twuvcau (in the Revue de Mctapli.
cf Morale, 1901), apud JEANNIEKE, op, cit., p. 279, n. 2.
PRAGMATISM 357
true which stands the test of life s experience, which is felt to
assimilate itself in this process ; while that is false which does not
work, which is rejected, repudiated by this experience. Thus
the agreement of the French school with the American and
English Pragmatism and Humanism is apparent. How a belief
works is the test of its truth. By the extension of this theory to
revealed dogma Le Roy attempted a new theology which was
condemned as incompatible with orthodox Christian belief. 1
In Italy, Papini interpreted Pragmatism as a method from
the standpoint of which every conceivable philosophical theory
or system could be seen to have its share of truth, viz. by con
sidering all theories and systems sub specie actionis, i.e. as pos
sessing a greater or less degree of practical value or utility in the
progressive evolution of humanity : a value which, apparently,
would be tested and determined automatically by the touchstone
of experience, sifting the wheat from the chaff, assimilating the
" useful " or " true " and rejecting the " noxious " or " erroneous ".
This interpretation W. James has felicitously described as " the
corridor-theory " of truth.
Among
the philosophies which, since Kant s time, have employed the
" speculative " reason for its own dethronement, the latest fashion
is undoubtedly that known as Pragmatism or Humanism.
Though of quite recent origin it has to its credit a very ex
tensive output of literature, 1 on the Continent, in England, and
in America its locus originis. Its principal exponents are, in
America, C. S. Peirce, W. James, and J. Dewey ; in England,
F. C. S. Schiller ; in France, Bergson {psychological direction),
Boutroux (critical direction of Poincare and Milhaud), Le Roy
(combining both directions in the "new philosophy") and
Wilbois ; and in Italy, Papini.
It is frankly anti-intellectualist, advocating as the sole test of
truth the practical test of utility in a very broad sense. It is
therefore voluntarist inasmuch as the "utility" of a judgment,
its " bonum utile" is not immediately an object of intellect but of
will. It has not, however, sprung from any preoccupation or
concern with the defence of moral and religious beliefs, but rather
from a teleological consideration of the function and purpose of
thought and knowledge in man, a consideration itself prompted
by the influence of the evolution concept in biological science. 2
For Pragmatism all truth is essentially relative, provisional,
transformable (142, 143).
It was first propounded by C. S. Peirce as a method of ending
the sterile controversies with which the speculative reason is ever
impeding the real progress of the human mind. The sense of
any proposition, and hence its truth or falsity, must be judged
by the mental habit it induces, the effect it has in action, its
pragmatic or working value : hence the title Pragmatism. The
truth or knowledge-value of a proposition is not at all any insight
it is supposed to give us into things, but simply its relation of
utility to human life. 3
1 For adequate bibliography, cf. JEANNIEKE, of. cit., pp. 269-71, whose treat
ment in the main we have followed.
2 Cf. NOEL, Art. in the Revue neo-scolastique, 1911, p. 46.
3 Such a view involves, of course, the abolition of Metaphysics in its traditional
sense of a speculative study of the real. Hence the severity of Pragmatist strictures
on Metaphysics, and the anxiety of Pragmatists to discourage such research. Here
VOL. II. 33
354 THE OK Y OF KNO W LEDGE
James develops this notion and applies it to religious beliefs,
especially in his Varieties of Religious Experience. All human
functions, not excluding the intellectual function of cognition
or belief, are essentially subservient to practical interests, to life,
conduct, behaviour. Assent is essentially teleological, purposive,
ordained to action. Religious beliefs, like all beliefs, have their
truth-value in the degree of their utility to human existence.
This doctrine he seeks to confirm by the consideration that (<?) dc
facto the cognitive function reveals nothing for certain, as witness
the contradictions of the metaphysicians who use reason in the
attempt to lay bare reality by exploring evidence, and that
(/>) de jure concepts can disclose nothing certain about reality
(cf. Bergson). Hence Pragmatism is more than a method : it is
a doctrine, a theory of knowledge. For it teaches that the truth
of a judgment does not consist in its giving us any insight into
what things really are, but in its working value, in its utility as
prompting and leading to action that is beneficial or helpful to
human progress. Similarly, Dewey holds all cognition to involve
a feeling of expectation or anticipation : by the satisfaction (or
otherwise) of which, in the event, the truth-value of the cognition
is determined.
