ANCES OR " PHENOMENA," BUT OF MATERIAL REALITIES.
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101
102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 112 113 114 115 117 118
119 120 121 122 123 124 125 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135
138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148
The
aim of the arguments just examined was to establish (i) that
space is a priori, (2) that it is a pure perception : from which two
characteristics it was to follow that space is a property not of
things in themselves but only of phenomena or mental appear
ances. In drawing this latter conclusion 2 Kant gives another
argument in support of the second characteristic, 3 an argument
based on the supposed synthetic a priori (and at the same time
intuitively evident) character of geometrical judgments. Since
we have already shown this latter position to be untenable (63)
we need not examine the argument in detail. But some points
1 C/. Critique, pp. 56-7, quoted vol. i., 52, pp. 186-7.
2 Ibid., pp. 20-4. 3 Ibid. (2nd edit.), pp. 728-9; Prolegomena, 6-n.
KANTS THEORY OF SENSE PERCEPTION, ETC. 197
in it are worthy of notice ; and his attempt to infer from the
supposed a priori and perceptive character of our apprehension of
space his final conclusion that space is a property of phenomena
only, and not of things in themselves, has also to be examined.
(1) Arguing from the character of geometrical judgments he
admits that all such judgments are intuitive or perceptive. 1 This
obliges him to apply the term a priori to perception as well as to
judgment. Applied to perception it can have only a temporal
sense and must mean " prior to all experience " ; and, as Prichard
remarks, 2 "since the object of perception is essentially individual, 3
the use of the term gives rise to the impossible task of explain
ing how a perception can take place prior to the actual experience
of an individual in perception ".
(2) Kant contends that such a perception (of empty space)
does take place, but that it can take place only if space, or the
perception of space (which he identifies with space 4 ), be a char
acteristic of our perceiving nature ; 5 and since such perception
does take place it must be such a characteristic.
(3) The question, How is it possible to perceive anything (in
this case, empty space) a priori? raising as it does the insuper
able difficulty of perceiving an object before the object is given,
forces Kant, therefore, to hold that what we apprehend in such
a perception can be only our own nature as percipient beings, or,
in other words, the mode in which we must necessarily perceive
objects when they are given (in empirical perception) : the reason
apparently being that nothing else but our own nature as per
cipient beings is present to us in such an a priori perception. " I
can only know what is contained in the object in itself, if it is
present and given to me" 6 as it is in empirical perception, in
which Kant allows the possibility of our knowing the given object
as it is in itself, 7 though only with a contingent, a posteriori
knowledge. In a priori perception, at all events, we can appre
hend only our own perceptive nature, or the mode in which subse-
1 Prol., 7. 2 Op. cit., p. 60 n.
Cf. Critique, pp. 572-3. 4 C/. PRICHARD, p. 51 n.
5 Critique, p. 729; Prol., 9 : " It is therefore possible only in one way for my
perception to precede the actuality of the object and to take place as a priori know
ledge, viz. if it contains nothing but the form of sensibility, which precedes in me,
the subject, all actual impressions through which I am affected by objects," apud
PRICHARD, p. 55.
6 Prol., 9.
~ This important admission (ibid.) has been referred to already supra, p. 185, n.
1 98 THEOR I OF KNO W I. EDGE
quently the sensuous content given in empirical perception
must necessarily be apprehended.
(4) From this the final conclusion is plausibly inferred, viz. that
the sensuous datum or material which is given in empirical intui
tion, and which is necessarily apprehended therein as spatial (owing
to the mode of our perceiving nature being spatial a priori] must
be itself something exclusively mental, must be, and be appre
hended as, a mental appearance or phenomenon, and cannot pos
sibly be anything extramental or any thing-in-itself : for if in
perceiving empty space a priori we are apprehending a law of our
nature as perceptive, then our empirical perceptions, or objects
empirically perceived, are spatial only because by being mental
appearances they come under the a priori mental law ; while it
must on the other hand remain impossible to say whether objects
apart from perception, or things in themselves, are or are not
spatial.
Plausible, however, as the conclusion is, nevertheless it is (i)
neither the conclusion warranted by his supposition that we have
an a priori perception of empty space whereby we can discover
the rules of spatial relation (geometrical truths) which must
apply to all spatial objects subsequently (and empirically) per
ceived ; nor (2) is the conclusion even compatible with the sup
position on which it is based.
For firstly, what is involved in the supposition that we have
such an apprehension of empty space as will yield the geometri
cal laws to which all empirically perceived objects must conform ?
