PERCEPTION.
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 83
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101
102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 112 113 114 115 117 118
119 120 121 122 123 124 125 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135
138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148
We have now to examine Kant s teaching on the
validity of sense perception, culminating as it docs in the view
that space and time are not features or characteristics of what is
given in sense perception, but are a priori mental endowments,
pure forms of sensibility, which render sense perception possible.
If it is true that Kant never relinquished his hold on extramental
reality, it is equally true that he kept his hold on it in defiance
of the whole theory outlined in the Critique of Pure Reason.
Many of the positions adopted in the course of the Critique are
untenable, 1 if not indeed meaningless,- unless on the assumption
that at least in sense perception the mind is directly aware of
extramental reality, an assumption that is fundamentally op
posed to the main assumption underlying the Critique.
We do not consider that Kant is to be blamed for not having
avowedly presupposed the validity of man s spontaneous convic
tion that the mind can know reality as it is, and conducted his
analysis in the light of this presupposition, though de facto it is
really latent in the opening passages of the Critique, where he
says that "by the sensibility objects are given to us," 3 where he
speaks of " objects which affect our senses," 4 and where he speaks
of reality in the plural as "things in themselves," seemingly
identifying these with real bodies in space. But we do think
that he adopted an unjustifiable procedure by introducing tacitly
at an early stage of his inquiry the opposite assumption, viz. that
the mind cannot know reality as it is, t; and by allowing this as-
1 E.g. the supposition that only a priori judgments, and not a posteriori judg
ments give rise to any "problem of knowledge" (cf. % 55 ; PRICHARD, op. cit.,
pp. 3 7 66-8).
E.g. the supposition that the cause of sensation is "a spatial and temporal
world " of " physical bodies," and that " this world is what we come to know".
PRICHARD, p. 32.
3 Critique, p. 40. *Ibid., p. 715.
Cf. PRICHARD, op. cit., pp. 30, 32. K Ibid., p. 30.
184
KANTS THEORY OF SENSE PERCEPTION, ETC. 185
sumption, perhaps unconsciously but none the less effectively,
to bias his whole analysis of our cognitive functions and their
a priori mental conditions, and indeed so to bias this analysis
that it inevitably issues in subjectivism.
That in the earlier portion of the Critique Kant vacillates
between the realist and the idealist views of sense perception
will be apparent from a comparison of the opening passages of
the Introduction (47) and the Transcendental Aesthetic (50> with
his subsequent treatment of the general problem of knowledge.
He commences by asserting that in intuition or perception, and
there alone, cognition directly reaches its " objects " ; that in
perception these act upon our sensibility and produce sensations
therein; that thereby objects are "given to us": "The effect
produced by an object upon the faculty of representation, so far
as we are affected by it, is called sensation. An intuition of an
object by means of a sensation is called empirical" (51). Now
here he identifies the "objects " with the " causes " of sensation,
and he is manifestly thinking of these as things and events in the
physical universe of space and time, for his aim is to explain our
sense knowledge of this latter. But as the sensation is in the
mind and the supposed cause or causes of it beyond and outside
the mind, and as he cannot see how anything extramental can be
presented to the mind or become an object of the mind s aware
ness, 1 he rejects the view that the causes of our sensations are
bodies and events in the physical universe, substituting the as
sumption that they are an unknowable reality ; 2 and he leaves us
1 In other words, how the mind can " transcend itself" (21). In one remarkable
passage of the Prolegomena Kant admits that it is at all events possible, if not posi
tively intelligible, that a thing present to perception can reveal itself as it is in itself.
