INTELLECT.
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 44 46 48 49
52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66
68 69 70 71 75 76 78 79 80 81 83
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101
102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 112 113 114 115 117 118
119 120 121 122 123 124 125 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135
138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148
The scholastic analysis of sense data into " proper "
and " common " sensibles may possibly mislead by reason of its
incompleteness : especially in view of the fact that the " primary
qualities" or common sensibles" are claimed on the one hand
to be themselves percepts and on the other hand to be (as to what
they really are) less relative to, and more independent of, the
nature and conditions of the self as percipient subject, than the
" proper sensibles" are ; and to furnish to the abstractive faculty
of thought more distinctively " external " or " non-self" data than
the proper sensibles do for our intellectual knowledge of a real,
external, three-dimensional, spatial universe. 1
The fact that the sensible features of " externality," and
"extensity" or " voluminousness," are furnished simultaneously
in different qualities of conscious data (e.g. in visual and tactual
sensations), and not only as unified in a subjective unity of
consciousness, but also as unified in one spatial and external
continuum having colour, resistance, volume, shape, motion, etc.,
this fact undoubtedly presents to intellect, reflecting intro-
spectively on sense perception, the strongest evidence in justifica
tion of the spontaneously assumed objective and real validity of
our concepts of " extension" and "space". In other words the
"sense evidence," or "appearance to sense" of extensity and ex
ternality attaching to concrete data, apprehended by sense as
voluminous or space-filling (size\ as continuous or discontinuous
(unity, number\ as having definite limits (shape), as at rest or in
motion, is also " intellectual evidence," or "appearance to in
tellect" of these same data intellectually conceived as an external
1 " The perfect identity of ratios subsisting between parts of space, e.g. the re
lation of the side to the diagonal of the square, known through visual and tactual
sensations, the mathematical power of the blind, the recognition of circular and
square figures by those just receiving sight for the first time, present an irresistible
testimony to the reality of what is affirmed by such diverse witnesses. In addition
to this the manifestation of extension in the two different experiences of colour and
pressure enables us to detach in a singularly perfect manner the common element,
and so to form an abstract idea of extension, far surpassing in clearness those derived
from any single sensuous channel." MAHER, op. cit., p. 157; cf. ibid., pp. 101,
159-62.
76 THEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
universe of spatially extended real bodies. That is a fact which
we have already emphasized (105). But here we want to
scrutinize the "perceptual" character of those primary qualities
or common sensibles in relation to the various " concepts" which
thought abstracts from sense data.
Whatever can be perceived in the concrete by sense can be
conceived in the abstract by intellect. Whatever is " sensible "
is likewise " intelligible "- 1 Of every single concrete sense datum
and of every concrete complex of such data, of every " sensibile
proprium " and of every unified or composite datum (or " sensibile
commune") presented by the joint action of different external
senses, and of the inner or " common " sense or faculty of associa
tion (the " sensus communis" of the scholastics), we have or
can have an abstract intellectual concept. But the functions of
these various external and internal senses, whether in isolation
or in conjunction with one another, are confined merely to report
ing or registering Q* presenting some concrete (simple or complex)
datum in consciousness. So far as the senses go, these data are
all, so to speak, inarticulate^ uninterpreted, without meaning:"
each is simply a "something there," a " something present". It
is intellect that must give each a meaning by conceiving it as some
mode or other of reality, as a colour, taste, sound, etc. ; as si/e,
shape, motion, rest, etc. ; as a quality, relation, action, cause, sub
stance, etc. 3
1 Is whatever is intelligible (or an object of thought) also sensible (or an object
of sense) ? To say that whatever is intelligible must be also itself an object of sense
(a " sensibile per se ") would be sensism. And Kant s position, that although we
can think or conceive the suprasensible we cannot know it to be real,- is near to
this. The truth is that whatever is intelligible (to the human mind), although it
need not be itself an object of sense (a " sensibile /r se "), must nevertheless be
cognitively conjoined with something that is itself an object of sense. That is, it
must be either a " sensibile per accideiis," like the essences, substances, causes, rela
tions, etc., apprehended in our direct (sensuous and intellectual) experience, or some
thing the reality of which we can prove to be necessarily implied by this experience,
and which we can conceive only analogically, or by concepts which have their
proper application to realities that are themselves directly sensible. Cf. vol. i., 65,
66, 74, 77.