It does not involve what Kant says it does, viz. that space is a
form of sensibility, or a mode or way in which objects must ap
pear. It simply involves that space is the form of all perceivable
objects, or that all perceivable objects are spatial. 1 For, provided
that perceivable objects are spatial,
" they must be subject to the laws of space, and if, therefore, \ve can dis
cover these laws by a study of empty space, the only condition to be satisfied,
if the objects of subsequent perception are to conform to the laws which we
discover, is that all objects should be spatial. Nothing is implied which
enables us to decide whether the objects are objects as they are in themselves
or objects as perceived ; for in cither case the required result follows. If in
empirical perception we apprehend objects only as they appear to us, and if
1 That space is a form of objects (whether we call these phenomena or not) is
quite a different assertion from this other, with which Kant confounds it : that space
is a form of sensibility, or of our perception of objects.
KANTS THEORY OF SENSE PERCEPTION, ETC. 199
space is the form of them as they appear to us, it will no doubt be true that
the laws of spatial relation which we discover must apply to things as they
appear to us. But on the other hand, if in empirical perception we appre
hend things as they are, and if space is their form, i.e. if things are spatial,
it will be equally true that the laws discovered by geometry must apply to
things as they are." 1
Secondly, the conclusion that space is a characteristic of
phenomena is really incompatible with the initial supposition that
the truths of geometry imply an a priori spatial perception which
turns out to be a perception of the mind s perceiving nature. For,
strange though it may seem, Kant s account of this latter a priori
perception implies that space is a characteristic of things as they
are in themselves ! In this way : When explaining how we can
perceive the characteristics of an object before the object is given,
he allows that if the thing or object were given, or were present
to us (as in empirical perception), we could perceive the char
acteristics of it as it really is. 2 But if this is so, and if the
objects given in empirical perception are given as spatial, as Kant
allows that they are, then it follows that space is their real form
and that the truths of geometry relate to them as they really are.
But if so, Kant s presupposition would involve this, that in per
ceiving empty space a priori we should be perceiving a real
characteristic of things in space before actually perceiving the
things ; "and no doubt, Kant thinks this impossible". 2 But, as
Prichard justly maintains, no greater difficulty is really involved
in it than in Kant s actual presupposition that we perceive how
objects will appear, before they actually do appear : " It is really
just as difficult to hold that we can perceive a characteristic of
things as they appear to us before they appear, as to hold that we
can perceive a characteristic of them as they are in themselves
before we perceive them ". 4
The fact is, of course, that the necessary character of geo
metrical judgments does not presuppose a pure a priori perception
of empty space. But even if it did, the paradox which such a
perception presents to Kant that of perceiving the characteristics
an object must have, before the object itself is given is really a
paradox only because it is supposed that we can perceive the
characteristics of the object when it is given, i.e. in empirical per
ception ; and since we can, and since the empirically perceived
1 PRICHARD, p. 58 (italics ours). 2 Cf. supra, pp. 185, 197.
3 PRICHARD, p. 59. *Ibid.
200 THEOR Y OP AW0 WLEDGE
object is spatial, it follows that space must be a real characteristic
of such an object. Hence Kant s final conclusion is incompatible
with a portion of his initial supposition.
We referred above to the plausible character of Kant s con
clusion that space can be a characteristic only of mental pheno
mena. The conclusion is equally plausible if we connect it
directly with the absolutely necessary character of geometrical
judgments, without postulating an a priori perception of empty
space. For just as Kant argues from the necessity and uni
versality of what he calls the principles underlying physics to
the existence of a priori conceptions, and from the similar char
acteristics of mathematical judgments to the existence of a priori
perceptions, so to he infers, in regard to both classes of judgments
alike, that they cannot possibly be applicable to things in them
selves, to reality, but only to mental phenomena. The argument
for the phenomenal character of space would then be as follows :
Space is obviously that to which geometrical judgments relate,
and of which they formulate the necessary and universal laws.