" Were our perception necessarily of such a kind as to represent things as they are
in themselves, no perception would take place a priori, but would always be empiri
cal. For I can only know what is contained in the object in itself, if it is present
and given to me. No doubt it is even then unintelligible how the perception of a
present thing should make me know it as it is in itself, since its qualities cannot
migrate over into my faculty of representation ; but even granting this possibility
[italics ours], such a perception would not occur a priori, i.e. before the object was
presented tome. ..." (Prol.,g; cf. PRICHARD, op. cit., p. 55). If the "thing"
is " present " to " my faculty of representation," why should the " qualities " of the
thing have to " migrate over into " the latter, in order that the thing be known as it
is in itself? The notion that such " migration " is necessary reveals a rather crude
and mechanical conception of the process of cognition ; nor is it easy to see how
the mystery or obscurity of the latter is one whit lessened by supposing any sort
of real identity of the perceiver and the perceived (cf. 21).
2 Kant s employment of the principle; of causality here, to infer a transcendental
reality correlative to our sensations, is manifestly inconsistent with his own theory
as to the limits of its valid and legitimate employment.
1 86 THEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
wondering what " objects are given to us by the sensibility ".
What is given is simply a. manifold of sensations, a " raw material
of ... sensuous impressions " l (47), whereby we are to become
aware of a physical universe of bodies and events in space and
time. How this can be done is now the problem.
" For if [writes Prichard] the contribution of the sensibility to our
knowledge of the physical world is limited to a succession of sensations,
explanation must be given of the fact that we have succeeded with an experi
ence confined to sensations in acquiring a knowledge of a world which does
not consist of sensations. Kant, in fact, in the Aesthetic has this problem
continually before him, and tries to solve it. He holds that the mind . . .
superinduces upon sensations, as data, spatial and other relations in such a
way that it acquires knowledge of the spatial world." "
In stating the problem Kant appears to have been un
doubtedly influenced by his assumption of realism, i.e. the spon
taneous conviction of mankind that our sensations are caused by
(extramental) bodies in space. And even after he had rejected
this assumption and ascribed the origin of sensations to extra-
mental, unknowable " things in themselves," he continued to
speak of these latter in terms which show that he was really think
ing of bodies in space. In corroboration of this, Prichard refers
to " certain passages in the Critique which definitely mention the
senses/ a term which refers to bodily organs," and to " others to
which meaning can be given only if they are taken to imply that
the objects which affect our sensibility are not unknown things in
themselves, but things known to be spatial. Even the use of
the plural in the term things in themselves implies a tendency
to identify the unknowable reality beyond the mind with bodies
in space. For the implication that different sensations are due
to different things in themselves originates in the view that
different sensations are due to the operation of different spatial
bodies." 3
Prichard even contends that the problem of the Aesthetic,
" How do we, beginning with mere sensation, come to know a
spatial and temporal world?" is only a problem "so long as it
is supposed that the cause of sensation is a spatial and temporal
world or part of it, and that this world is what we come to know.
If the cause of sensation, as being beyond the mind, is held to
be unknowable and so not known to be spatial or temporal, the
1 Critique, p. 715. 2 Of. cit., p. 31. s lbid., p. 32,
KANTS THEORY OF SENSE PERCEPTION, ETC. 187
problem has disappeared." l We would say rather, that the prob
lem is changed. It is now no longer the (insoluble) problem,
" How do we, beginning with mere awareness of our own indivi
dual mental states, originated by a supposed extramental reality,
ever come to know this latter ? " It is now the (fictitious) problem,
" How do we transform a chaotic stream of isolated sensuous im
pressions (originated in us by an unknowable reality) into the
orderly system of mental appearances which we apprehend as the
physical, material universe of space and time, and which, be it
remarked incidentally, uncritical people by a spontaneous illu
sion believe to be extramental?" His solution of this problem
(51) is that, whereas the visual, tactual, auditory, gustatory, and
olfactory elements (i.e. what are called the " proper sensibles " or
the " secondary qualities " of bodies) in our states of sense con
sciousness constitute the matter or data or chaotic manifold of
sense impressions, the space and time elements in these states (the
" common sensibles" or "primary qualities ") are not given em
pirically, with or in those sensation manifolds, but are pure
mental forms of a priori intuition ; and that only by the a priori
synthesis of these with the empirical data is it possible for us
to become conscious or aware of anything as a phenomenon of
physical nature existing in space and time. 2 We shall now deal
separately and in order with his attempts to prove space and
time to be a priori forms of sense perception.
