127. THE MAIN DIFFICULTY.
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 75 76 78 79 80 81 83
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101
102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 112 113 114 115 117 118
119 120 121 122 123 124 125 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135
138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148
We must next examine a
form of difficulty which is brought against the theory of immedi
ate sense perception and plausibly supported by appeal to a
variety of facts commonly described as "sense illusions" (118).
It may be stated as follows : 3
If that which is present to consciousness in perception, that
of which we are directly and immediately aware, be the external
reality, then contradictory predicates would be true of the same
reality. But this is obviously impossible. Therefore what is
present to consciousness is not the external reality but a psychic
or mental " appearance " or " representation " produced by the
1 And no supporter of the theory of mediate or representative sense perception.
2 Knowing that " what it is really and externally" means "what it appears to
the normal perceiver " : the very real but normal and uniform subjective influence
of the perceiver s organism on " what it appears," being an element of difference
which is tacitly understood to be really there but to be left out of account in equi-
parating the meaning of those two phrases.
3 C/. JEANNIBRE, op. cit., pp. 398-9.
1 60 THEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
reality, and from which under due conditions we can infer the
latter. 1 And that contradictory predicates are affirmed of what
is present to consciousness is abundantly evident from facts like
the following : " Tepid water is cold to the hot hand and hot to
the cold hand (i.e. is simultaneously cold and not cold) ; the
same house is larger or smaller, the same tower is square or
round, according to the distance of the observer ; the sun is
two feet in diameter to one person and one foot in diameter to
another, though its real magnitude is great and does not change ;
the same colour is red to one and green to another (i.e. to a
Daltonian) ; the same substance is sweet to one and bitter to
another ; the same insect is tiny or large according as seen with
the naked eye or through a microscope ; things are purple or
yellow according as seen through purple or yellow glasses ; stars
are now visible which have ceased to exist long ages ago ;
sometimes people see two suns in the heavens, while there is
only one de facto ; and so of innumerable other examples ". "
Now such facts can be easily explained, and all contradiction
avoided, if the contradictory predicates be understood to have for
their subjects not the one self-identical external reality, but the
mental appearances produced by it ; for while it remains the
same these do indeed differ through change in the subjective
and the external or spatial conditions of perception, so that it is
not to tlie same subject that the contradictory predicates refer.
Hence in all such examples as those referred to, the copula "is"
means "appears " : otherwise error is incurred by an unlawful
transition from the order of appearances to the order of reality. 3
Now in reply to this difficulty we purpose showing firstly,
that the manner it suggests of avoiding self-contradiction is not
the only way of doing so, or in other words that perceptionism
as propounded in the preceding sections is in no way self-con-
1 The conclusion, as formulated by JEANNIKRE (op. cit., pp. 398-9), " Ergo, ne
violctur pyincipium contradictions, dicendum est realitatem sensibus referri, non nt est
in seipsa, sed ut apparet sensibus " : " reality is reported by the senses not as it is in
itself, but as it appears to the senses," seems to make the (perceived) " appearance "
and the (known) " externality" two aspects or modes or conditions of one and the
same reality (cf. infra, 128, 129) ; but he clearly supposes that contradiction|can be
avoided only by holding that in every such case the contradictory predicates should
be understood to refer not to the external reality but to the mental appearances,
which are really different and therefore really susceptible of contradictory predicates,
while the external reality of which they are appearances remains of course one
and the same unchanged reality.
"JEANNIERE, ibid. 3 Ibid., p. 399.
INTUITIVE REALISM 161
tradictory ; and secondly, that there are very grave reasons against
adopting the suggested distinction between " mental appear
ances " and "external reality" as a satisfactory explanation of
the facts.