-"Meaning" is something essentially rational, intellectual, conceptual.
3 Cf. art. Appearance and Reality, by the present writer, in the Irish Ecclesi
astical Record, vol. xxiv. (September, 1908), pp. 275-80. The article is the second
of a series of three in the same volume; and these are a continuation of an earlier
series under the title, Subject and Object in Knowledge and Conscioiisness, in the pre
ceding volume (xxiii., April, May, and June, 1908) of the same periodical. As the
articles discuss in some detail many points in connexion with consciousness, know
ledge, perception, conception, phenomenism, Kantism, etc., it may not be amiss to
give this reference to them.
PERCEPTION OF SENSE QUALITIES 77
When we think and speak even of a " proper sensible," such
as red, redness, and say that " redness is a proper object of the
sense of vision" we must remember that this sense does not ap
prehend " redness " in the abstract, but merely that it apprehends
an individual, concrete datum which intellect simultaneously con
ceives in the abstract, and to which intellect gives the name red,
redness : conceiving it also at the same time as a thing or reality,
an accident or quality, a colour, of some substance. And so of the
other proper sensibles.
But by the simultaneous functioning of the separate external
senses, and of the unifying and associating faculty of the internal
sense or sensus communis, we have also presented in sense con
sciousness complex or composite concrete data in which intellect
apprehends or conceives such thought-objects as unity or con
tinuity ; plurality or multitude ; volume, magnitude, or three-
dimensional extension ; form, -igure, or shape ; rest or motion.
Now when these are called " common sensibles" it is not meant
that each of them is apprehended in the abstract (and known and
named as such) by any joint action of the senses. It is only meant
that the individual, concrete data, from which intellect abstracts
these thought-objects, are complex or composite data for the
presence of which in sense-consciousness the functioning of more
than one external sense is needed. Nor is it implied that any
such composite sense-datum has in it any sense element beyond
the sensibilia propria contributed by the separate senses (external
and internal) which co-operated in presenting it to consciousness.
Of course the perception of such a composite datum as a
"sensibile commune" involves the conscious discrimination, as
sociation, and co-ordination or unification of the proper objects
of sight, passive contact, active touch or muscular and motor
sensations : their unification not only in a subjective unity of
consciousness but in an objective unity of composite datum or
content. Now, there are of course intellectual functions of dis
criminating, associating, co-ordinating, unifying, etc. functions
which enter into the process of comparing, judging, interpreting.
But, subserving these, there are analogous sense functions which
belong to the internal sense or " sensus communis" the faculty
of sensuous association : * an organic or sense faculty of the
sentient conscious being, having in the brain and nervous system
partly the same physiological basis as the external senses, and
1 Cf. MAHER, op. cit., pp. 92-6, 197-9.
78 THEOR Y OF KNO WLEDGE
possessed not only by man but by animals generally. By means
of this internal sense the sentient-conscious being can apprehend
in the concrete relations l of co-existence and sequence, perman
ence and change, similarity and diversity, among its sense data ;
and can have feelings of " recalled " or " remembered " or " past "
data, and " anticipations " of future similar data. But these are
all concrete percepts, not abstract concepts. They do not involve
the essentially rational or intellectual process whereby we ap
prehend "relation," "difference," "similarity," "duration,"
"sequence," etc., as such or in the abstract: i.e. by which we
apprehend the essence (or " quidditas ") of the presented datum,
or what the concrete datum is.
