THEORIES.
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101
102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 111 112 113 114 115 116 117 118
119 120 121 122 123 124 125 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135
138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148
The conclusions we have reached in regard to the
function and force of evidence will affect different types of mind
differently. They show that the human intellect can attain to
some truth 1 with reasoned certitude, provided it prudently follow
its own natural dictates and assent firmly only to such judgments
as it sees to be clearly called for by the real exigencies of the
data presented for its interpretation. They therefore prove the
attitude of Scepticism (chap, iv.) to be unreasonable. On the
other hand they show that although the intellect is infallible in
its assent to self-evident abstract axioms, and to self-evident
interpretations of the immediate concrete data of conscious ex
perience, it is not infallible in interpreting the truth-value or
knowledge- value of such compelled spontaneous assents, or in
interpreting the real nature either of the human mind itself or of
the world that is given it for interpretation. Hence they account
for the possibility of error, and for its prevalence in regard to
the solutions of those ultimate questions that are of the most
profound import to man, the questions which constitute the
domain of philosophy proper. Our conclusions are therefore in
conformity with the broad and undeniable facts which emerge
from the history of philosophy.
But there are many philosophers who will not allow that it
is by the exercise of intellect or reason on the data of experience,
by interpreting these data and reasoning about them in the light
of the demands which they make on this faculty reflecting on
them, that the human mind can or does attain to the possession
of any truth and certitude, or at least to truth and certitude
regarding the great questions of the origin, nature, and destiny
of man and the universe. The anti-intellectualist or voluntarist
1 To how much truth ? Cf. infra, 173.
281
282 THEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
theories of knowledge, represented by Kant s Practical Philo
sophy, and in our own time by Pragmatism or Humanism, will
be seen below (chap, xxv.) to involve a perversion of the right
use of reason confronted with the problem of knowledge.
Again, there are philosophers who, apparently underrating
and losing faith in the power of the human intellect to attain
to a reasoned certitude on those same fundamental problems by
scrutinizing the evidence furnished by the data of human ex
perience, contend that it is only by the aid of a supernatural
Divine Revelation that man has attained, or can attain, to such
certitude. This theory known as Fideism or Traditionalism
will next claim our attention. In passing, however, from the
subject of evidence as the criterion of truth, we may glance
briefly here at a few theories, some of which are really only
modifications of the scholastic theory, and others attempts to
indicate some means apparently distinct from evidence itself, for
testing the truth of judgments.
(1) We have already examined (43, 44) the test proposed by
Spencer, as the supreme and ultimate criterion of the truth of
a judgment, viz. the "inconceivability of its opposite " ; and we
saw that not all inconceivability is, as he contended, subjective,
psychological, relative and merely negative. There is an incon
ceivability which springs from our direct and positive intuition
of the real, ontological incompatibility of the terms compared in
the "opposite" or "contradictory" of the judgment. Such, for
instance, is the incompatibility of the subject "two straight
lines " with the predicate " enclosing a space ". Such, too, is the
inconceivability of the contradictory of such a judgment as " two
and two are four," or such a judgment as " I exist". Manifestly
the test entitled "inconceivability of the opposite," understood in
this sense of positively apprehended real and objective impossibility,
is precisely the same as the scholastic test of immediate, cogent,
objective evidence, stated, however, in a needlessly indirect and
possibly misleading manner : for such judgments are not seen to
be true because their opposites are seen to be inconceivable, but
rather their opposites are seen to be inconceivable because they
themselves are seen to be objectively and necessarily true.
