OF " INTERNAL " PERCEPTION.
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101
102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 112 113 114 115 117 118
119 120 121 122 123 124 125 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135
138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148
According to Kant time is no
more a characteristic of things than space. Like space it is an
a priori form of perception. The arguments 3 by which he seeks
to establish this contention are, mutatis mutandis, the same as
those on which he bases his doctrine of space, and therefore we
need not reconsider them. What they should prove, apparently,
is that time, like space, is an a priori form under which we per
ceive things. Kant, however, concludes from them that time is
the a priori form under which we perceive not things, but ourselves ;
for, he teaches, while space is the form of external sense perception,
does not imply that our spontaneous conviction as to the mind s capacity to attain
to real truth must be assumed from the outset as a reasoned certitude, but only that
the spontaneous conviction can be and will be, if the mind proceeds carefully
transformed by reflection into a reasoned certitude (ff. chap, iii.) ; nor does it imply
that the mind is infallible, but only that in the measure in which it interprets the
given according to the laws of thought and the evidence of reality it will avoid error
and attain to truth about reality.
1 PRICHARD, p. 65. "Cf. MERCIER, op. cit., 147, pp. 401-2 ; supra, no.
Critique, pp. 24-33, 731.
KANTS THEORY OF SENSE PERCEPTION, ETC. 203
time is the form of internal sense perception, or of the internal
sense. Let us see what this can mean.
The distinction to which Kant endeavoured to give expres
sion by the phrases " external sense " and " internal sense " is the
familiar psychological distinction between the group of cognitive
states or activities which make us immediately aware of what
we call things and their qualities, and the cognitive activity where
by we become directly aware of the former activities as states
or activities of our minds. The latter activity is, of course, the
activity of reflection or self-consciousness. Locke, 1 distinguishing
these two main sources of knowledge, called the former " sensa
tion " and the latter " reflection," suggesting at the same time
however, that the latter " though it be not sense as having noth
ing to do with external objects," is nevertheless " very like it
[sense], and might properly enough be called internal sense ".
He realizes that it is not sense, because sense, as he understands
the term, involves the operation upon the mind (through sense
organs) of bodies existing externally, or independently of the
mind, and the production of " perception " in the mind thereby.
Yet he describes the activity in question in terms of sense, adding
the adjective " internal " ; the assumption being, apparently, that
just as in direct cognition external things act on the mind and pro
duce sensation-percepts, or what he calls " ideas of sensation," so
in reflex cognition, where the mind contemplates its own activities,
the mind acts upon itself and produces reflection-percepts, or
what he calls "ideas of reflection ".
Now Kant adopted this description of the facts in terms of
" external sense " and " internal sense ". For him, however, the
term " sense " cannot mean the affecting of physical sense organs
by bodies, but the affecting of the mind by things in themselves,
i.e. things independent of the mind. " External sense " or " outer
sense " is then, for Kant, the mind s capacity for receiving im
pressions (" receptivity of impressions ") produced by things in
dependent of the mind, and of becoming thereby aware of mental
states or appearances or phenomena : the supposed things in
themselves remaining unknowable. So too, the mind, in order
to perceive itself and its own states or activities, must be affected
by itself, by its own states or activities : it must have a capacity
to be affected by its own states (parallel to its capacity to be
affected by things independent of itself), and this capacity Kant
1 Essay, ii., i, 2-4.
204 THEOR V OF k NO WLEDGE
calls the internal sense. Moreover, if the external sense does
not reveal things, but only sensations or representations or ap
pearances produced by things, so too the internal sense cannot
reveal the mind itself or its states or activities, but only appear
ances produced by these: "and since time is a mode of relation
of these appearances, it is a determination not of ourselves [the
real or transcendental Ego], but only of the appearances due
to ourselves [the empirical, phenomenal Ego~\," l just as space is
a determination not of things [the real or transcendental non-Ego]
but only of the appearances due to things [the empirical or pheno
menal universe]. Thus, then, through " external sense " we do not
know whether things in themselves are either spatial or temporal ;
we know the states or appearances produced by them in the mind
to be spatial, because by the a priori form of space we arrange
these appearances spatially ; but by the internal sense we do not
know these mental states to be really and in themselves temporal,
for we do not know these mental states as they are in themselves,-
or in the real mind : we only know the representations pro
duced in our minds by these states or activities. It is only
this second layer, so to speak, of representations representa
tions of ourselves, appearances produced by the action of our own
mental states upon our minds that we can know to be really
temporal : inasmuch as time is the a priori form under which
alone all mental activities, states, appearances, etc., can be per
ceived or apprehended.