When, therefore, we speak of three-dimensional extension
or size or volume, of shape or form, of multitude or number, of
rest or motion, as " primary (sense] qualities " or as " common
sensible*" we must distinguish between the concrete condition in
which alone they can be percepts or sense data, and the abstract
condition in which they are conceived by intellect as objects of
thought. If in the former condition we claim them to be percepts,
"common" percepts, but nevertheless real percepts or objects
of sense awareness, " sensibilia per se," we must remember that
we have called in the aid of the internal or " common " sense,
or faculty of sensuous association, unification, etc., to make
them so.
But intellect conceives in the abstract not only those "com
mon " sense data, but also each of the " sensibilia propria " or
proper sense data : the function of abstract thought is closely
allied with every conscious sense cognition. Hence in their ab
stract condition the proper sensibles are objects of intellect, of
thought or conception ; and conversely it is only in their concrete
condition that the so-called common sensibles are indeed really
objects of sense.
But intellect furthermore apprehends in the abstract, in and
through the (proper and common) data of sense, i.e. by reflecting
1 Sense can apprehend a concrete individual relation between two or more con
crete individual sense terms, though it cannot apprehend relation in the abstract, or
what a relation is. Cf. vol. i., 91, iii. ; PRICHARD, op. cit., pp. 228-9. The scholastics
sometimes spoke of this sensuous apprehension of relations between associated sense
terms as sensuous" judgment " after the analogy of intellectual comparison or judg
ment proper. Apart from instinct, these sensuous apprehensions of concrete rel?-
tions explain animal " memories," " anticipations," " inferences," etc., and constitute
portion of the domain of what is commonly called "animal intelligence".
PERCEPTION OF SENSE QUALITIES 79
on, and interpreting, and reasoning from, these latter, 1 certain
thought-objects, of which it is assumed that the senses alone
could not make us cognizant even in the concrete : and these
are described as being objects of sense only "per accidens," i.e. by
being really conjoined with data which are themselves (proper or
common) objects of sense. The "common sensibles " no less
than the " proper sensibles " are claimed by scholastics to be
direct data of sense perception, to be percepts, not concepts. This
they express by saying that both the " proper " and the
"common" sensibles are " sensibilia/^r se," i.e. that they are
themselves objects of the senses, as distinct from certain other
data or objects of knowledge which cannot be designated " ob
jects of sense" except " per accidens" . These other objects of
knowledge are themselves data of intellect, and can be only de
scribed as being " accidentally or concomitantly sensible " (" sensi-
bilia per accidens ") : because they are objectively conjoined with
the data that are " sensibilia per se" or objects of sense percep
tion proper, and are apprehended by the intellectual faculty
which is subjectively a faculty of the same conscious self that
possesses the sense faculties. Thus, substance is not itself a
datum of any sense. Substance, and the various kinds of sub
stances, simple and composite, spiritual and material, and cause,
and relation, and their various kinds, are themselves objects of
intellect, conceived objects, " intelligibila " per se? Yet, although
we see only coloured surface, and taste only such a sense quality
as sweet, and touch only a hard, cold, resisting surface, we never
theless say, " I see a man, 1 " I taste honey," " I feel ice" etc. 3
But "man," "honey," "ice," etc., are substances, and, as such,
are objects only of thought or conception, not of perception.
Hence, as such, they can be said to be perceptible or sensible
only per accidens, inasmuch as the concrete data which are directly
1 Has intellect any concrete intuitions of its own, independently of sense
activity, from which also to derive abstract thought-objects ? " Nihil est in intellectu
quod prius non fuerit \aliquo modo saltern per accidens] in sensu ? " Cf. vol. i.,
74. 77 ; supra, 100, 105.
2 Cf. Ontology ,62, p. 218.
3 Similarly I may say " I see the sweet honey ". But I do not really see the
sweetness. Sweetness is itself (" per se ") an object only of taste. What I see is
the coloured surface of that which I otherwise know to be also sweet. Thus sweet
ness is indirectly or concomitantly an object of vision : it is " visibile per accidens ".
To be thus an object per accidens of any faculty, a datum must be (i) itself an ob
ject per se of some other faculty, and (2) objectively conjoined with what is an
object per se of the former faculty. Cf. JEANNIERE, op. cit., pp. 386-7.