But since the necessity and universality of such judgments cannot
be grounded on what is given a posteriori from without, in repeated
empirical perceptions of bodies, the validity of such judgments
can in nowise be defended on the assumption that space, of
which they formulate the laws, is a thing in itself, for how could
a necessity of thought (which such judgments express) be bind
ing on what is ex hypotJiesi independent of the nature of the
mind? If, however, that to which such judgments refer, viz,
space, be merely a mental appearance, or apprehension, or per
ception, then it is at once intelligible how a necessity of thought
could and should apply to that which is itself mental through
and through. 1
One fatal flaw in the argument as just stated is this : it as
sumes that contingent, empirical, a posteriori judgments can and do
reveal real characteristics of the things given in empirical per
ception, and that the reason why necessary, " a priori" judgments
cannot reveal real characteristics of the latter, but only character
istics of something mental, is precisely because the connexions
they reveal are necessary and universal. But as we saw already
(55), no such distinction can be drawn between necessary and
contingent judgments. To question the reality of a connexion
which we see to be necessary and which we think to be real, and
1 Cf. vol. i., 55, 94 ; infra, i.^o.
KANTS THEORY OF SENSE PERCEPTION, ETC. 201
to do so simply on the ground that it is necessary, is <( to question
the validity of thinking altogether, and to do this is implicitly to
question the validity of our thought about the nature of our own
mind, as well as the validity of thought about things independent
of the mind "- 1 What right, after all, have we to assume that we
think or judge validly about our perceptions of things any more
than about things themselves ?
Furthermore, the assumption that space is something mental
and not real, not a characteristic of things as they are but only
of our mental representations of things, in no way helps to
explain the necessary and universal validity of geometrical judg
ments. 2 Kant thinks that it does because he confounds the
necessity of apprehended spatial law, or relation, or connexion,
with the universal validity of the judgment whereby we appre
hend such law as necessary.
" No doubt [writes Prichard ], if it be a law OF OUR PERCEIVING NATURE
that, whenever we perceive an object as a three-sided figure, the object AS
PERCEIVED contains three angles, it follows that any object AS PERCEIVED
[i.e. perceived as a three-sided figure] will conform to this law ; just as if it be
a law OF THINGS AS THEY ARE IN THEMSELVES that three-sided figures con
tain three angles, all three-sided figures will IN THEMSELVES contain three
angles. But what has to be explained is the universal applicability, not of a
law, but of a judgment about a law. For Kant s real problem is to explain
why our judgment that a three-sided figure must contain three angles must
apply to all three-sided figures. Of course if it be granted that in the judg
ment we apprehend the true law, the problem may be regarded as solved.
But how are we to know that what we judge is the true law ? The answer is
in no way facilitated by the supposition that the judgment relates to our
perceiving nature. IT CAN JUST AS WELL BE URGED THAT WHAT WE THINK
TO BE A NECESSITY OF OUR PERCEIVING NATURE IS NOT A NECESSITY OF
IT AS THAT WHAT WE THINK TO BE A NECESSITY OF THINGS AS THEY
ARE IN THEMSELVES IS NOT A NECESSITY OF THEM. 4 The best, Or rather
the only possible, answer is simply that that of which we apprehend the
necessity must be true, or, in other words, that we must accept the validity
ot thought. . . . 5 No vindication of a judgment in which we are conscious
1 PRICHARD, p. 62 (italics ours). 2 C/. vol. i., 55.
3 Op. cit., pp. 63, 65-6 (capitals ours).
4 Cf. vol. i., 59, where this objection is urged against the whole reasoning of
the Critique.
5 In other words, that which the intellect, reflecting on the data of human
experience, is necessitated to think as involved in this experience, is real : what is
given to the mind for its interpretation is real : and what is seen by the mind to be
necessarily involved in the given is likewise real. This is the thesis on which scho
lastics have at all times emphatically insisted : The proper object of intellect is
reality: Objectum intellectus est Ens (cf. Science of Logic, ii., 215, p. 58). This
202 THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE
of a necessity could do more than take the problem a stage further back by
basing it upon some other consciousness of a necessity, and since this latter
judgment could be questioned for precisely the same reason, we should only
be embarking upon an infinite process."
When, therefore, Kant thinks that he has solved " the original
problem of the conformity of things to our minds " by the con
tention that the " things " about which we judge are not " things
as they are in themselves" but "perceptions," " it can be forced
upon him again, even after he thinks he has solved it, in the new
form of that of the conformity within the mind of perceiving and
thinking". 1 Of course Kant "solves" the problem, stated in
this latter form, by the contention that just as what we perceive
is not the thing in itself but a mental impression produced by
the latter and made conformable to the mind s perceiving nature
by the forms of sense perception, so what we think or conceive or
judge is not the perception but the perception transfigured once
more and made conformable with the mind s thinking or judging
nature by the categories of the understanding : a solution which
really empties the question of the validity of knowledge of all
intelligible meaning by issuing in the " logical idealism " which
identifies thought with its object and denies all " extra-logical "
reality. 2
The
aim of the arguments just examined was to establish (i) that
space is a priori, (2) that it is a pure perception : from which two
characteristics it was to follow that space is a property not of
things in themselves but only of phenomena or mental appear
ances. In drawing this latter conclusion 2 Kant gives another
argument in support of the second characteristic, 3 an argument
based on the supposed synthetic a priori (and at the same time
intuitively evident) character of geometrical judgments. Since
we have already shown this latter position to be untenable (63)