Now it will be manifest to anyone who follows Kant s line of
thought, as just indicated, that on his own principles he could
have had absolutely no ground for distinguishing between "ex
ternal " and " internal " sense. For, manifestly, if we cannot
know our real selves or minds, any more than real things, we
have no means of determining whether any given representa
tion is due to " things" or to our "selves". To be consistent
he should ascribe all representations alike to "unknowable
reality," and recognize the mind s inability to distinguish this
latter into a transcendental Ego and a transcendental non-Ego, and
consequently to distinguish between " internal " and external "
sense.
1 PIUCHARD, op. cit., p. 107.
2 Therefore it should follow that we do not know even these " phenomena " or
" mental appearances " to be in themselves spatial : it is only our (a priori " tem
poral ") representations of these representations that we could really know to be
(both) spatial (and temporal).
KANT S THEOR Y OF SENSE PERCEPTION, ETC. 205
Not only, however, is the distinction between " external "
and " internal " sense incompatible with the general theory that
reality is in itself unknowable. It can also be shown, and this
is more important still, that Kant s doctrine on the ideal or
phenomenal character of space, and the consequent unknow-
ability of things in themselves, rests on the assumption that we
can at least know our own minds, or our own mental states, as they
really are in themselves, an assumption which, nevertheless, he
flatly contradicts by his contention that time is an a priori form
whereby alone we can perceive our own minds and their states
not as they really are, but only as they appear under this form.
For why does Kant hold that we cannot know things in them
selves, but only the "mental appearances" produced by them?
Why does he hold that space cannot be a determination of things
in themselves, but can only be a determination of phenomena or
mental appearances? Because he accepts unquestioningly the
fundamental postulate of Idealism that the mind cannot trans
cend itself to know the extramental, or what is independent of
mind. But this at least implies that the mind can know the
intramental, or what is dependent on mind, i.e. can know its own
conscious states, representations, etc., as these really are. Other
wise what right has he to assert that space is mental ? or that
any of the other supposed a priori factors of knowledge are
mental ? Therefore it appears that the mind can know its own
states as they really are. But temporal succession is an
essential characteristic of these states ; therefore, since they are
real, and are known as real, time, which is a characteristic of
them, is likewise real, and is not merely an a priori form or
mode under which or in which they are perceived. 1
1 C/. Kant s own formulation of the argument as a difficulty against his doctrine
of the a priori character of time : " Changes are real (this is proved by the change
of our own representations, even if all external phenomena and their changes be
denied). Changes, however, are possible in time only, and therefore time must be
something real." Critique, p. 29. And he rightly points out that the reason why
people urge the objection particularly against the a priori character of time is that
whatever about the extramental reality of external, spatial objects, " the reality of
the object of our internal perceptions (the perception of my own self and of my own
states) is clear immediately through our consciousness. The former might be
merely phenomenal [ blosser Schein, mere illusion cf. PRICHARD, p. 113],
but the latter, according to their opinion, is undeniably something real."-
Critiqne, p. 30. He thinks he answers the difficulty by pointing out that time is real
as a real form of our perception of our own states : but the difficulty is that his own
view of space as a form not of things but only of mental representations, implies
that time is a real form and real characteristic of these representations themselves,
206 THEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
If, on the other hand, we do not and cannot know the real
mind and its real states (and time as a real characteristic of them),
then (i) we have no intelligible ground for distinguishing in
knowledge some factors as belonging to (and contributed by)
the mind or knowing subject, from other factors as belonging
to (and contributed by) the supposed extramental reality in
contrast with the knowing subject ; and (2) even if we do in
consistently make the distinction, it would appear that what we
can know is neither (a) real things, nor (b} our mental spatial
arrangements of sensations supposed to be caused by such things,
nor (c) any other real state whatsoever of our own minds, but (d)
only temporal mental arrangements which constitute the empirical
or phenomenal Ego, and which are arrangements of spatial sensa
tions, these in turn (being now both temporal and spatial) con
stituting the phenomenal universe or non-Ego. Or rather, to be
accurate we should say that all we have comprehended under
the last head (tf) is not itself known, but furnishes only the data
or material of knowledge : since what we really know is a
and not merely of our perception of them. And from this difficulty there is really no
escape for him : unless indeed by withdrawing his contention that space is a char
acteristic merely of mind-dependent appearances, and at the same time withdrawing
the idealistic principle underlying it, viz. that the mind cannot know things or
realities independent of itself, in other words, by abandoning his general theory.