So THE OK Y OF A NO W LEDGE
attained by sense really and objectively embody these other ob
jects which are apprehended only by intellect, viz., substance,
cause, matter, spirit, intellect, will, thought, volition, etc.
Now it might, perhaps, be maintained that sense docs make us aware of
all these objects in the concrete : that it makes us aware of material substance
in the concrete, and therefore of substance and all its accidents, of being or
reality and all its modes, in the concrete : and that therefore all knowable
modes of reality are themselves (per sc} objects of sense in the concrete as well
as of intellect in the abstract : so that all intelligibilia per se (as abstract}
would be scnsibilia per accidens, just as all sensibilia per se (as concrete) would
be intelligibilia per accidens.^
If this latter assertion were understood in the sense which we have ex
plained as the true meaning of the aphorism, Nihil est in intellcciu quod
prius non fucrit in sensu, i.e. if it were understood to mean that all modes
of reality which become intelligible to the human intellect become objects of
the latter only through concepts which, being derived from sense data, are
properly applicable only to the per se sensible or material modes of reality,
the modes that are made " immaterial " or " intelligible " only " negatively " or
" by abstraction " (71, 74, 76), it might be allowed to pass as admissible.
But if it (and the assertion immediately preceding it) were understood to mean
that only such modes of reality as are themselves, per se, sensible, are intel
ligible and knowable by the human mind, these assertions would then be ex
pressions of the erroneous doctrine of Sensism?
As a matter of fact sense does not make us aware of substance, or of
material substance, or of cause, spirit, intellect, volition, etc., even in the con
crete. We may, no doubt, say that it makes us aware of materiality in the con
crete ; for materiality in the concrete means just all those concrete qualities,
proper and common, which are themselves ^ per sc, objects of sense. But if
we were merely sentient beings, like the lower animals, and had no higher or
rational cognitive faculty, we could never attain to any awareness of substance,
cause, spirit, intellect, will, etc., even though we sensuously apprehended
beings which were really substances and causes, which really had a spiritual
nature and spiritual faculties such as intellect and will. To say that such
modes of being are for us "sensibilia per accidens " is really another way of
saying that we do not sensuously perceive them at all, but that intellect con
ceives or apprehends them in and with the data which we do sensuously
perceive.
Now all the positive content of our concepts of substance, cause, attribute
Are space and time "per se intelligible" or "per sc sensible"? Are they
per se " concepts," objects of intellect, or per sc " percepts " objects of sense. Per se
they are concepts, objects of intellect ; for the terms space and time express abstract
objects. They are sensible, or objects of sense, only per accidens. They are per se
neither proper nor common sensibles. No one sense and no combination of senses
can perceive them. They are objects elaborated by thought through the addition
of rational relations (entia rationis) to our concepts of the "common sensibles," ex
tension and motion respectively. Cf. Ontology, 84, 85.
2 Cf. supra, p. 76, n. i.
PERCEPTION OF SENSE QUALITIES 81
or accident, quality, power, faculty, relation, action, etc., is derived from the
" material " data of sense consciousness, together with the data furnished by
reflection on the immediate intuitions we have of our own higher (intellectual
and volitional) activities (71, 100, 105). But intellect, reflecting on those
concepts, and on all the data of our conscious experience, can see that those
concepts or thought-objects, considered apart from the sense-data in which
they were originally apprehended, are applicable to modes of reality that are
not themselves, or per se, sensible ; can see the possibility of such positively
immaterial motes of reality ; and can infer the actual existence of such modes
of being the rational, intelligent, spiritual, human soul with its spiritual
faculties ; and the Divine, Infinite, Necessary Being or First Cause as neces
sarily involved in, and implied by, the direct data of conscious human experi
ence (71). And it can see at the same time that such concepts, though they
can be applied to such positively suprasensible or immaterial realities only by
emptying them of their sensible or material content (via negationis], can give
us a knowledge which, though negative and analogical, is nevertheless, so far
as it goes, an objectively and really valid knowledge of such suprasensible or
spiritual domains of being (66, 74, 100).