First, then, the facts alleged are undeniable. Moreover, it
must be admitted that if " what reality appears to the individual
perceiver in any and every condition, organic and extra-organic,
of perception," be judged to be a function of the " reality as it is
externally," in other words if naif perceptionism, which does
not take account of the part played by the actual conditions,
organic and extra-organic, of perception, in determining how the
external reality appears, be adopted, then indeed self-contradic
tion would result : water would be simultaneously hot and not
hot, the same colour would be red and not red, etc., etc. But if,
on the contrary, our interpretation of "what the thing is really
and externally " takes the influence of these conditions into ac
count, and allows for them, if it is realized that we know " what
the thing is really and externally " only by " what it appears to
the normal perceiver," so that this latter appearance is always
understood to be implied in the very meaning of "what the
thing is really and externally," 1 then, while what we perceive
is not a mental appearance but the extramental reality, not a
single one of the predications in the examples cited, or in any
other examples, is really self-contradictory. For whenever in
such a case we make a number of incompatible predications
about the perceived reality, they are incompatible because they
refer to what the thing appears under different sets of (organic or
extra-organic) conditions : and only one predication (in respect to
the domain of predication in question), whether it be among the
predications actually made or not, can refer to " the thing as it
is really and externally," "what it is really and externally"
being known to us only through " what it appears to the normal
perceiver," since this mode of appearance is a real function of
" what the thing is really and externally ". It is a question of
understanding what we mean by our assertions that material
things " are such or such really and externally". This has been
explained already, and we may refer the reader again to our
1 I.e. the function of appearing in a certain way in normal conditions of percep
tion is a real function of the external reality, and is precisely the function, and the
only function, which makes it possible for us to know intellectually what the thing
is, in so far as we have (inadequate) intellectual knowledge of this latter.
VOL. II. II
1 62 THEOR Y OF KNO VVLEDGE
discussion of one of the examples given above, that of Dalton
ism (126). For the sake of illustration let us take another
example. A person in one part of the world sees the sun high
in the heavens " a foot in diameter" ; another in a different part
of the world sees it sinking near the horizon " two feet in dia
meter". Suppose they judge it accordingly. Both judgments
refer to the same "external reality ". Both predicates are right
if they are referred to "what this reality appears" to each in the
two separate sets of spatial conditions ; both predicates are wrong
if they are referred to "what this reality is externally (in respect
of size or diameter) ". What it is externally in this respect is
not what it appears to any one or more individuals, for such
appearances include the influence of different spatial conditions
of distance and perspective: what it is really and externally in
point of size, is what its normally appearing size which differs
in varying spatial conditions is interpreted to be for a reality
situated at such a distance from normal perceivers. 1
This, of course, raises again the question, How do we know
intellectually what a reality is really and externally ? And par
ticularly it raises the question of which more presently as to
the significance of our concept of space. How can we know
(intellectually) that a reality is external, or what it is externally,
otherwise than by seeing, through reflection, that the contents of
our abstract intellectual concepts of extension, externality, space,
etc., given in the concretely felt extensity and externality of the
immediate data of sense perception, are real ; and that when a
sense datum appears to the normal perceiver as extended, spatial,
external, it is therefore not only conceived intellectually to be so,
but is really so ? The two people looking at the sun perceive
something real. How do we or they know? How else but be
cause we and they regard sense perception as a process which
makes us aware of reality? They perceive something extra-
mental and external? Again, how do we or they know? Be
cause we regard the sensuously felt extramentality of the immediate
data of consciousness as being eo ipso real, and the sensuously felt
externality of such data as being in normal conditions of sense per-
1 C/. JEANNIERE, op. cit., pp. 413-14 : " Ex eo quod res apparet vg. dulcis aut
amara, quadrata aut rotunda, rubra aut viridis, non est certum illam rem esse talem
qualis apparet, nisi intellectus attenderit ad omnes sensus qui aliquid de ea referunt,
et constiterit ab eis illam rem mocJo iwrmali referri ".
"/.P. Gxtrz-snbjective,
INTUITIVE REALISM 163
ception eo ipso real. But suppose we refuse to regard any im
mediate data of sense consciousness as being at all extramental,
and insist on regarding them all as infra-subjective, intramental
entities, how then are we ever to know that there is anything
beyond, anything really extramental or external ?
Realist supporters of the theory of mediate sense perception
have recourse to the principle of causality a procedure which we
need not re-examine here. But let us return to the difficulty set
forth above, and endeavour to show in the second place how un
satisfactory it is to account for the apparent contradictions of
sense perception by recourse to the view that in preception we
become immediately aware only of " appearances ".