(2) We also saw (30, 34) that the first test adopted by Des
cartes was that known as the " clear and distinct idea " : he could
not doubt his own existence because he " saw very clearly that,
in order to think, one must exist " ; and so he accepted as a
INTELLECTUALIST THEORIES OF CERTITUDE 283
general rule the test "that the things which we conceive very
clearly and very distinctly are all true "^ It is beyond doubt,
too, that he accepted this test as guaranteeing the objective truth
of the intuition of his own existence, and not merely in the
Kantian sense of revealing this intuition as a subjective mental
synthesis of conscious thought-products (30, 31). Now, if the
test is understood in this objective sense, 2 if it means that the
clearly apprehended real exigency of a given conscious content
to be represented by some definite judgment or interpretation, or
the cogency with which it compels such a judgment, is to be
taken as adequate ground for the objective truth of this judgment,
then the test is obviously identical with that described by schol
astics as cogent, immediate, objective evidence. Where Descartes
erred, therefore, was (a) in not applying the test impartially to
other self-evident truths besides that of his own existence ; (fr)
in thinking that it was not ultimate, in entertaining a serious
doubt about its real validity, in imagining that its real validity
needed to be vindicated by establishing its dependence on the
Divine Veracity ; and (c} in trying to prove the existence of God
by employing principles and premisses for the truth of which
he had no other test than the one he had just declared to be
unreliable (34).
(3) It is needless to point out that a reasoned knowledge of the -veracity
of God as the author of our faculties cannot possibly be for us the ultimate
guarantee of the truth of our judgments : on such an assumption any and
every attempted proof of God s existence would be a petitio principal
(4) The same is true of the theory according to which the ultimate guar
antee of the truth of necessary principles of the ideal order would be not their
objective self-evidence but the knowledge that they are expressions of the
Eternal Exemplar or Archetype Ideas in the Divine Mind.* In the onto-
logical order, of course, the Divine Essence is the ultimate ground of the
necessary truth of such judgments. 5 But it is another thing altogether to
contend that in the logical order we must know this dependence of truth on
the Divine Intellect before we can have any reasoned certitude : 6 if this were
so, reasoned certitude would be unattainable.
(5) Again, we have seen that the immediate disciples of Descartes, and
notably MALEBRANCHE (80, 123), considering that even immediate sense evi
dence, as presented to the intellect, could give us no cognitive insight into the
1 Discours de la Mcthode, apiid MERCIER, op. cit., pp. 213-14.
2 Cf. vol. i., 30, p. 112, n. i.
3 Cf. MERCIER, op. cit., 94-6, for critique of Descartes arguments.
4 Ibid., too; cf. vol. i., 69, 70, 80; supra, 139.
5 Cf. Ontology, 20. 6 MERCIER, op. cit., 101.
284 TI1EOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
existence of contingent, material reality, i.e. reality transcending the Ego and
external to the Ego, adopted the view that the only rational ground we have
for assenting to judgments which affirm the existence and nature of material
reality must be the conviction that such judgments are intuitions of this
reality in the Divine Mind decreeing its existence. Not only does this theory
confuse our knowledge of the existence of things with our knowledge of the
mode of their origin? but it likewise involves a vicious circle and renders all
knowledge impossible. For we are certainly not conscious of seeing either
the essences or the existences of contingent things in the Divine Mind. The
existence of God has therefore to be proved. But in order to prove it the
individual human being must be certain (a) of the objective and real truth of
principles of the ideal order (on the ground of their immediate intellectual
evidence), and (b] of his own existence as a rent, permanent, abiding, contin
gent being, distinct from the flow of his conscious states. But he cannot
consistently accept the evidence forthcoming for this latter conviction if he
rejects the similar evidence furnished by sense perception for the real,
permanent, abiding existence of a material reality distinct from his perception,
and from himself the perceiver. 2
In a similar way, when Berkeley (failing to see how the conscious sub
ject can transcend his own conscious states, and apparently concluding that
they cannot be transcended) denied that immediate sense evidence must be
interpreted as revealing an external material reality whose real esse would be
independent of \\.s percipi, he was inconsistent in interpreting any of his con
scious states as revealing, beyond themselves, anything in the nature of a real,
permanent, abiding, substantial Ego or mind : an inconsistency which Hume
was not slow to bring to light, and which he himself escaped only by drawing
the logical conclusion of pan-phenomenism. From this intellectual morass
Kant in turn tried to emerge ; but his effort was futile simply because he too
misinterpreted the significance of objective evidence by clinging to the
idealist postulate in the face of this same evidence.