Cf. MAHER, Psychology (4th edit.), p. 120 : " A conscious state cannot have any
exlstence-in-itsclfa.pa.rt from what it is apprehended to be. Its essc is fcrcipi. Since,
then, mental states are as they are apprehended, and since they are apprehended as
successive, they must form a real succession in-themselves. They cannot be timeless
as they are non-spatial. But if so Kant s form of the internal sense the intuition
of time as extinguished." And Maher further argues that therefore time-succession
must likewise be a real characteristic of the extramental world which causes these
successive states: "As . . . there is a real succession in our ideas there is a true
correlate to the notion of time. A sequence of changes being once admitted in our
conscious states, an analogous succession of alterations cannot be denied to the
external reality which acts upon us, and so we are justified in maintaining the
objective reality of the notion " p. 120. Cf. ibid., pp. 474-5 : " Consciousness
affords at all events an immediate knowledge of my states and of myself in those
states. There is no room for appearances or phenomena here; the mind, the
object of knowledge, is really immediately present to itself."
In accordance with the view that time is an a priori form under which alone we
can apprehend all mental representations whatsoever, Kant holds that " the con
cept of change, and with it the concept of motion (as change of place) is possible
only through and in the representation of time ; and that, if this representation were
not intuitive (internal) a priori, no concept, whatever it be, could make us under
stand the possibility of change ". Critique, p. 721. This is an inversion of the facts.
Time, apprehended in the manner in which Kant deals with it, is not a percept at all,
but an abstract concept ; and it is a concept based upon, and derived from, our per
ception of motion or change. Cf. Ontology, 85, pp. 322-8.
KANTS THEORY OF SENSE PERCEPTION, ETC. 207
synthesis of these mental materials with the a priori concepts of
the understanding.
The argument, then, against Kant s view that time is an a
priori form of our perception of our own mental states or activities,
or, in other words, that it is a " form of internal sense intuition,"
is briefly this, that his own proof of the phenomenality of space
(if we may coin the expression) implies the reality of time. As
Prichard puts it, " Kant must at least concede that ive undergo a
succession of changing states, even if he holds that things, being
independent of the mind, cannot be shown to undergo such a
succession ; consequently he ought to allow that time is not a way
in which we apprehend ourselves, but a real feature of our real
states". 1 Or, finally, to put the argument in the converse way,
if Kant will not allow that we can apprehend any " real feature
of our real states," or that we can therefore know time to be such,
then he destroys the ground of his own contention that space is
not a characteristic of things but only of mental representations or
phenomena, for the ground of this contention is that whereas we
cannot know things that are " external " or " independent of the
mind," as they really are, we can know states that are "internal "
or "dependent on the mind," as these states really are.
One final and fatal flaw in Kant s thesis that time is a form
of our perceptions of events is this. He himself is forced to
recognize that some temporal relations belong to the physical
events which we perceive : that there are, in these, temporal
successions, which, by virtue of their irreversibility, differ from
mere successions of our perceptions : that we can apprehend
this distinction in general, and apply it in detail so as to appre
hend some successions (e.g. that of the moon moving round the
earth), as objective, from other successions (e.g. of our impres
sions as we survey the parts of a house), as subjective (cf. 93).
Hence time would not be a form or character of our perceptions
exclusively, but also of things perceived. Of course if Kant
were consistent he should see that his theory, by identifying
perceptions with things perceived, makes it impossible to appre
hend, either in general or in detail, any such distinction between
two classes of temporal successions. 2
1 Op. cit., p. 114. 2 C/. PRICHARU, op. cit., p. 139.
PART V.
TRUTH AND CERTITUDE: THEIR CRITERIA AND
MOTIVES.
CHAPTER XXII.