If in sense perception we become immediately aware only
of what are (intellectually interpreted to be) subjective, psychic,
mental states, and not of anything (interpreted to be) external
(or even extramental), then, since on the one hand intellect con
ceives, and interprets in judgment, only the content 1 of these
states, and since on the other hand it is not contended that in
tellect can, independently of sense, come into cognitive relation
with (what is interpreted as) external reality, 2 it would seem to
follow necessarily that all our intellectual knowledge, all our con
cepts, predicates, and judgments are of the real domain of inental
states only, externality itself, perceived or conceived, concrete
or abstract, being no exception, but just a mental state like all
the others. No doubt, the concept of cause, like that of sub
stance, is derived from these states and is validly applied to them
to bring to light their real implications ; but how can it bring to
light real externality as an implication of them if the concept of
externality itself is emptied of real validity by the contention
that the concrete sense correlate immediately felt externality
from which the concept is derived, is not real externality at all
but merely a feature of a state of consciousness? (104, in).
When, therefore, Jeanniere asserts that by the senses we attain
1 Including the real implications of this content.
2 I.e. this contention is not put forward at least by scholastics, who, as defenders
of realism, are contemplated in the text. It is the scholastic view that intellect
directly apprehends the real self in its conscious processes, and rightly interprets
the self as an extramental reality, i.e. a reality whose real being (" esse ") is inde
pendent of its being consciously apprehended (its "percifi"), but that even such
conception has for its content only the sense content of the direct conscious pro
cesses by which such intellectual apprehension is conditioned (cf. 100) ; but
scholastics do not contend that intellect has any apprehension or conception of
external or non-self reality independently of the data furnished by sense (100, 105).
1 64 THEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
" to things not in themselves but in their appearances," T and
that nevertheless * things can be known as they are in themselves,
i.e. so that we can attribute to them predicates which are really
intrinsic to them, " 2 he is equivalently asserting that concepts
whose real contents are derived only from conscious states of
the self have contents which are really intrinsic to external or
non-self reality : for only if they have such contents are they
really intrinsic " (in content) to this reality. But it is only if
the latter is given in the concrete, felt externality of the immedi
ate data of " external " sense perception, and if the abstract con
cept of externality (derived from this concrete) is thus known to
be really valid, that our other concepts can be known to have
contents really intrinsic to external reality.
Furthermore, it is useless to discuss what qualities can or
cannot be attributed to "external " things, or "things as they
really are " until the real validity of our abstract intellectual con
cept of externality is first vindicated. In support of the main
objection stated above, Jeanniere argues that because e.g. the
external object is a square tower, and the perceived object is not
a square tower (but a round tower), therefore the perceived ob
ject is not the external object. But this assumes that we know
that there is a reality external to us, and ivhat it is really and ex
ternally, while the real difficulty of his own position (that sense
only makes us aware of conscious states of the self, called " ap
pearances") is to show how he can know any object whatsoever
to be an external reality.
"According to the perceptionist," he writes, "the appearance (perceived
object) = external object (that which is outside me). Now, facts prove this
to be inadmissible. Let us give these two in syllogistic form : (i) The ex
ternal object is a square tower ; but the perceived object (appearance] is not
a square tower (but a round tower) ; therefore the perceived object is not
the external object. (2} The perceived object (the appearance} is actual ;
but the external object is not actual (v.g. a star extinct ten thousand years
ago} ; therefore tJic perceived object is not the external object. To my very
great confusion (he continues), I have to confess that the replies to those two
common syllogisms (second figure ; mood, Catncstres} have always appeared
to me unintelligible. The data of physiology, says the Abbe COSTE, ;; re-
1 He refers of course to external things; and the expression means that by the
senses we attain not to the external things but to mental states. The ambiguity of
such modes of expression wilt be examined later (128, 129).
2 " Praedicata quae eis vere sint intrinseca." Op. cit., p. 417; supra, 123,
p. 108, n. 2.
K Rev. da Clcrge franfais, ist August, 1903, p. 534.
INTUITIVE REALISM 165
move all doubt that the direct object of our visual perception is the effect of
the retinal image, as the retinal image itself is the effect of the external
body. With the same author, I regard the thesis of the Abbe DuBOSC on
TV/,? Formal Objectivity of Colours * as undoubtedly ingenious, but as not
proven." 2
Now we doubt if any reflecting perceptionist would allow that his view is
fairly expressed by the formula " appearance (perceived object) = external ob
ject ". We doubt if even the unreflecting plain man would hold that what
an individual perceives (" perceived object ") is always the " external object ".
