REASONED CERTITUDE.
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101
102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 111 112 113 114 115 117 118
119 120 121 122 123 124 125 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135
138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148
A few points, however, call for notice.
First, when scholastics emphasize the doctrine that the immediate
objective evidence of axioms of the ideal order is the supreme
criterion of all truth and the ultimate motive of all human certi
tude, they are not to be understood as implying that the evidence
we have for the judgments that are of the most profound im
portance to the human race can be reduced to such evidence (cf.
148). The true solutions of the great problems concerning the
origin, nature, and destiny of man and the universe, concerning
the immortality of the soul, the existence of God, the reality of
the moral order, the obligation and sanctions of religion, are,
needless to say, not immediately evident. Indeed no solutions
of these problems are immediately evident. Nor can the true
solutions of them be deduced from self-evident axioms of the
ideal order by any process of pure deductive reasoning, of which
every step would be cogently self-evident (35) : such, for instance,
as the reasoning employed in pure mathematics. Their solution
involves mixed demonstration. 1 It therefore implies certitude
about some judgments of the existential order ; it implies that
abstract concepts and principles are validly applicable to the
actually experienced order of concrete, existing things, i.e. it
implies the truth of Moderate Realism ; and finally it implies
well-grounded certitude on our part that in the actual process of
applying concepts to percepts, of interpreting singulars by uni-
versals, of locating the intellectual abstract in the sense concrete, we
are allowing ourselves to be guided by the real evidence^ i.e. that
we are representing or interpreting the reality presented to us for
1 Cf. Science of Logic, ii., 254, c; supra, 154.
278 THEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
interpretation only according to its real or ontological exigencies
and not otherwise. 1 Now this evidence is by no means cogent.
It can be sufficient to ground a firm or certain assent ; but, clearly,
it allows wide scope for the exercise of prudence, care, and caution
in conducting the intellectual processes of conception, judgment,
generalization, induction, deduction, etc., through which alone we
can hope to attain to a reasoned and reasonable certitude regard
ing the true solutions of the momentous problems referred to.
There is nothing to justify the impression which one sometimes
encounters concerning the scholastic doctrine of evidence (as the
supreme criterion of truth and the ultimate motive of certitude),
that this doctrine would make the attainment of human certitude
on the ultimate problems of science, philosophy, and religion, a
much simpler and easier matter than it really is ; or that it seems
to imply that the evidence for these ultimate truths ought to be,
and must be, and really is of the same cogent character as
e.g. the evidence forthcoming in mathematical demonstrations.
On the contrary, scholastics have always distinguished between
cogent evidence for the truth of judgments and reasonably suffi
cient evidence for the credibility of judgments (ii, 12, 38, 67);
and they have always protested against the unreasonableness of
demanding as a universal condition of certain assent to judg
ments in every domain the sort of cogent evidence which compels
intellectual assent to asbtract axioms.-
The real reason why scholastics have emphasized the im
portance of the thesis that the " supreme criterion or test of
true or genuine knowledge, and the ultimate motive of human
certitude, is to be found in the intrinsic, immediate objective
evidence of first principles of the ideal order," 3 is not far to seek.
1 It is this question of the possibility and grounds of certitude about concrete
matters (especially in the domain of religion), or the possibility and legitimacy of
applying abstract principles of the ideal order to the interpretation of concrete
matters of fact and thus reaching certitude about such interpretations, that Cardinal
Newman has examined in his Grammar of Assent. His analysis, which is ably con
ducted on original lines, will at least convince the student that such certitude rests
on evidential grounds which, so far from being intellectually cogent, call for the
exercise of diligence, candour, caution and prudence, in appreciating their suffici
ency for reasoned and reflex certitude. But it is hardly too much to say that the
author would have been materially assisted in his investigation by a fuller know
ledge of the scholastic doctrine of Moderate Realism than he was in a position to
bring to the investigation.