RETROSPECT. RELATIVIST THEORIES OF KNOWLEDGE.
According to Kant time is no
more a characteristic of things than space. Like space it is an
a priori form of perception. The arguments 3 by which he seeks
to establish this contention are, mutatis mutandis, the same as
those on which he bases his doctrine of space, and therefore we
need not reconsider them. What they should prove, apparently,
is that time, like space, is an a priori form under which we per
ceive things. Kant, however, concludes from them that time is
the a priori form under which we perceive not things, but ourselves ;
for, he teaches, while space is the form of external sense perception,
does not imply that our spontaneous conviction as to the mind s capacity to attain
to real truth must be assumed from the outset as a reasoned certitude, but only that
the spontaneous conviction can be and will be, if the mind proceeds carefully
transformed by reflection into a reasoned certitude (ff. chap, iii.) ; nor does it imply
that the mind is infallible, but only that in the measure in which it interprets the
given according to the laws of thought and the evidence of reality it will avoid error
and attain to truth about reality.
1 PRICHARD, p. 65. "Cf. MERCIER, op. cit., 147, pp. 401-2 ; supra, no.
Critique, pp. 24-33, 731.
KANTS THEORY OF SENSE PERCEPTION, ETC. 203
time is the form of internal sense perception, or of the internal
sense. Let us see what this can mean.
The distinction to which Kant endeavoured to give expres
sion by the phrases " external sense " and " internal sense " is the
familiar psychological distinction between the group of cognitive
states or activities which make us immediately aware of what
we call things and their qualities, and the cognitive activity where
by we become directly aware of the former activities as states
or activities of our minds. The latter activity is, of course, the
activity of reflection or self-consciousness. Locke, 1 distinguishing
these two main sources of knowledge, called the former " sensa
tion " and the latter " reflection," suggesting at the same time
however, that the latter " though it be not sense as having noth
ing to do with external objects," is nevertheless " very like it
[sense], and might properly enough be called internal sense ".
He realizes that it is not sense, because sense, as he understands
the term, involves the operation upon the mind (through sense
organs) of bodies existing externally, or independently of the
mind, and the production of " perception " in the mind thereby.
Yet he describes the activity in question in terms of sense, adding
the adjective " internal " ; the assumption being, apparently, that
just as in direct cognition external things act on the mind and pro
duce sensation-percepts, or what he calls " ideas of sensation," so
in reflex cognition, where the mind contemplates its own activities,
the mind acts upon itself and produces reflection-percepts, or
what he calls "ideas of reflection ".
Now Kant adopted this description of the facts in terms of
" external sense " and " internal sense ". For him, however, the
term " sense " cannot mean the affecting of physical sense organs
by bodies, but the affecting of the mind by things in themselves,
i.e. things independent of the mind. " External sense " or " outer
sense " is then, for Kant, the mind s capacity for receiving im
pressions (" receptivity of impressions ") produced by things in
dependent of the mind, and of becoming thereby aware of mental
states or appearances or phenomena : the supposed things in
themselves remaining unknowable. So too, the mind, in order
to perceive itself and its own states or activities, must be affected
by itself, by its own states or activities : it must have a capacity
to be affected by its own states (parallel to its capacity to be
affected by things independent of itself), and this capacity Kant
1 Essay, ii., i, 2-4.
204 THEOR V OF k NO WLEDGE
calls the internal sense. Moreover, if the external sense does
not reveal things, but only sensations or representations or ap
pearances produced by things, so too the internal sense cannot
reveal the mind itself or its states or activities, but only appear
ances produced by these: "and since time is a mode of relation
of these appearances, it is a determination not of ourselves [the
real or transcendental Ego], but only of the appearances due
to ourselves [the empirical, phenomenal Ego~\," l just as space is
a determination not of things [the real or transcendental non-Ego]
but only of the appearances due to things [the empirical or pheno
menal universe]. Thus, then, through " external sense " we do not
know whether things in themselves are either spatial or temporal ;
we know the states or appearances produced by them in the mind
to be spatial, because by the a priori form of space we arrange
these appearances spatially ; but by the internal sense we do not
know these mental states to be really and in themselves temporal,
for we do not know these mental states as they are in themselves,-
or in the real mind : we only know the representations pro
duced in our minds by these states or activities. It is only
this second layer, so to speak, of representations representa
tions of ourselves, appearances produced by the action of our own
mental states upon our minds that we can know to be really
temporal : inasmuch as time is the a priori form under which
alone all mental activities, states, appearances, etc., can be per
ceived or apprehended.