Bearing in mind that sense itself does not pronounce or judge its object to
be internal or external, and that when we speak of the " sense verdict " or
"sense evidence " we always mean our intellectual interpretation of what is
given or presented in sense consciousness, a fact which is sometimes lost
sight of in this connexion, bearing that in mind, our statement of percep-
tionism would be rather something like this : " The object perceived under
normal conditions is identically the real, external object : not of course ade
quately the latter, but a real function or aspect of the latter ". In the second
place we believe that even the naif, unreflecting perceptionist would agree
with us in repudiating the identification of " appearance " and " perceived
object" in the author s description of perceptionism. When an object "ap
pears " or " is presented " to consciousness, whatever be the nature of this
object, whether it be mental or extramental, internal or external, we have a
right to demand justification for the very questionable procedure of setting
up this process of " appearing " or " being presented " as a new object sup
posed to intervene between consciousness and the original object/ 1 Of this
more anon (128, 129). Coming now to the syllogisms, we might ask how any
one who holds that sense reveals to him only mental states can know that
what he judges to be "a square tower" or to be "not actual" is an " ex
ternal object" at all, as distinct from a mental state. But letting even that
pass, the major of the first syllogism means that what appears in sense per
ception tinder normal conditions of distance and perspective as a square
tower is judged to be therefore really and externally a square tower ; and the
minor means that this same reality appears under other conditions as a round
tower, i.e. otherwise than it appears under normal conditions, i.e. otherwise
as "it really and externally is " : from which the only legitimate conclusion is
that what a thing appears under special conditions is not what it appears under
normal conditions (i.e. " what it really and externally is " : the "external ob
ject"). The distinction between what a thing may "look" or "appear"
and what it "is," will be examined below (128, 129). The major of the
second syllogism means " The object (or reality) here and now perceived or
appearing is judged to be (externally) actual " ; the minor means that what
we know otherwise through inferences from other perceptions of external
reality (and we could know nothing of external reality were real externality
not presented, and known to be presented, to sense) enables us to judge
not that the appearing reality (the " perceived object ") has no present exter
nal actuality, and that our present perception is merely of a mental state or
1 Ann. de philos. chret., 1895, t. 130, pp. 449 sqq.; 592 sqq.
"Op. tit., p. 399, n. 3 C/. PRICHARD, op. cit., p. 133.
1 66 THEOR r OF KNO W LEDGE
" appearance," but that the perceived object has not all the external actuality
which we would naturally attribute to it if we interpreted external reality ac
cording to present perceptions and without taking note of the knowledge
gathered from other perceptions, and interpretations and inferences from
these. 1 In the present instance though the star is itself extinct there is real
and external light still travelling from it. The legitimate conclusion from the
premisses is simply that the total actual reality of the external object is not
identical with, or determined solely by, the portion which at any given
moment we can perceive.
As to the Abbe COSTE S assertion, we may merely remark that while the
physiologist can trace the physiological effects of the retinal image on the
optic nerves and on the brain, and while he can say that the concomitant,
or immediate consequent, of the cerebral excitation is a conscious act of
visual perception, no facts brought to light by his order of investigation can
help him in the least to make any assertion whatever on a question con
cerning this wholly new order of phenomenon (i.e. the consciously perceptive
visual act), the question, namely, as to what is the direct object apprehended
through this perceptive act (112, 124).
1 Cf. JEANMERE, op. cit., pp. 413-14 ; supra, p. 162, n. i.
CHAPTER XX.
IDEALISM AND THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN "APPEARANCE"
AND "REALITY".
We must next examine a
form of difficulty which is brought against the theory of immedi
ate sense perception and plausibly supported by appeal to a
variety of facts commonly described as "sense illusions" (118).
It may be stated as follows : 3
If that which is present to consciousness in perception, that
of which we are directly and immediately aware, be the external
reality, then contradictory predicates would be true of the same
reality. But this is obviously impossible. Therefore what is
present to consciousness is not the external reality but a psychic
or mental " appearance " or " representation " produced by the
1 And no supporter of the theory of mediate or representative sense perception.
2 Knowing that " what it is really and externally" means "what it appears to
the normal perceiver " : the very real but normal and uniform subjective influence
of the perceiver s organism on " what it appears," being an element of difference
which is tacitly understood to be really there but to be left out of account in equi-
parating the meaning of those two phrases.