The scholastic analysis of sense data into " proper "
and " common " sensibles may possibly mislead by reason of its
incompleteness : especially in view of the fact that the " primary
qualities" or common sensibles" are claimed on the one hand
to be themselves percepts and on the other hand to be (as to what
they really are) less relative to, and more independent of, the
nature and conditions of the self as percipient subject, than the
" proper sensibles" are ; and to furnish to the abstractive faculty
of thought more distinctively " external " or " non-self" data than
the proper sensibles do for our intellectual knowledge of a real,
external, three-dimensional, spatial universe. 1
The fact that the sensible features of " externality," and
"extensity" or " voluminousness," are furnished simultaneously
in different qualities of conscious data (e.g. in visual and tactual
sensations), and not only as unified in a subjective unity of
consciousness, but also as unified in one spatial and external
continuum having colour, resistance, volume, shape, motion, etc.,
this fact undoubtedly presents to intellect, reflecting intro-
spectively on sense perception, the strongest evidence in justifica
tion of the spontaneously assumed objective and real validity of
our concepts of " extension" and "space". In other words the
"sense evidence," or "appearance to sense" of extensity and ex
ternality attaching to concrete data, apprehended by sense as
voluminous or space-filling (size\ as continuous or discontinuous
(unity, number\ as having definite limits (shape), as at rest or in
motion, is also " intellectual evidence," or "appearance to in
tellect" of these same data intellectually conceived as an external
1 " The perfect identity of ratios subsisting between parts of space, e.g. the re
lation of the side to the diagonal of the square, known through visual and tactual
sensations, the mathematical power of the blind, the recognition of circular and
square figures by those just receiving sight for the first time, present an irresistible
testimony to the reality of what is affirmed by such diverse witnesses. In addition
to this the manifestation of extension in the two different experiences of colour and
pressure enables us to detach in a singularly perfect manner the common element,
and so to form an abstract idea of extension, far surpassing in clearness those derived
from any single sensuous channel." MAHER, op. cit., p. 157; cf. ibid., pp. 101,
159-62.
76 THEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
universe of spatially extended real bodies. That is a fact which
we have already emphasized (105). But here we want to
scrutinize the "perceptual" character of those primary qualities
or common sensibles in relation to the various " concepts" which
thought abstracts from sense data.
Whatever can be perceived in the concrete by sense can be
conceived in the abstract by intellect. Whatever is " sensible "
is likewise " intelligible "- 1 Of every single concrete sense datum
and of every concrete complex of such data, of every " sensibile
proprium " and of every unified or composite datum (or " sensibile
commune") presented by the joint action of different external
senses, and of the inner or " common " sense or faculty of associa
tion (the " sensus communis" of the scholastics), we have or
can have an abstract intellectual concept. But the functions of
these various external and internal senses, whether in isolation
or in conjunction with one another, are confined merely to report
ing or registering Q* presenting some concrete (simple or complex)
datum in consciousness. So far as the senses go, these data are
all, so to speak, inarticulate^ uninterpreted, without meaning:"
each is simply a "something there," a " something present". It
is intellect that must give each a meaning by conceiving it as some
mode or other of reality, as a colour, taste, sound, etc. ; as si/e,
shape, motion, rest, etc. ; as a quality, relation, action, cause, sub
stance, etc. 3
1 Is whatever is intelligible (or an object of thought) also sensible (or an object
of sense) ? To say that whatever is intelligible must be also itself an object of sense
(a " sensibile per se ") would be sensism. And Kant s position, that although we
can think or conceive the suprasensible we cannot know it to be real,- is near to
this. The truth is that whatever is intelligible (to the human mind), although it
need not be itself an object of sense (a " sensibile /r se "), must nevertheless be
cognitively conjoined with something that is itself an object of sense. That is, it
must be either a " sensibile per accideiis," like the essences, substances, causes, rela
tions, etc., apprehended in our direct (sensuous and intellectual) experience, or some
thing the reality of which we can prove to be necessarily implied by this experience,
and which we can conceive only analogically, or by concepts which have their
proper application to realities that are themselves directly sensible. Cf. vol. i., 65,
66, 74, 77.