we need not examine the argument in detail. But some points
1 C/. Critique, pp. 56-7, quoted vol. i., 52, pp. 186-7.
2 Ibid., pp. 20-4. 3 Ibid. (2nd edit.), pp. 728-9; Prolegomena, 6-n.
KANTS THEORY OF SENSE PERCEPTION, ETC. 197
in it are worthy of notice ; and his attempt to infer from the
supposed a priori and perceptive character of our apprehension of
space his final conclusion that space is a property of phenomena
only, and not of things in themselves, has also to be examined.
(1) Arguing from the character of geometrical judgments he
admits that all such judgments are intuitive or perceptive. 1 This
obliges him to apply the term a priori to perception as well as to
judgment. Applied to perception it can have only a temporal
sense and must mean " prior to all experience " ; and, as Prichard
remarks, 2 "since the object of perception is essentially individual, 3
the use of the term gives rise to the impossible task of explain
ing how a perception can take place prior to the actual experience
of an individual in perception ".
(2) Kant contends that such a perception (of empty space)
does take place, but that it can take place only if space, or the
perception of space (which he identifies with space 4 ), be a char
acteristic of our perceiving nature ; 5 and since such perception
does take place it must be such a characteristic.
(3) The question, How is it possible to perceive anything (in
this case, empty space) a priori? raising as it does the insuper
able difficulty of perceiving an object before the object is given,
forces Kant, therefore, to hold that what we apprehend in such
a perception can be only our own nature as percipient beings, or,
in other words, the mode in which we must necessarily perceive
objects when they are given (in empirical perception) : the reason
apparently being that nothing else but our own nature as per
cipient beings is present to us in such an a priori perception. " I
can only know what is contained in the object in itself, if it is
present and given to me" 6 as it is in empirical perception, in
which Kant allows the possibility of our knowing the given object
as it is in itself, 7 though only with a contingent, a posteriori
knowledge. In a priori perception, at all events, we can appre
hend only our own perceptive nature, or the mode in which subse-
1 Prol., 7. 2 Op. cit., p. 60 n.
Cf. Critique, pp. 572-3. 4 C/. PRICHARD, p. 51 n.
5 Critique, p. 729; Prol., 9 : " It is therefore possible only in one way for my
perception to precede the actuality of the object and to take place as a priori know
ledge, viz. if it contains nothing but the form of sensibility, which precedes in me,
the subject, all actual impressions through which I am affected by objects," apud
PRICHARD, p. 55.
6 Prol., 9.
~ This important admission (ibid.) has been referred to already supra, p. 185, n.
1 98 THEOR I OF KNO W I. EDGE
quently the sensuous content given in empirical perception
must necessarily be apprehended.
(4) From this the final conclusion is plausibly inferred, viz. that
the sensuous datum or material which is given in empirical intui
tion, and which is necessarily apprehended therein as spatial (owing
to the mode of our perceiving nature being spatial a priori] must
be itself something exclusively mental, must be, and be appre
hended as, a mental appearance or phenomenon, and cannot pos
sibly be anything extramental or any thing-in-itself : for if in
perceiving empty space a priori we are apprehending a law of our
nature as perceptive, then our empirical perceptions, or objects
empirically perceived, are spatial only because by being mental
appearances they come under the a priori mental law ; while it
must on the other hand remain impossible to say whether objects
apart from perception, or things in themselves, are or are not
spatial.
Plausible, however, as the conclusion is, nevertheless it is (i)
neither the conclusion warranted by his supposition that we have
an a priori perception of empty space whereby we can discover
the rules of spatial relation (geometrical truths) which must
apply to all spatial objects subsequently (and empirically) per
ceived ; nor (2) is the conclusion even compatible with the sup
position on which it is based.
For firstly, what is involved in the supposition that we have
such an apprehension of empty space as will yield the geometri
cal laws to which all empirically perceived objects must conform ?