3 C/. JEANNIBRE, op. cit., pp. 398-9.
1 60 THEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
reality, and from which under due conditions we can infer the
latter. 1 And that contradictory predicates are affirmed of what
is present to consciousness is abundantly evident from facts like
the following : " Tepid water is cold to the hot hand and hot to
the cold hand (i.e. is simultaneously cold and not cold) ; the
same house is larger or smaller, the same tower is square or
round, according to the distance of the observer ; the sun is
two feet in diameter to one person and one foot in diameter to
another, though its real magnitude is great and does not change ;
the same colour is red to one and green to another (i.e. to a
Daltonian) ; the same substance is sweet to one and bitter to
another ; the same insect is tiny or large according as seen with
the naked eye or through a microscope ; things are purple or
yellow according as seen through purple or yellow glasses ; stars
are now visible which have ceased to exist long ages ago ;
sometimes people see two suns in the heavens, while there is
only one de facto ; and so of innumerable other examples ". "
Now such facts can be easily explained, and all contradiction
avoided, if the contradictory predicates be understood to have for
their subjects not the one self-identical external reality, but the
mental appearances produced by it ; for while it remains the
same these do indeed differ through change in the subjective
and the external or spatial conditions of perception, so that it is
not to tlie same subject that the contradictory predicates refer.
Hence in all such examples as those referred to, the copula "is"
means "appears " : otherwise error is incurred by an unlawful
transition from the order of appearances to the order of reality. 3
Now in reply to this difficulty we purpose showing firstly,
that the manner it suggests of avoiding self-contradiction is not
the only way of doing so, or in other words that perceptionism
as propounded in the preceding sections is in no way self-con-
1 The conclusion, as formulated by JEANNIKRE (op. cit., pp. 398-9), " Ergo, ne
violctur pyincipium contradictions, dicendum est realitatem sensibus referri, non nt est
in seipsa, sed ut apparet sensibus " : " reality is reported by the senses not as it is in
itself, but as it appears to the senses," seems to make the (perceived) " appearance "
and the (known) " externality" two aspects or modes or conditions of one and the
same reality (cf. infra, 128, 129) ; but he clearly supposes that contradiction|can be
avoided only by holding that in every such case the contradictory predicates should
be understood to refer not to the external reality but to the mental appearances,
which are really different and therefore really susceptible of contradictory predicates,
while the external reality of which they are appearances remains of course one
and the same unchanged reality.
"JEANNIERE, ibid. 3 Ibid., p. 399.
INTUITIVE REALISM 161
tradictory ; and secondly, that there are very grave reasons against
adopting the suggested distinction between " mental appear
ances " and "external reality" as a satisfactory explanation of
the facts.
First, then, the facts alleged are undeniable. Moreover, it
must be admitted that if " what reality appears to the individual
perceiver in any and every condition, organic and extra-organic,
of perception," be judged to be a function of the " reality as it is
externally," in other words if naif perceptionism, which does
not take account of the part played by the actual conditions,
organic and extra-organic, of perception, in determining how the
external reality appears, be adopted, then indeed self-contradic
tion would result : water would be simultaneously hot and not
hot, the same colour would be red and not red, etc., etc. But if,
on the contrary, our interpretation of "what the thing is really
and externally " takes the influence of these conditions into ac
count, and allows for them, if it is realized that we know " what
the thing is really and externally " only by " what it appears to
the normal perceiver," so that this latter appearance is always
understood to be implied in the very meaning of "what the
thing is really and externally," 1 then, while what we perceive
is not a mental appearance but the extramental reality, not a
single one of the predications in the examples cited, or in any
other examples, is really self-contradictory. For whenever in
such a case we make a number of incompatible predications
about the perceived reality, they are incompatible because they
refer to what the thing appears under different sets of (organic or
extra-organic) conditions : and only one predication (in respect to
the domain of predication in question), whether it be among the
predications actually made or not, can refer to " the thing as it
is really and externally," "what it is really and externally"
being known to us only through " what it appears to the normal
perceiver," since this mode of appearance is a real function of
" what the thing is really and externally ". It is a question of
understanding what we mean by our assertions that material
things " are such or such really and externally". This has been
explained already, and we may refer the reader again to our
1 I.e. the function of appearing in a certain way in normal conditions of percep
tion is a real function of the external reality, and is precisely the function, and the
only function, which makes it possible for us to know intellectually what the thing
is, in so far as we have (inadequate) intellectual knowledge of this latter.