The conclusions we have reached in regard to the
function and force of evidence will affect different types of mind
differently. They show that the human intellect can attain to
some truth 1 with reasoned certitude, provided it prudently follow
its own natural dictates and assent firmly only to such judgments
as it sees to be clearly called for by the real exigencies of the
data presented for its interpretation. They therefore prove the
attitude of Scepticism (chap, iv.) to be unreasonable. On the
other hand they show that although the intellect is infallible in
its assent to self-evident abstract axioms, and to self-evident
interpretations of the immediate concrete data of conscious ex
perience, it is not infallible in interpreting the truth-value or
knowledge- value of such compelled spontaneous assents, or in
interpreting the real nature either of the human mind itself or of
the world that is given it for interpretation. Hence they account
for the possibility of error, and for its prevalence in regard to
the solutions of those ultimate questions that are of the most
profound import to man, the questions which constitute the
domain of philosophy proper. Our conclusions are therefore in
conformity with the broad and undeniable facts which emerge
from the history of philosophy.
But there are many philosophers who will not allow that it
is by the exercise of intellect or reason on the data of experience,
by interpreting these data and reasoning about them in the light
of the demands which they make on this faculty reflecting on
them, that the human mind can or does attain to the possession
of any truth and certitude, or at least to truth and certitude
regarding the great questions of the origin, nature, and destiny
of man and the universe. The anti-intellectualist or voluntarist
1 To how much truth ? Cf. infra, 173.
281
282 THEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
theories of knowledge, represented by Kant s Practical Philo
sophy, and in our own time by Pragmatism or Humanism, will
be seen below (chap, xxv.) to involve a perversion of the right
use of reason confronted with the problem of knowledge.
Again, there are philosophers who, apparently underrating
and losing faith in the power of the human intellect to attain
to a reasoned certitude on those same fundamental problems by
scrutinizing the evidence furnished by the data of human ex
perience, contend that it is only by the aid of a supernatural
Divine Revelation that man has attained, or can attain, to such
certitude. This theory known as Fideism or Traditionalism
will next claim our attention. In passing, however, from the
subject of evidence as the criterion of truth, we may glance
briefly here at a few theories, some of which are really only
modifications of the scholastic theory, and others attempts to
indicate some means apparently distinct from evidence itself, for
testing the truth of judgments.
(1) We have already examined (43, 44) the test proposed by
Spencer, as the supreme and ultimate criterion of the truth of
a judgment, viz. the "inconceivability of its opposite " ; and we
saw that not all inconceivability is, as he contended, subjective,
psychological, relative and merely negative. There is an incon
ceivability which springs from our direct and positive intuition
of the real, ontological incompatibility of the terms compared in
the "opposite" or "contradictory" of the judgment. Such, for
instance, is the incompatibility of the subject "two straight
lines " with the predicate " enclosing a space ". Such, too, is the
inconceivability of the contradictory of such a judgment as " two
and two are four," or such a judgment as " I exist". Manifestly
the test entitled "inconceivability of the opposite," understood in
this sense of positively apprehended real and objective impossibility,
is precisely the same as the scholastic test of immediate, cogent,
objective evidence, stated, however, in a needlessly indirect and
possibly misleading manner : for such judgments are not seen to
be true because their opposites are seen to be inconceivable, but
rather their opposites are seen to be inconceivable because they
themselves are seen to be objectively and necessarily true.