Now it will be manifest to anyone who follows Kant s line of
thought, as just indicated, that on his own principles he could
have had absolutely no ground for distinguishing between "ex
ternal " and " internal " sense. For, manifestly, if we cannot
know our real selves or minds, any more than real things, we
have no means of determining whether any given representa
tion is due to " things" or to our "selves". To be consistent
he should ascribe all representations alike to "unknowable
reality," and recognize the mind s inability to distinguish this
latter into a transcendental Ego and a transcendental non-Ego, and
consequently to distinguish between " internal " and external "
sense.
1 PIUCHARD, op. cit., p. 107.
2 Therefore it should follow that we do not know even these " phenomena " or
" mental appearances " to be in themselves spatial : it is only our (a priori " tem
poral ") representations of these representations that we could really know to be
(both) spatial (and temporal).
KANT S THEOR Y OF SENSE PERCEPTION, ETC. 205
Not only, however, is the distinction between " external "
and " internal " sense incompatible with the general theory that
reality is in itself unknowable. It can also be shown, and this
is more important still, that Kant s doctrine on the ideal or
phenomenal character of space, and the consequent unknow-
ability of things in themselves, rests on the assumption that we
can at least know our own minds, or our own mental states, as they
really are in themselves, an assumption which, nevertheless, he
flatly contradicts by his contention that time is an a priori form
whereby alone we can perceive our own minds and their states
not as they really are, but only as they appear under this form.
For why does Kant hold that we cannot know things in them
selves, but only the "mental appearances" produced by them?
Why does he hold that space cannot be a determination of things
in themselves, but can only be a determination of phenomena or
mental appearances? Because he accepts unquestioningly the
fundamental postulate of Idealism that the mind cannot trans
cend itself to know the extramental, or what is independent of
mind. But this at least implies that the mind can know the
intramental, or what is dependent on mind, i.e. can know its own
conscious states, representations, etc., as these really are. Other
wise what right has he to assert that space is mental ? or that
any of the other supposed a priori factors of knowledge are
mental ? Therefore it appears that the mind can know its own
states as they really are. But temporal succession is an
essential characteristic of these states ; therefore, since they are
real, and are known as real, time, which is a characteristic of
them, is likewise real, and is not merely an a priori form or
mode under which or in which they are perceived. 1
1 C/. Kant s own formulation of the argument as a difficulty against his doctrine
of the a priori character of time : " Changes are real (this is proved by the change
of our own representations, even if all external phenomena and their changes be
denied). Changes, however, are possible in time only, and therefore time must be
something real." Critique, p. 29. And he rightly points out that the reason why
people urge the objection particularly against the a priori character of time is that
whatever about the extramental reality of external, spatial objects, " the reality of
the object of our internal perceptions (the perception of my own self and of my own
states) is clear immediately through our consciousness. The former might be
merely phenomenal [ blosser Schein, mere illusion cf. PRICHARD, p. 113],
but the latter, according to their opinion, is undeniably something real."-
Critiqne, p. 30. He thinks he answers the difficulty by pointing out that time is real
as a real form of our perception of our own states : but the difficulty is that his own
view of space as a form not of things but only of mental representations, implies
that time is a real form and real characteristic of these representations themselves,
206 THEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
If, on the other hand, we do not and cannot know the real
mind and its real states (and time as a real characteristic of them),
then (i) we have no intelligible ground for distinguishing in
knowledge some factors as belonging to (and contributed by)
the mind or knowing subject, from other factors as belonging
to (and contributed by) the supposed extramental reality in
contrast with the knowing subject ; and (2) even if we do in
consistently make the distinction, it would appear that what we
can know is neither (a) real things, nor (b} our mental spatial
arrangements of sensations supposed to be caused by such things,
nor (c) any other real state whatsoever of our own minds, but (d)
only temporal mental arrangements which constitute the empirical
or phenomenal Ego, and which are arrangements of spatial sensa
tions, these in turn (being now both temporal and spatial) con
stituting the phenomenal universe or non-Ego. Or rather, to be
accurate we should say that all we have comprehended under
the last head (tf) is not itself known, but furnishes only the data
or material of knowledge : since what we really know is a
and not merely of our perception of them. And from this difficulty there is really no
escape for him : unless indeed by withdrawing his contention that space is a char
acteristic merely of mind-dependent appearances, and at the same time withdrawing
the idealistic principle underlying it, viz. that the mind cannot know things or
realities independent of itself, in other words, by abandoning his general theory.