Schiller enlarged this doctrine into a system called Human
ism, applying it to every department of human speculation and
action. When we reflect on the relation between these two
functions of man, between what intellect conceives by way of
theory or theories on the data of experience, and what it dictates
to us to do, or how to live in and through this experience, we
find four possible interpretations of this relation : (i) Intellect in
its practical dictate is a lower and derivative form of the intel
lect as speculative (a view ascribed by Schiller to Plato) ; (2)
they are mutually irreducible, but the speculative is the higher
(Aristotle} ; (3) they are mutually irreducible, but the practical
holds the primacy (Kant} ; (4) the speculative is a lower and
derivative form of the practical (Humanist Pragmatism}. For
Humanism, then, the truth of a proposition would be its utility
to man : and man would thus be the measure of truth. 1
is a typical illustration : " Metaphysics has hitherto been a piece of amusement for
idle minds, a sort of game at chess ; and the ratio essendi of Pragmatism is to make
a clean sweep of the propositions of ontology, nearly all of which are senseless
rubbish, where words are defined by words and so on without ever reaching any
real concept". The Monist, April, 1905, p. 171, apud JEANNIERE, op. cit., p. 273 n.
1 Cf. The Humanism of Protagoras, in Mind, April, 191 1.
PRAGMATISM 355
It is not, however, utility to the individual that is the test,
but utility to society, to men generally. Look at the general
results of any belief on human progress ; that is the test : Ex
fructibus eorum cognoscetis eos. A proposition is not true merely
because to act on it would suit some individual utility : " it could
not gain currency as effectively true, unless it somehow afforded
satisfaction socially". 1 But social utility can evolve and change.
A belief that " suited " men generally at one time may cease to
serve them any longer ; may indeed disserve them and be re
pudiated. Hence the belief was true, but has become false "
(142, 144). In defence of this view of truth and its criterion
Schiller seeks to show (i) that the intellectualist conception of
truth as mental insight into reality, or cognitive assimilation of
reality, issues in contradictions and cannot account for error ;
(2) that no proposition can have any significance as true or false
unless in relation to the practical issues involved in believing it :
by these alone can its truth-claim be tested, and only in relation
to these is such claim at all intelligible; 3 (3) that psychological
analysis proves man to be always, in all his thinking and judging
functions, influenced by affective motives or interests prompted
by biologically evolved tendencies and impulses of an instinctively
utilitarian order. 4
In France, Boutroux, Milhaud, Poincare, and in Germany,
Simmel, Mach, Hertz, Ostwald, etc., among others, had pro
claimed that the theoretical science attained by reason is but a
system of contingent, conventional conceptions formulated by
reason for the convenience of our practical manipulation or utili-
1 SCHILLER, Error, p. 10, apud JEANNIERE, op. cit., p. 276, n. 3.
2 " Truth and error . . . are continuous, as history shows. Either may de
velop out of the other, and both are rooted in the same problems of knowing, which
are ultimately problems of living. The truths of one generation become the
errors of the next, when it has achieved more valuable and efficient modes of
interpreting and manipulating the apparent facts, which the new truths are
continuously transforming. And conversely, what is now scouted as error may
hereafter become the fruitful parent of a long progeny of truths." Error, p. n,
apud JEANNIERE, p. 277, n. i.
3 Every true or false proposition is relevant to an intention. Error is never
accepted as such, but always presents itself as a. truth-claim : " Truth-claims that
have worked badly are those condemned as errors ; those which have worked
well are those accepted as truths ". Error, apud JEANNIERE, op. cit., p. 276 n.