We have now to examine Kant s teaching on the
validity of sense perception, culminating as it docs in the view
that space and time are not features or characteristics of what is
given in sense perception, but are a priori mental endowments,
pure forms of sensibility, which render sense perception possible.
If it is true that Kant never relinquished his hold on extramental
reality, it is equally true that he kept his hold on it in defiance
of the whole theory outlined in the Critique of Pure Reason.
Many of the positions adopted in the course of the Critique are
untenable, 1 if not indeed meaningless,- unless on the assumption
that at least in sense perception the mind is directly aware of
extramental reality, an assumption that is fundamentally op
posed to the main assumption underlying the Critique.
We do not consider that Kant is to be blamed for not having
avowedly presupposed the validity of man s spontaneous convic
tion that the mind can know reality as it is, and conducted his
analysis in the light of this presupposition, though de facto it is
really latent in the opening passages of the Critique, where he
says that "by the sensibility objects are given to us," 3 where he
speaks of " objects which affect our senses," 4 and where he speaks
of reality in the plural as "things in themselves," seemingly
identifying these with real bodies in space. But we do think
that he adopted an unjustifiable procedure by introducing tacitly
at an early stage of his inquiry the opposite assumption, viz. that
the mind cannot know reality as it is, t; and by allowing this as-
1 E.g. the supposition that only a priori judgments, and not a posteriori judg
ments give rise to any "problem of knowledge" (cf. % 55 ; PRICHARD, op. cit.,
pp. 3 7 66-8).
E.g. the supposition that the cause of sensation is "a spatial and temporal
world " of " physical bodies," and that " this world is what we come to know".
PRICHARD, p. 32.
3 Critique, p. 40. *Ibid., p. 715.
Cf. PRICHARD, op. cit., pp. 30, 32. K Ibid., p. 30.
184
KANTS THEORY OF SENSE PERCEPTION, ETC. 185
sumption, perhaps unconsciously but none the less effectively,
to bias his whole analysis of our cognitive functions and their
a priori mental conditions, and indeed so to bias this analysis
that it inevitably issues in subjectivism.
That in the earlier portion of the Critique Kant vacillates
between the realist and the idealist views of sense perception
will be apparent from a comparison of the opening passages of
the Introduction (47) and the Transcendental Aesthetic (50> with
his subsequent treatment of the general problem of knowledge.
He commences by asserting that in intuition or perception, and
there alone, cognition directly reaches its " objects " ; that in
perception these act upon our sensibility and produce sensations
therein; that thereby objects are "given to us": "The effect
produced by an object upon the faculty of representation, so far
as we are affected by it, is called sensation. An intuition of an
object by means of a sensation is called empirical" (51). Now
here he identifies the "objects " with the " causes " of sensation,
and he is manifestly thinking of these as things and events in the
physical universe of space and time, for his aim is to explain our
sense knowledge of this latter. But as the sensation is in the
mind and the supposed cause or causes of it beyond and outside
the mind, and as he cannot see how anything extramental can be
presented to the mind or become an object of the mind s aware
ness, 1 he rejects the view that the causes of our sensations are
bodies and events in the physical universe, substituting the as
sumption that they are an unknowable reality ; 2 and he leaves us
1 In other words, how the mind can " transcend itself" (21). In one remarkable
passage of the Prolegomena Kant admits that it is at all events possible, if not posi
tively intelligible, that a thing present to perception can reveal itself as it is in itself.
" Were our perception necessarily of such a kind as to represent things as they are
in themselves, no perception would take place a priori, but would always be empiri
cal. For I can only know what is contained in the object in itself, if it is present
and given to me. No doubt it is even then unintelligible how the perception of a
present thing should make me know it as it is in itself, since its qualities cannot
migrate over into my faculty of representation ; but even granting this possibility
[italics ours], such a perception would not occur a priori, i.e. before the object was
presented tome. ..." (Prol.,g; cf. PRICHARD, op. cit., p. 55). If the "thing"
is " present " to " my faculty of representation," why should the " qualities " of the
thing have to " migrate over into " the latter, in order that the thing be known as it
is in itself? The notion that such " migration " is necessary reveals a rather crude
and mechanical conception of the process of cognition ; nor is it easy to see how
the mystery or obscurity of the latter is one whit lessened by supposing any sort
of real identity of the perceiver and the perceived (cf. 21).