Cf. MAHER, Psychology (4th edit.), p. 120 : " A conscious state cannot have any
exlstence-in-itsclfa.pa.rt from what it is apprehended to be. Its essc is fcrcipi. Since,
then, mental states are as they are apprehended, and since they are apprehended as
successive, they must form a real succession in-themselves. They cannot be timeless
as they are non-spatial. But if so Kant s form of the internal sense the intuition
of time as extinguished." And Maher further argues that therefore time-succession
must likewise be a real characteristic of the extramental world which causes these
successive states: "As . . . there is a real succession in our ideas there is a true
correlate to the notion of time. A sequence of changes being once admitted in our
conscious states, an analogous succession of alterations cannot be denied to the
external reality which acts upon us, and so we are justified in maintaining the
objective reality of the notion " p. 120. Cf. ibid., pp. 474-5 : " Consciousness
affords at all events an immediate knowledge of my states and of myself in those
states. There is no room for appearances or phenomena here; the mind, the
object of knowledge, is really immediately present to itself."
In accordance with the view that time is an a priori form under which alone we
can apprehend all mental representations whatsoever, Kant holds that " the con
cept of change, and with it the concept of motion (as change of place) is possible
only through and in the representation of time ; and that, if this representation were
not intuitive (internal) a priori, no concept, whatever it be, could make us under
stand the possibility of change ". Critique, p. 721. This is an inversion of the facts.
Time, apprehended in the manner in which Kant deals with it, is not a percept at all,
but an abstract concept ; and it is a concept based upon, and derived from, our per
ception of motion or change. Cf. Ontology, 85, pp. 322-8.
KANTS THEORY OF SENSE PERCEPTION, ETC. 207
synthesis of these mental materials with the a priori concepts of
the understanding.
The argument, then, against Kant s view that time is an a
priori form of our perception of our own mental states or activities,
or, in other words, that it is a " form of internal sense intuition,"
is briefly this, that his own proof of the phenomenality of space
(if we may coin the expression) implies the reality of time. As
Prichard puts it, " Kant must at least concede that ive undergo a
succession of changing states, even if he holds that things, being
independent of the mind, cannot be shown to undergo such a
succession ; consequently he ought to allow that time is not a way
in which we apprehend ourselves, but a real feature of our real
states". 1 Or, finally, to put the argument in the converse way,
if Kant will not allow that we can apprehend any " real feature
of our real states," or that we can therefore know time to be such,
then he destroys the ground of his own contention that space is
not a characteristic of things but only of mental representations or
phenomena, for the ground of this contention is that whereas we
cannot know things that are " external " or " independent of the
mind," as they really are, we can know states that are "internal "
or "dependent on the mind," as these states really are.
One final and fatal flaw in Kant s thesis that time is a form
of our perceptions of events is this. He himself is forced to
recognize that some temporal relations belong to the physical
events which we perceive : that there are, in these, temporal
successions, which, by virtue of their irreversibility, differ from
mere successions of our perceptions : that we can apprehend
this distinction in general, and apply it in detail so as to appre
hend some successions (e.g. that of the moon moving round the
earth), as objective, from other successions (e.g. of our impres
sions as we survey the parts of a house), as subjective (cf. 93).
Hence time would not be a form or character of our perceptions
exclusively, but also of things perceived. Of course if Kant
were consistent he should see that his theory, by identifying
perceptions with things perceived, makes it impossible to appre
hend, either in general or in detail, any such distinction between
two classes of temporal successions. 2
1 Op. cit., p. 114. 2 C/. PRICHARU, op. cit., p. 139.
PART V.
TRUTH AND CERTITUDE: THEIR CRITERIA AND
MOTIVES.
CHAPTER XXII.
RETROSPECT. RELATIVIST THEORIES OF KNOWLEDGE.