VOL. II. II
1 62 THEOR Y OF KNO VVLEDGE
discussion of one of the examples given above, that of Dalton
ism (126). For the sake of illustration let us take another
example. A person in one part of the world sees the sun high
in the heavens " a foot in diameter" ; another in a different part
of the world sees it sinking near the horizon " two feet in dia
meter". Suppose they judge it accordingly. Both judgments
refer to the same "external reality ". Both predicates are right
if they are referred to "what this reality appears" to each in the
two separate sets of spatial conditions ; both predicates are wrong
if they are referred to "what this reality is externally (in respect
of size or diameter) ". What it is externally in this respect is
not what it appears to any one or more individuals, for such
appearances include the influence of different spatial conditions
of distance and perspective: what it is really and externally in
point of size, is what its normally appearing size which differs
in varying spatial conditions is interpreted to be for a reality
situated at such a distance from normal perceivers. 1
This, of course, raises again the question, How do we know
intellectually what a reality is really and externally ? And par
ticularly it raises the question of which more presently as to
the significance of our concept of space. How can we know
(intellectually) that a reality is external, or what it is externally,
otherwise than by seeing, through reflection, that the contents of
our abstract intellectual concepts of extension, externality, space,
etc., given in the concretely felt extensity and externality of the
immediate data of sense perception, are real ; and that when a
sense datum appears to the normal perceiver as extended, spatial,
external, it is therefore not only conceived intellectually to be so,
but is really so ? The two people looking at the sun perceive
something real. How do we or they know? How else but be
cause we and they regard sense perception as a process which
makes us aware of reality? They perceive something extra-
mental and external? Again, how do we or they know? Be
cause we regard the sensuously felt extramentality of the immediate
data of consciousness as being eo ipso real, and the sensuously felt
externality of such data as being in normal conditions of sense per-
1 C/. JEANNIERE, op. cit., pp. 413-14 : " Ex eo quod res apparet vg. dulcis aut
amara, quadrata aut rotunda, rubra aut viridis, non est certum illam rem esse talem
qualis apparet, nisi intellectus attenderit ad omnes sensus qui aliquid de ea referunt,
et constiterit ab eis illam rem mocJo iwrmali referri ".
"/.P. Gxtrz-snbjective,
INTUITIVE REALISM 163
ception eo ipso real. But suppose we refuse to regard any im
mediate data of sense consciousness as being at all extramental,
and insist on regarding them all as infra-subjective, intramental
entities, how then are we ever to know that there is anything
beyond, anything really extramental or external ?
Realist supporters of the theory of mediate sense perception
have recourse to the principle of causality a procedure which we
need not re-examine here. But let us return to the difficulty set
forth above, and endeavour to show in the second place how un
satisfactory it is to account for the apparent contradictions of
sense perception by recourse to the view that in preception we
become immediately aware only of " appearances ".
If in sense perception we become immediately aware only
of what are (intellectually interpreted to be) subjective, psychic,
mental states, and not of anything (interpreted to be) external
(or even extramental), then, since on the one hand intellect con
ceives, and interprets in judgment, only the content 1 of these
states, and since on the other hand it is not contended that in
tellect can, independently of sense, come into cognitive relation
with (what is interpreted as) external reality, 2 it would seem to
follow necessarily that all our intellectual knowledge, all our con
cepts, predicates, and judgments are of the real domain of inental
states only, externality itself, perceived or conceived, concrete
or abstract, being no exception, but just a mental state like all
the others. No doubt, the concept of cause, like that of sub
stance, is derived from these states and is validly applied to them
to bring to light their real implications ; but how can it bring to
light real externality as an implication of them if the concept of
externality itself is emptied of real validity by the contention
that the concrete sense correlate immediately felt externality
from which the concept is derived, is not real externality at all
but merely a feature of a state of consciousness? (104, in).
When, therefore, Jeanniere asserts that by the senses we attain
1 Including the real implications of this content.
2 I.e. this contention is not put forward at least by scholastics, who, as defenders
of realism, are contemplated in the text. It is the scholastic view that intellect
directly apprehends the real self in its conscious processes, and rightly interprets
the self as an extramental reality, i.e. a reality whose real being (" esse ") is inde
pendent of its being consciously apprehended (its "percifi"), but that even such
conception has for its content only the sense content of the direct conscious pro
cesses by which such intellectual apprehension is conditioned (cf. 100) ; but
scholastics do not contend that intellect has any apprehension or conception of
external or non-self reality independently of the data furnished by sense (100, 105).