It does not involve what Kant says it does, viz. that space is a
form of sensibility, or a mode or way in which objects must ap
pear. It simply involves that space is the form of all perceivable
objects, or that all perceivable objects are spatial. 1 For, provided
that perceivable objects are spatial,
" they must be subject to the laws of space, and if, therefore, \ve can dis
cover these laws by a study of empty space, the only condition to be satisfied,
if the objects of subsequent perception are to conform to the laws which we
discover, is that all objects should be spatial. Nothing is implied which
enables us to decide whether the objects are objects as they are in themselves
or objects as perceived ; for in cither case the required result follows. If in
empirical perception we apprehend objects only as they appear to us, and if
1 That space is a form of objects (whether we call these phenomena or not) is
quite a different assertion from this other, with which Kant confounds it : that space
is a form of sensibility, or of our perception of objects.
KANTS THEORY OF SENSE PERCEPTION, ETC. 199
space is the form of them as they appear to us, it will no doubt be true that
the laws of spatial relation which we discover must apply to things as they
appear to us. But on the other hand, if in empirical perception we appre
hend things as they are, and if space is their form, i.e. if things are spatial,
it will be equally true that the laws discovered by geometry must apply to
things as they are." 1
Secondly, the conclusion that space is a characteristic of
phenomena is really incompatible with the initial supposition that
the truths of geometry imply an a priori spatial perception which
turns out to be a perception of the mind s perceiving nature. For,
strange though it may seem, Kant s account of this latter a priori
perception implies that space is a characteristic of things as they
are in themselves ! In this way : When explaining how we can
perceive the characteristics of an object before the object is given,
he allows that if the thing or object were given, or were present
to us (as in empirical perception), we could perceive the char
acteristics of it as it really is. 2 But if this is so, and if the
objects given in empirical perception are given as spatial, as Kant
allows that they are, then it follows that space is their real form
and that the truths of geometry relate to them as they really are.
But if so, Kant s presupposition would involve this, that in per
ceiving empty space a priori we should be perceiving a real
characteristic of things in space before actually perceiving the
things ; "and no doubt, Kant thinks this impossible". 2 But, as
Prichard justly maintains, no greater difficulty is really involved
in it than in Kant s actual presupposition that we perceive how
objects will appear, before they actually do appear : " It is really
just as difficult to hold that we can perceive a characteristic of
things as they appear to us before they appear, as to hold that we
can perceive a characteristic of them as they are in themselves
before we perceive them ". 4
The fact is, of course, that the necessary character of geo
metrical judgments does not presuppose a pure a priori perception
of empty space. But even if it did, the paradox which such a
perception presents to Kant that of perceiving the characteristics
an object must have, before the object itself is given is really a
paradox only because it is supposed that we can perceive the
characteristics of the object when it is given, i.e. in empirical per
ception ; and since we can, and since the empirically perceived
1 PRICHARD, p. 58 (italics ours). 2 Cf. supra, pp. 185, 197.
3 PRICHARD, p. 59. *Ibid.
200 THEOR Y OP AW0 WLEDGE
object is spatial, it follows that space must be a real characteristic
of such an object. Hence Kant s final conclusion is incompatible
with a portion of his initial supposition.
We referred above to the plausible character of Kant s con
clusion that space can be a characteristic only of mental pheno
mena. The conclusion is equally plausible if we connect it
directly with the absolutely necessary character of geometrical
judgments, without postulating an a priori perception of empty
space. For just as Kant argues from the necessity and uni
versality of what he calls the principles underlying physics to
the existence of a priori conceptions, and from the similar char
acteristics of mathematical judgments to the existence of a priori
perceptions, so to he infers, in regard to both classes of judgments
alike, that they cannot possibly be applicable to things in them
selves, to reality, but only to mental phenomena. The argument
for the phenomenal character of space would then be as follows :
Space is obviously that to which geometrical judgments relate,
and of which they formulate the necessary and universal laws.