-"Meaning" is something essentially rational, intellectual, conceptual.
3 Cf. art. Appearance and Reality, by the present writer, in the Irish Ecclesi
astical Record, vol. xxiv. (September, 1908), pp. 275-80. The article is the second
of a series of three in the same volume; and these are a continuation of an earlier
series under the title, Subject and Object in Knowledge and Conscioiisness, in the pre
ceding volume (xxiii., April, May, and June, 1908) of the same periodical. As the
articles discuss in some detail many points in connexion with consciousness, know
ledge, perception, conception, phenomenism, Kantism, etc., it may not be amiss to
give this reference to them.
PERCEPTION OF SENSE QUALITIES 77
When we think and speak even of a " proper sensible," such
as red, redness, and say that " redness is a proper object of the
sense of vision" we must remember that this sense does not ap
prehend " redness " in the abstract, but merely that it apprehends
an individual, concrete datum which intellect simultaneously con
ceives in the abstract, and to which intellect gives the name red,
redness : conceiving it also at the same time as a thing or reality,
an accident or quality, a colour, of some substance. And so of the
other proper sensibles.
But by the simultaneous functioning of the separate external
senses, and of the unifying and associating faculty of the internal
sense or sensus communis, we have also presented in sense con
sciousness complex or composite concrete data in which intellect
apprehends or conceives such thought-objects as unity or con
tinuity ; plurality or multitude ; volume, magnitude, or three-
dimensional extension ; form, -igure, or shape ; rest or motion.
Now when these are called " common sensibles" it is not meant
that each of them is apprehended in the abstract (and known and
named as such) by any joint action of the senses. It is only meant
that the individual, concrete data, from which intellect abstracts
these thought-objects, are complex or composite data for the
presence of which in sense-consciousness the functioning of more
than one external sense is needed. Nor is it implied that any
such composite sense-datum has in it any sense element beyond
the sensibilia propria contributed by the separate senses (external
and internal) which co-operated in presenting it to consciousness.
Of course the perception of such a composite datum as a
"sensibile commune" involves the conscious discrimination, as
sociation, and co-ordination or unification of the proper objects
of sight, passive contact, active touch or muscular and motor
sensations : their unification not only in a subjective unity of
consciousness but in an objective unity of composite datum or
content. Now, there are of course intellectual functions of dis
criminating, associating, co-ordinating, unifying, etc. functions
which enter into the process of comparing, judging, interpreting.
But, subserving these, there are analogous sense functions which
belong to the internal sense or " sensus communis" the faculty
of sensuous association : * an organic or sense faculty of the
sentient conscious being, having in the brain and nervous system
partly the same physiological basis as the external senses, and
1 Cf. MAHER, op. cit., pp. 92-6, 197-9.
78 THEOR Y OF KNO WLEDGE
possessed not only by man but by animals generally. By means
of this internal sense the sentient-conscious being can apprehend
in the concrete relations l of co-existence and sequence, perman
ence and change, similarity and diversity, among its sense data ;
and can have feelings of " recalled " or " remembered " or " past "
data, and " anticipations " of future similar data. But these are
all concrete percepts, not abstract concepts. They do not involve
the essentially rational or intellectual process whereby we ap
prehend "relation," "difference," "similarity," "duration,"
"sequence," etc., as such or in the abstract: i.e. by which we
apprehend the essence (or " quidditas ") of the presented datum,
or what the concrete datum is.
When, therefore, we speak of three-dimensional extension
or size or volume, of shape or form, of multitude or number, of
rest or motion, as " primary (sense] qualities " or as " common
sensible*" we must distinguish between the concrete condition in
which alone they can be percepts or sense data, and the abstract
condition in which they are conceived by intellect as objects of
thought. If in the former condition we claim them to be percepts,
"common" percepts, but nevertheless real percepts or objects
of sense awareness, " sensibilia per se," we must remember that
we have called in the aid of the internal or " common " sense,
or faculty of sensuous association, unification, etc., to make
them so.