(2) We also saw (30, 34) that the first test adopted by Des
cartes was that known as the " clear and distinct idea " : he could
not doubt his own existence because he " saw very clearly that,
in order to think, one must exist " ; and so he accepted as a
INTELLECTUALIST THEORIES OF CERTITUDE 283
general rule the test "that the things which we conceive very
clearly and very distinctly are all true "^ It is beyond doubt,
too, that he accepted this test as guaranteeing the objective truth
of the intuition of his own existence, and not merely in the
Kantian sense of revealing this intuition as a subjective mental
synthesis of conscious thought-products (30, 31). Now, if the
test is understood in this objective sense, 2 if it means that the
clearly apprehended real exigency of a given conscious content
to be represented by some definite judgment or interpretation, or
the cogency with which it compels such a judgment, is to be
taken as adequate ground for the objective truth of this judgment,
then the test is obviously identical with that described by schol
astics as cogent, immediate, objective evidence. Where Descartes
erred, therefore, was (a) in not applying the test impartially to
other self-evident truths besides that of his own existence ; (fr)
in thinking that it was not ultimate, in entertaining a serious
doubt about its real validity, in imagining that its real validity
needed to be vindicated by establishing its dependence on the
Divine Veracity ; and (c} in trying to prove the existence of God
by employing principles and premisses for the truth of which
he had no other test than the one he had just declared to be
unreliable (34).
(3) It is needless to point out that a reasoned knowledge of the -veracity
of God as the author of our faculties cannot possibly be for us the ultimate
guarantee of the truth of our judgments : on such an assumption any and
every attempted proof of God s existence would be a petitio principal
(4) The same is true of the theory according to which the ultimate guar
antee of the truth of necessary principles of the ideal order would be not their
objective self-evidence but the knowledge that they are expressions of the
Eternal Exemplar or Archetype Ideas in the Divine Mind.* In the onto-
logical order, of course, the Divine Essence is the ultimate ground of the
necessary truth of such judgments. 5 But it is another thing altogether to
contend that in the logical order we must know this dependence of truth on
the Divine Intellect before we can have any reasoned certitude : 6 if this were
so, reasoned certitude would be unattainable.
(5) Again, we have seen that the immediate disciples of Descartes, and
notably MALEBRANCHE (80, 123), considering that even immediate sense evi
dence, as presented to the intellect, could give us no cognitive insight into the
1 Discours de la Mcthode, apiid MERCIER, op. cit., pp. 213-14.
2 Cf. vol. i., 30, p. 112, n. i.
3 Cf. MERCIER, op. cit., 94-6, for critique of Descartes arguments.
4 Ibid., too; cf. vol. i., 69, 70, 80; supra, 139.
5 Cf. Ontology, 20. 6 MERCIER, op. cit., 101.
284 TI1EOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
existence of contingent, material reality, i.e. reality transcending the Ego and
external to the Ego, adopted the view that the only rational ground we have
for assenting to judgments which affirm the existence and nature of material
reality must be the conviction that such judgments are intuitions of this
reality in the Divine Mind decreeing its existence. Not only does this theory
confuse our knowledge of the existence of things with our knowledge of the
mode of their origin? but it likewise involves a vicious circle and renders all
knowledge impossible. For we are certainly not conscious of seeing either
the essences or the existences of contingent things in the Divine Mind. The
existence of God has therefore to be proved. But in order to prove it the
individual human being must be certain (a) of the objective and real truth of
principles of the ideal order (on the ground of their immediate intellectual
evidence), and (b] of his own existence as a rent, permanent, abiding, contin
gent being, distinct from the flow of his conscious states. But he cannot
consistently accept the evidence forthcoming for this latter conviction if he
rejects the similar evidence furnished by sense perception for the real,
permanent, abiding existence of a material reality distinct from his perception,
and from himself the perceiver. 2
In a similar way, when Berkeley (failing to see how the conscious sub
ject can transcend his own conscious states, and apparently concluding that
they cannot be transcended) denied that immediate sense evidence must be
interpreted as revealing an external material reality whose real esse would be
independent of \\.s percipi, he was inconsistent in interpreting any of his con
scious states as revealing, beyond themselves, anything in the nature of a real,
permanent, abiding, substantial Ego or mind : an inconsistency which Hume
was not slow to bring to light, and which he himself escaped only by drawing
the logical conclusion of pan-phenomenism. From this intellectual morass
Kant in turn tried to emerge ; but his effort was futile simply because he too
misinterpreted the significance of objective evidence by clinging to the
idealist postulate in the face of this same evidence.