But since the necessity and universality of such judgments cannot
be grounded on what is given a posteriori from without, in repeated
empirical perceptions of bodies, the validity of such judgments
can in nowise be defended on the assumption that space, of
which they formulate the laws, is a thing in itself, for how could
a necessity of thought (which such judgments express) be bind
ing on what is ex hypotJiesi independent of the nature of the
mind? If, however, that to which such judgments refer, viz,
space, be merely a mental appearance, or apprehension, or per
ception, then it is at once intelligible how a necessity of thought
could and should apply to that which is itself mental through
and through. 1
One fatal flaw in the argument as just stated is this : it as
sumes that contingent, empirical, a posteriori judgments can and do
reveal real characteristics of the things given in empirical per
ception, and that the reason why necessary, " a priori" judgments
cannot reveal real characteristics of the latter, but only character
istics of something mental, is precisely because the connexions
they reveal are necessary and universal. But as we saw already
(55), no such distinction can be drawn between necessary and
contingent judgments. To question the reality of a connexion
which we see to be necessary and which we think to be real, and
1 Cf. vol. i., 55, 94 ; infra, i.^o.
KANTS THEORY OF SENSE PERCEPTION, ETC. 201
to do so simply on the ground that it is necessary, is <( to question
the validity of thinking altogether, and to do this is implicitly to
question the validity of our thought about the nature of our own
mind, as well as the validity of thought about things independent
of the mind "- 1 What right, after all, have we to assume that we
think or judge validly about our perceptions of things any more
than about things themselves ?
Furthermore, the assumption that space is something mental
and not real, not a characteristic of things as they are but only
of our mental representations of things, in no way helps to
explain the necessary and universal validity of geometrical judg
ments. 2 Kant thinks that it does because he confounds the
necessity of apprehended spatial law, or relation, or connexion,
with the universal validity of the judgment whereby we appre
hend such law as necessary.
" No doubt [writes Prichard ], if it be a law OF OUR PERCEIVING NATURE
that, whenever we perceive an object as a three-sided figure, the object AS
PERCEIVED contains three angles, it follows that any object AS PERCEIVED
[i.e. perceived as a three-sided figure] will conform to this law ; just as if it be
a law OF THINGS AS THEY ARE IN THEMSELVES that three-sided figures con
tain three angles, all three-sided figures will IN THEMSELVES contain three
angles. But what has to be explained is the universal applicability, not of a
law, but of a judgment about a law. For Kant s real problem is to explain
why our judgment that a three-sided figure must contain three angles must
apply to all three-sided figures. Of course if it be granted that in the judg
ment we apprehend the true law, the problem may be regarded as solved.
But how are we to know that what we judge is the true law ? The answer is
in no way facilitated by the supposition that the judgment relates to our
perceiving nature. IT CAN JUST AS WELL BE URGED THAT WHAT WE THINK
TO BE A NECESSITY OF OUR PERCEIVING NATURE IS NOT A NECESSITY OF
IT AS THAT WHAT WE THINK TO BE A NECESSITY OF THINGS AS THEY
ARE IN THEMSELVES IS NOT A NECESSITY OF THEM. 4 The best, Or rather
the only possible, answer is simply that that of which we apprehend the
necessity must be true, or, in other words, that we must accept the validity
ot thought. . . . 5 No vindication of a judgment in which we are conscious
1 PRICHARD, p. 62 (italics ours). 2 C/. vol. i., 55.
3 Op. cit., pp. 63, 65-6 (capitals ours).
4 Cf. vol. i., 59, where this objection is urged against the whole reasoning of
the Critique.
5 In other words, that which the intellect, reflecting on the data of human
experience, is necessitated to think as involved in this experience, is real : what is
given to the mind for its interpretation is real : and what is seen by the mind to be
necessarily involved in the given is likewise real. This is the thesis on which scho
lastics have at all times emphatically insisted : The proper object of intellect is
reality: Objectum intellectus est Ens (cf. Science of Logic, ii., 215, p. 58). This
202 THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE
of a necessity could do more than take the problem a stage further back by
basing it upon some other consciousness of a necessity, and since this latter
judgment could be questioned for precisely the same reason, we should only
be embarking upon an infinite process."
When, therefore, Kant thinks that he has solved " the original
problem of the conformity of things to our minds " by the con
tention that the " things " about which we judge are not " things
as they are in themselves" but "perceptions," " it can be forced
upon him again, even after he thinks he has solved it, in the new
form of that of the conformity within the mind of perceiving and
thinking". 1 Of course Kant "solves" the problem, stated in
this latter form, by the contention that just as what we perceive
is not the thing in itself but a mental impression produced by
the latter and made conformable to the mind s perceiving nature
by the forms of sense perception, so what we think or conceive or
judge is not the perception but the perception transfigured once
more and made conformable with the mind s thinking or judging
nature by the categories of the understanding : a solution which
really empties the question of the validity of knowledge of all
intelligible meaning by issuing in the " logical idealism " which
identifies thought with its object and denies all " extra-logical "
reality. 2