2 Cf. Science of Logic, ii., 203, p. 12 ; 275, pp. 322-7. Cf. vol. i., $ 67,
P. 234 n.
3 Vol. i., 67, p. 233 n.
TRUTH AND EVIDENCE 279
It is simply because unless such evidence is a revelation of reality
to the intellect, unless the intellect infallibly attains to true or
faithful (if inadequate) representations of reality through the
intuition of such principles, it cannot possibly attain to any truth,
but is doomed to hopeless scepticism. And why ? Because
these principles are involved in every single item of what we
regard as knowledge. They form the very warp and woof of
all knowledge. They are implicit in all our judgments ; and all
inference, all inductive generalizations from facts and all de
ductive explanations of facts, depend on them. Therefore the
real truth-value of all our knowledge, i.e. its value as giving us a
genuine insight into reality, depends altogether on whether the
intellect, when its assent to such principles is compelled, as all,
even subjectivists and sceptics, admit that it is compelled, there
by gets an insight into reality. And this in turn depends on
whether the compelling factor is objective evidence, i.e. the reality
itself presented as necessarily representable by intellect through
such axiomatic judgments, as having and displaying a real
exigency for such representation ; or whether on the contrary the
compelling factor is a subjective influence which, whether con
scious or unconscious, has no claim to any evidential value, i.e. to
any significance as manifesting reality to the mind. From this
it is clear that what scholastics describe as "evidence" would
be useless as an index to truth and a motive of certitude (i.e. firm
assent to judgments as true, as revealing reality to the mind), if
it appeared on reflection either that the determining factor of the
judicial nexus between our concepts were not objective, or that
the concepts containing that determining factor (or sufficient
ground) of the nexus were not themselves manifestations of
reality.
In other words, the function of evidence, even of cogent immediate evi
dence, as revealing real truth and determining certitude, had to be vindicated
against the suspicion cast upon it by subjectivists, and notably by Kant, in
the manner in which we saw (29-35) that it is possible to raise such a sus
picion. For there is a sense in which even self-evident judgments can be,
and have been, doubted. It has been doubted whether what is called their
" evidence " is indeed real evidence, i.e. whether what the mind sees, in assent
ing to them, is indeed reality, whether it is a feature of reality that is repre
sentable and faithfully represented in and through them. Until such a doubt
was removed the scholastic thesis in regard to evidence stood unproven. And
how was such a doubt removed ? By the whole process of introspective analy
sis which established the objectivity of the nexus in regard to our judgments, the
280 THEOR Y OF KNO WLEDGE
reality of our concepts as propounded in Moderate Realism, and the reality
of our percepts in regard to sense perception. And what was it that guided
us in our investigations and determined our conclusions ? At every stage in
the process we reflected on what came into consciousness ; we examined the
appearances of our data as critically and carefully as we could with a view
to discovering their real demands upon our faculty of interpretation, i.e. their
real evidence, and with a view to representing or interpreting them accord
ingly. The whole process was not a process of demonstration but of
introspective analysis (33). And if it be described as a process of " testing "
evidence, it must be observed that on the subjective side our testing " instru
ment " was intellect, and on the objective side we had no test for evidence
except evidence itself : which means simply that we tried to judge appearances
critically according to what we detected, in the appearing reality, as its real
exigencies for intellectual interpretation, i.e. its real evidence.
This is what the human mind has to do in every department if it is to
attain to truth and avoid error : it has to explore the data of experience, or
how things appear, in order to discover, as far as it can, what intellectual
interpretations they really call for, or what judgments will, as far as they
go, truly represent what those things are. This applies equally to men s
"common" knowledge, to their "scientific" knowledge, to their "philo
sophical" convictions, and to their "religious" convictions. The mind has
certain possession of truth only in so far as it knows its judgments to be in con
formity with what reality demands as its intellectual representations. Hence
those real exigencies of things must be clear to the intellect before it can
give a firm or certain assent to the judgments they call for : i.e. sufficiently
clear either to compel assent or to be reasonably and prudently considered
to yield adequate ground for assent. But though some of those exigencies are
clear ab initio, most of them can be made clear only gradually and by the
sustained application of intellect to the data of human experience. This is
true especially of the evidence for the ethical and religious truths that are of
the deepest import to human life. 1 Hence the fact that real objective evidence,
or the manifestation of reality to the intellect, is the supreme test of truth and
the ultimate motive of certitude, by no means dispenses the intellect from
labour : " There is no royal road to knowledge". In the data of experience
there is potential evidence, so to speak, for as much truth as the finite human
mind can ever reach concerning man and the universe ; but this potential
evidence must be made actual to the individual mind before it can "inform "
the individual mind with truth ; and only by its own active application can
the individual mind make this potential evidence actual.
1 That is, for reasoned, reflex certitude in regard to such truths. Obviously, it
is not by way of original research that the masses of mankind attain to their spon
taneous ethical and religious convictions : they receive these on extrinsic evidence,
by way of authority, a vehicle which can have the requisite conditions for ground
ing firm or certain assent to its deliverances.
CHAPTER XXIV.