2 Kant s employment of the principle; of causality here, to infer a transcendental
reality correlative to our sensations, is manifestly inconsistent with his own theory
as to the limits of its valid and legitimate employment.
1 86 THEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
wondering what " objects are given to us by the sensibility ".
What is given is simply a. manifold of sensations, a " raw material
of ... sensuous impressions " l (47), whereby we are to become
aware of a physical universe of bodies and events in space and
time. How this can be done is now the problem.
" For if [writes Prichard] the contribution of the sensibility to our
knowledge of the physical world is limited to a succession of sensations,
explanation must be given of the fact that we have succeeded with an experi
ence confined to sensations in acquiring a knowledge of a world which does
not consist of sensations. Kant, in fact, in the Aesthetic has this problem
continually before him, and tries to solve it. He holds that the mind . . .
superinduces upon sensations, as data, spatial and other relations in such a
way that it acquires knowledge of the spatial world." "
In stating the problem Kant appears to have been un
doubtedly influenced by his assumption of realism, i.e. the spon
taneous conviction of mankind that our sensations are caused by
(extramental) bodies in space. And even after he had rejected
this assumption and ascribed the origin of sensations to extra-
mental, unknowable " things in themselves," he continued to
speak of these latter in terms which show that he was really think
ing of bodies in space. In corroboration of this, Prichard refers
to " certain passages in the Critique which definitely mention the
senses/ a term which refers to bodily organs," and to " others to
which meaning can be given only if they are taken to imply that
the objects which affect our sensibility are not unknown things in
themselves, but things known to be spatial. Even the use of
the plural in the term things in themselves implies a tendency
to identify the unknowable reality beyond the mind with bodies
in space. For the implication that different sensations are due
to different things in themselves originates in the view that
different sensations are due to the operation of different spatial
bodies." 3
Prichard even contends that the problem of the Aesthetic,
" How do we, beginning with mere sensation, come to know a
spatial and temporal world?" is only a problem "so long as it
is supposed that the cause of sensation is a spatial and temporal
world or part of it, and that this world is what we come to know.
If the cause of sensation, as being beyond the mind, is held to
be unknowable and so not known to be spatial or temporal, the
1 Critique, p. 715. 2 Of. cit., p. 31. s lbid., p. 32,
KANTS THEORY OF SENSE PERCEPTION, ETC. 187
problem has disappeared." l We would say rather, that the prob
lem is changed. It is now no longer the (insoluble) problem,
" How do we, beginning with mere awareness of our own indivi
dual mental states, originated by a supposed extramental reality,
ever come to know this latter ? " It is now the (fictitious) problem,
" How do we transform a chaotic stream of isolated sensuous im
pressions (originated in us by an unknowable reality) into the
orderly system of mental appearances which we apprehend as the
physical, material universe of space and time, and which, be it
remarked incidentally, uncritical people by a spontaneous illu
sion believe to be extramental?" His solution of this problem
(51) is that, whereas the visual, tactual, auditory, gustatory, and
olfactory elements (i.e. what are called the " proper sensibles " or
the " secondary qualities " of bodies) in our states of sense con
sciousness constitute the matter or data or chaotic manifold of
sense impressions, the space and time elements in these states (the
" common sensibles" or "primary qualities ") are not given em
pirically, with or in those sensation manifolds, but are pure
mental forms of a priori intuition ; and that only by the a priori
synthesis of these with the empirical data is it possible for us
to become conscious or aware of anything as a phenomenon of
physical nature existing in space and time. 2 We shall now deal
separately and in order with his attempts to prove space and
time to be a priori forms of sense perception.