But intellect conceives in the abstract not only those "com
mon " sense data, but also each of the " sensibilia propria " or
proper sense data : the function of abstract thought is closely
allied with every conscious sense cognition. Hence in their ab
stract condition the proper sensibles are objects of intellect, of
thought or conception ; and conversely it is only in their concrete
condition that the so-called common sensibles are indeed really
objects of sense.
But intellect furthermore apprehends in the abstract, in and
through the (proper and common) data of sense, i.e. by reflecting
1 Sense can apprehend a concrete individual relation between two or more con
crete individual sense terms, though it cannot apprehend relation in the abstract, or
what a relation is. Cf. vol. i., 91, iii. ; PRICHARD, op. cit., pp. 228-9. The scholastics
sometimes spoke of this sensuous apprehension of relations between associated sense
terms as sensuous" judgment " after the analogy of intellectual comparison or judg
ment proper. Apart from instinct, these sensuous apprehensions of concrete rel?-
tions explain animal " memories," " anticipations," " inferences," etc., and constitute
portion of the domain of what is commonly called "animal intelligence".
PERCEPTION OF SENSE QUALITIES 79
on, and interpreting, and reasoning from, these latter, 1 certain
thought-objects, of which it is assumed that the senses alone
could not make us cognizant even in the concrete : and these
are described as being objects of sense only "per accidens," i.e. by
being really conjoined with data which are themselves (proper or
common) objects of sense. The "common sensibles " no less
than the " proper sensibles " are claimed by scholastics to be
direct data of sense perception, to be percepts, not concepts. This
they express by saying that both the " proper " and the
"common" sensibles are " sensibilia/^r se," i.e. that they are
themselves objects of the senses, as distinct from certain other
data or objects of knowledge which cannot be designated " ob
jects of sense" except " per accidens" . These other objects of
knowledge are themselves data of intellect, and can be only de
scribed as being " accidentally or concomitantly sensible " (" sensi-
bilia per accidens ") : because they are objectively conjoined with
the data that are " sensibilia per se" or objects of sense percep
tion proper, and are apprehended by the intellectual faculty
which is subjectively a faculty of the same conscious self that
possesses the sense faculties. Thus, substance is not itself a
datum of any sense. Substance, and the various kinds of sub
stances, simple and composite, spiritual and material, and cause,
and relation, and their various kinds, are themselves objects of
intellect, conceived objects, " intelligibila " per se? Yet, although
we see only coloured surface, and taste only such a sense quality
as sweet, and touch only a hard, cold, resisting surface, we never
theless say, " I see a man, 1 " I taste honey," " I feel ice" etc. 3
But "man," "honey," "ice," etc., are substances, and, as such,
are objects only of thought or conception, not of perception.
Hence, as such, they can be said to be perceptible or sensible
only per accidens, inasmuch as the concrete data which are directly
1 Has intellect any concrete intuitions of its own, independently of sense
activity, from which also to derive abstract thought-objects ? " Nihil est in intellectu
quod prius non fuerit \aliquo modo saltern per accidens] in sensu ? " Cf. vol. i.,
74. 77 ; supra, 100, 105.
2 Cf. Ontology ,62, p. 218.
3 Similarly I may say " I see the sweet honey ". But I do not really see the
sweetness. Sweetness is itself (" per se ") an object only of taste. What I see is
the coloured surface of that which I otherwise know to be also sweet. Thus sweet
ness is indirectly or concomitantly an object of vision : it is " visibile per accidens ".
To be thus an object per accidens of any faculty, a datum must be (i) itself an ob
ject per se of some other faculty, and (2) objectively conjoined with what is an
object per se of the former faculty. Cf. JEANNIERE, op. cit., pp. 386-7.