OTHER INTELLECTUALIST THEORIES OF CERTITUDE.
TRADITIONALISM.
A few points, however, call for notice.
First, when scholastics emphasize the doctrine that the immediate
objective evidence of axioms of the ideal order is the supreme
criterion of all truth and the ultimate motive of all human certi
tude, they are not to be understood as implying that the evidence
we have for the judgments that are of the most profound im
portance to the human race can be reduced to such evidence (cf.
148). The true solutions of the great problems concerning the
origin, nature, and destiny of man and the universe, concerning
the immortality of the soul, the existence of God, the reality of
the moral order, the obligation and sanctions of religion, are,
needless to say, not immediately evident. Indeed no solutions
of these problems are immediately evident. Nor can the true
solutions of them be deduced from self-evident axioms of the
ideal order by any process of pure deductive reasoning, of which
every step would be cogently self-evident (35) : such, for instance,
as the reasoning employed in pure mathematics. Their solution
involves mixed demonstration. 1 It therefore implies certitude
about some judgments of the existential order ; it implies that
abstract concepts and principles are validly applicable to the
actually experienced order of concrete, existing things, i.e. it
implies the truth of Moderate Realism ; and finally it implies
well-grounded certitude on our part that in the actual process of
applying concepts to percepts, of interpreting singulars by uni-
versals, of locating the intellectual abstract in the sense concrete, we
are allowing ourselves to be guided by the real evidence^ i.e. that
we are representing or interpreting the reality presented to us for
1 Cf. Science of Logic, ii., 254, c; supra, 154.
278 THEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
interpretation only according to its real or ontological exigencies
and not otherwise. 1 Now this evidence is by no means cogent.
It can be sufficient to ground a firm or certain assent ; but, clearly,
it allows wide scope for the exercise of prudence, care, and caution
in conducting the intellectual processes of conception, judgment,
generalization, induction, deduction, etc., through which alone we
can hope to attain to a reasoned and reasonable certitude regard
ing the true solutions of the momentous problems referred to.
There is nothing to justify the impression which one sometimes
encounters concerning the scholastic doctrine of evidence (as the
supreme criterion of truth and the ultimate motive of certitude),
that this doctrine would make the attainment of human certitude
on the ultimate problems of science, philosophy, and religion, a
much simpler and easier matter than it really is ; or that it seems
to imply that the evidence for these ultimate truths ought to be,
and must be, and really is of the same cogent character as
e.g. the evidence forthcoming in mathematical demonstrations.
On the contrary, scholastics have always distinguished between
cogent evidence for the truth of judgments and reasonably suffi
cient evidence for the credibility of judgments (ii, 12, 38, 67);
and they have always protested against the unreasonableness of
demanding as a universal condition of certain assent to judg
ments in every domain the sort of cogent evidence which compels
intellectual assent to asbtract axioms.-
The real reason why scholastics have emphasized the im
portance of the thesis that the " supreme criterion or test of
true or genuine knowledge, and the ultimate motive of human
certitude, is to be found in the intrinsic, immediate objective
evidence of first principles of the ideal order," 3 is not far to seek.
1 It is this question of the possibility and grounds of certitude about concrete
matters (especially in the domain of religion), or the possibility and legitimacy of
applying abstract principles of the ideal order to the interpretation of concrete
matters of fact and thus reaching certitude about such interpretations, that Cardinal
Newman has examined in his Grammar of Assent. His analysis, which is ably con
ducted on original lines, will at least convince the student that such certitude rests
on evidential grounds which, so far from being intellectually cogent, call for the
exercise of diligence, candour, caution and prudence, in appreciating their suffici
ency for reasoned and reflex certitude. But it is hardly too much to say that the
author would have been materially assisted in his investigation by a fuller know
ledge of the scholastic doctrine of Moderate Realism than he was in a position to
bring to the investigation.