4 " Purpose, interest, desire, emotion, satisfaction, are more essential to thinking
than steam is to a steam-engine. . . . Without these psychological conditions,
thinking disappears, and with it presumably Logic. The Rationalistic Conception
of Truth (Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 1909, p. 83), apud JEANNIERE,
I.e., n. 2.
23*
3 ,6 THEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
zation of experience: symbolizing results and anticipations of
experience but not attaining to the real. Then Bergson, in his
Matiere et Memoire (1897), Essai sur lesdonnees iinmcdiates de la
conscience (1889), and L Evolution Crfatrice (1907), gradually for
mulated the view that intellectual cognition gives us, in its ab
stract, isolated, fixed and static thought-objects, only evanescent
and kaleidoscopic glances at a reality which is essentially dynamic,
continuous and fluent (86) ; that this intellectual mode of cogni
tion is exclusively practical in its purpose and function, evolved
in order to enable us to adapt our action to our environment, and
not at all to inform us as to what reality really is; that the
mistake of intellectual ism has been to interpret this essentially
practical function as a representation that attains to reality itself ;
that in so far as we attain to reality at all, we do so not by
intellect, but by an active, sympathetic identification of ourselves
with the dynamic process or fieri of our immediate vital experi
ence ; that this immediate vital experience of reality as a dynamic
process (elan vital} or evolution that is sui generis, at once thought
and action (la Pensee-Action, les I dees-Forces]^ may be described
as intuitional, as a vital intuition (at once conscious, volitional,
affective, dynamic), in opposition to the static, abstract, intel
lectual, logical, conceptual and judicial processes which were
wrongly supposed to give us a genuine speculative insight into
reality, whereas they are only practical aids to the vital process
wherein we attain to reality by feeling and living it.
Le Roy combined the conception of scientific laws as mere
practical inventions of the intellect, with Bergson s intuition
theory, to form a " new philosophy " in which the test of practical
vital experience would supplant that of intellectual evidence in
the discerning of truth. The "truths" or laws arrived at by
speculation are not representative of the real : they are simply
aids to the concrete, complex, vital process in which alone reality
is attained, not by contemplating it but by living it. 1 That is
1 " Vivre une verite consiste & en faire un object de vie interieure auquel on
croit, dont on se nourrit, que Ton pratique et que Ton aime au point d unifer en lui
toute son ame : cst vraic dcfimiivement ce qui re siste 1 epreuve d une tclle vie. . . .
" Au fond le seul critere c est la vie. Est Evident d abord tout cc qui est vecu a
chaque instant par nous : images, affections, sentiments, idees ou actes, pris en eux-
metnes et en tant que fails. Est ensuite Evident par le progres de la pensee, tout ce
qui . . . rdsiste a I dpreuve de I: 1 , pratique, peut etre assimile par nous, convert!
en notre substance, integre a notre moi, organise avec 1 ensemble de notre vie.
Ainsi 1 evidence appartient a ce qui se montre capable dc durde. Rien n est Evident
de soi, mais tout peut ledevenir." Unposltivismc twuvcau (in the Revue de Mctapli.
cf Morale, 1901), apud JEANNIEKE, op, cit., p. 279, n. 2.
PRAGMATISM 357
true which stands the test of life s experience, which is felt to
assimilate itself in this process ; while that is false which does not
work, which is rejected, repudiated by this experience. Thus
the agreement of the French school with the American and
English Pragmatism and Humanism is apparent. How a belief
works is the test of its truth. By the extension of this theory to
revealed dogma Le Roy attempted a new theology which was
condemned as incompatible with orthodox Christian belief. 1
In Italy, Papini interpreted Pragmatism as a method from
the standpoint of which every conceivable philosophical theory
or system could be seen to have its share of truth, viz. by con
sidering all theories and systems sub specie actionis, i.e. as pos
sessing a greater or less degree of practical value or utility in the
progressive evolution of humanity : a value which, apparently,
would be tested and determined automatically by the touchstone
of experience, sifting the wheat from the chaff, assimilating the
" useful " or " true " and rejecting the " noxious " or " erroneous ".
This interpretation W. James has felicitously described as " the
corridor-theory " of truth.