So THE OK Y OF A NO W LEDGE
attained by sense really and objectively embody these other ob
jects which are apprehended only by intellect, viz., substance,
cause, matter, spirit, intellect, will, thought, volition, etc.
Now it might, perhaps, be maintained that sense docs make us aware of
all these objects in the concrete : that it makes us aware of material substance
in the concrete, and therefore of substance and all its accidents, of being or
reality and all its modes, in the concrete : and that therefore all knowable
modes of reality are themselves (per sc} objects of sense in the concrete as well
as of intellect in the abstract : so that all intelligibilia per se (as abstract}
would be scnsibilia per accidens, just as all sensibilia per se (as concrete) would
be intelligibilia per accidens.^
If this latter assertion were understood in the sense which we have ex
plained as the true meaning of the aphorism, Nihil est in intellcciu quod
prius non fucrit in sensu, i.e. if it were understood to mean that all modes
of reality which become intelligible to the human intellect become objects of
the latter only through concepts which, being derived from sense data, are
properly applicable only to the per se sensible or material modes of reality,
the modes that are made " immaterial " or " intelligible " only " negatively " or
" by abstraction " (71, 74, 76), it might be allowed to pass as admissible.
But if it (and the assertion immediately preceding it) were understood to mean
that only such modes of reality as are themselves, per se, sensible, are intel
ligible and knowable by the human mind, these assertions would then be ex
pressions of the erroneous doctrine of Sensism?
As a matter of fact sense does not make us aware of substance, or of
material substance, or of cause, spirit, intellect, volition, etc., even in the con
crete. We may, no doubt, say that it makes us aware of materiality in the con
crete ; for materiality in the concrete means just all those concrete qualities,
proper and common, which are themselves ^ per sc, objects of sense. But if
we were merely sentient beings, like the lower animals, and had no higher or
rational cognitive faculty, we could never attain to any awareness of substance,
cause, spirit, intellect, will, etc., even though we sensuously apprehended
beings which were really substances and causes, which really had a spiritual
nature and spiritual faculties such as intellect and will. To say that such
modes of being are for us "sensibilia per accidens " is really another way of
saying that we do not sensuously perceive them at all, but that intellect con
ceives or apprehends them in and with the data which we do sensuously
perceive.
Now all the positive content of our concepts of substance, cause, attribute
Are space and time "per se intelligible" or "per sc sensible"? Are they
per se " concepts," objects of intellect, or per sc " percepts " objects of sense. Per se
they are concepts, objects of intellect ; for the terms space and time express abstract
objects. They are sensible, or objects of sense, only per accidens. They are per se
neither proper nor common sensibles. No one sense and no combination of senses
can perceive them. They are objects elaborated by thought through the addition
of rational relations (entia rationis) to our concepts of the "common sensibles," ex
tension and motion respectively. Cf. Ontology, 84, 85.
2 Cf. supra, p. 76, n. i.
PERCEPTION OF SENSE QUALITIES 81
or accident, quality, power, faculty, relation, action, etc., is derived from the
" material " data of sense consciousness, together with the data furnished by
reflection on the immediate intuitions we have of our own higher (intellectual
and volitional) activities (71, 100, 105). But intellect, reflecting on those
concepts, and on all the data of our conscious experience, can see that those
concepts or thought-objects, considered apart from the sense-data in which
they were originally apprehended, are applicable to modes of reality that are
not themselves, or per se, sensible ; can see the possibility of such positively
immaterial motes of reality ; and can infer the actual existence of such modes
of being the rational, intelligent, spiritual, human soul with its spiritual
faculties ; and the Divine, Infinite, Necessary Being or First Cause as neces
sarily involved in, and implied by, the direct data of conscious human experi
ence (71). And it can see at the same time that such concepts, though they
can be applied to such positively suprasensible or immaterial realities only by
emptying them of their sensible or material content (via negationis], can give
us a knowledge which, though negative and analogical, is nevertheless, so far
as it goes, an objectively and really valid knowledge of such suprasensible or
spiritual domains of being (66, 74, 100).