2 Cf. Science of Logic, ii., 203, p. 12 ; 275, pp. 322-7. Cf. vol. i., $ 67,
P. 234 n.
3 Vol. i., 67, p. 233 n.
TRUTH AND EVIDENCE 279
It is simply because unless such evidence is a revelation of reality
to the intellect, unless the intellect infallibly attains to true or
faithful (if inadequate) representations of reality through the
intuition of such principles, it cannot possibly attain to any truth,
but is doomed to hopeless scepticism. And why ? Because
these principles are involved in every single item of what we
regard as knowledge. They form the very warp and woof of
all knowledge. They are implicit in all our judgments ; and all
inference, all inductive generalizations from facts and all de
ductive explanations of facts, depend on them. Therefore the
real truth-value of all our knowledge, i.e. its value as giving us a
genuine insight into reality, depends altogether on whether the
intellect, when its assent to such principles is compelled, as all,
even subjectivists and sceptics, admit that it is compelled, there
by gets an insight into reality. And this in turn depends on
whether the compelling factor is objective evidence, i.e. the reality
itself presented as necessarily representable by intellect through
such axiomatic judgments, as having and displaying a real
exigency for such representation ; or whether on the contrary the
compelling factor is a subjective influence which, whether con
scious or unconscious, has no claim to any evidential value, i.e. to
any significance as manifesting reality to the mind. From this
it is clear that what scholastics describe as "evidence" would
be useless as an index to truth and a motive of certitude (i.e. firm
assent to judgments as true, as revealing reality to the mind), if
it appeared on reflection either that the determining factor of the
judicial nexus between our concepts were not objective, or that
the concepts containing that determining factor (or sufficient
ground) of the nexus were not themselves manifestations of
reality.
In other words, the function of evidence, even of cogent immediate evi
dence, as revealing real truth and determining certitude, had to be vindicated
against the suspicion cast upon it by subjectivists, and notably by Kant, in
the manner in which we saw (29-35) that it is possible to raise such a sus
picion. For there is a sense in which even self-evident judgments can be,
and have been, doubted. It has been doubted whether what is called their
" evidence " is indeed real evidence, i.e. whether what the mind sees, in assent
ing to them, is indeed reality, whether it is a feature of reality that is repre
sentable and faithfully represented in and through them. Until such a doubt
was removed the scholastic thesis in regard to evidence stood unproven. And
how was such a doubt removed ? By the whole process of introspective analy
sis which established the objectivity of the nexus in regard to our judgments, the
280 THEOR Y OF KNO WLEDGE
reality of our concepts as propounded in Moderate Realism, and the reality
of our percepts in regard to sense perception. And what was it that guided
us in our investigations and determined our conclusions ? At every stage in
the process we reflected on what came into consciousness ; we examined the
appearances of our data as critically and carefully as we could with a view
to discovering their real demands upon our faculty of interpretation, i.e. their
real evidence, and with a view to representing or interpreting them accord
ingly. The whole process was not a process of demonstration but of
introspective analysis (33). And if it be described as a process of " testing "
evidence, it must be observed that on the subjective side our testing " instru
ment " was intellect, and on the objective side we had no test for evidence
except evidence itself : which means simply that we tried to judge appearances
critically according to what we detected, in the appearing reality, as its real
exigencies for intellectual interpretation, i.e. its real evidence.
This is what the human mind has to do in every department if it is to
attain to truth and avoid error : it has to explore the data of experience, or
how things appear, in order to discover, as far as it can, what intellectual
interpretations they really call for, or what judgments will, as far as they
go, truly represent what those things are. This applies equally to men s
"common" knowledge, to their "scientific" knowledge, to their "philo
sophical" convictions, and to their "religious" convictions. The mind has
certain possession of truth only in so far as it knows its judgments to be in con
formity with what reality demands as its intellectual representations. Hence
those real exigencies of things must be clear to the intellect before it can
give a firm or certain assent to the judgments they call for : i.e. sufficiently
clear either to compel assent or to be reasonably and prudently considered
to yield adequate ground for assent. But though some of those exigencies are
clear ab initio, most of them can be made clear only gradually and by the
sustained application of intellect to the data of human experience. This is
true especially of the evidence for the ethical and religious truths that are of
the deepest import to human life. 1 Hence the fact that real objective evidence,
or the manifestation of reality to the intellect, is the supreme test of truth and
the ultimate motive of certitude, by no means dispenses the intellect from
labour : " There is no royal road to knowledge". In the data of experience
there is potential evidence, so to speak, for as much truth as the finite human
mind can ever reach concerning man and the universe ; but this potential
evidence must be made actual to the individual mind before it can "inform "
the individual mind with truth ; and only by its own active application can
the individual mind make this potential evidence actual.
1 That is, for reasoned, reflex certitude in regard to such truths. Obviously, it
is not by way of original research that the masses of mankind attain to their spon
taneous ethical and religious convictions : they receive these on extrinsic evidence,
by way of authority, a vehicle which can have the requisite conditions for ground
ing firm or certain assent to its deliverances.
CHAPTER XXIV.
OTHER INTELLECTUALIST THEORIES OF CERTITUDE.
TRADITIONALISM.