1 64 THEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
" to things not in themselves but in their appearances," T and
that nevertheless * things can be known as they are in themselves,
i.e. so that we can attribute to them predicates which are really
intrinsic to them, " 2 he is equivalently asserting that concepts
whose real contents are derived only from conscious states of
the self have contents which are really intrinsic to external or
non-self reality : for only if they have such contents are they
really intrinsic " (in content) to this reality. But it is only if
the latter is given in the concrete, felt externality of the immedi
ate data of " external " sense perception, and if the abstract con
cept of externality (derived from this concrete) is thus known to
be really valid, that our other concepts can be known to have
contents really intrinsic to external reality.
Furthermore, it is useless to discuss what qualities can or
cannot be attributed to "external " things, or "things as they
really are " until the real validity of our abstract intellectual con
cept of externality is first vindicated. In support of the main
objection stated above, Jeanniere argues that because e.g. the
external object is a square tower, and the perceived object is not
a square tower (but a round tower), therefore the perceived ob
ject is not the external object. But this assumes that we know
that there is a reality external to us, and ivhat it is really and ex
ternally, while the real difficulty of his own position (that sense
only makes us aware of conscious states of the self, called " ap
pearances") is to show how he can know any object whatsoever
to be an external reality.
"According to the perceptionist," he writes, "the appearance (perceived
object) = external object (that which is outside me). Now, facts prove this
to be inadmissible. Let us give these two in syllogistic form : (i) The ex
ternal object is a square tower ; but the perceived object (appearance] is not
a square tower (but a round tower) ; therefore the perceived object is not
the external object. (2} The perceived object (the appearance} is actual ;
but the external object is not actual (v.g. a star extinct ten thousand years
ago} ; therefore tJic perceived object is not the external object. To my very
great confusion (he continues), I have to confess that the replies to those two
common syllogisms (second figure ; mood, Catncstres} have always appeared
to me unintelligible. The data of physiology, says the Abbe COSTE, ;; re-
1 He refers of course to external things; and the expression means that by the
senses we attain not to the external things but to mental states. The ambiguity of
such modes of expression wilt be examined later (128, 129).
2 " Praedicata quae eis vere sint intrinseca." Op. cit., p. 417; supra, 123,
p. 108, n. 2.
K Rev. da Clcrge franfais, ist August, 1903, p. 534.
INTUITIVE REALISM 165
move all doubt that the direct object of our visual perception is the effect of
the retinal image, as the retinal image itself is the effect of the external
body. With the same author, I regard the thesis of the Abbe DuBOSC on
TV/,? Formal Objectivity of Colours * as undoubtedly ingenious, but as not
proven." 2
Now we doubt if any reflecting perceptionist would allow that his view is
fairly expressed by the formula " appearance (perceived object) = external ob
ject ". We doubt if even the unreflecting plain man would hold that what
an individual perceives (" perceived object ") is always the " external object ".
Bearing in mind that sense itself does not pronounce or judge its object to
be internal or external, and that when we speak of the " sense verdict " or
"sense evidence " we always mean our intellectual interpretation of what is
given or presented in sense consciousness, a fact which is sometimes lost
sight of in this connexion, bearing that in mind, our statement of percep-
tionism would be rather something like this : " The object perceived under
normal conditions is identically the real, external object : not of course ade
quately the latter, but a real function or aspect of the latter ". In the second
place we believe that even the naif, unreflecting perceptionist would agree
with us in repudiating the identification of " appearance " and " perceived
object" in the author s description of perceptionism. When an object "ap
pears " or " is presented " to consciousness, whatever be the nature of this
object, whether it be mental or extramental, internal or external, we have a
right to demand justification for the very questionable procedure of setting
up this process of " appearing " or " being presented " as a new object sup
posed to intervene between consciousness and the original object/ 1 Of this
more anon (128, 129). Coming now to the syllogisms, we might ask how any
one who holds that sense reveals to him only mental states can know that
what he judges to be "a square tower" or to be "not actual" is an " ex
ternal object" at all, as distinct from a mental state. But letting even that
pass, the major of the first syllogism means that what appears in sense per
ception tinder normal conditions of distance and perspective as a square
tower is judged to be therefore really and externally a square tower ; and the
minor means that this same reality appears under other conditions as a round
tower, i.e. otherwise than it appears under normal conditions, i.e. otherwise
as "it really and externally is " : from which the only legitimate conclusion is
that what a thing appears under special conditions is not what it appears under
normal conditions (i.e. " what it really and externally is " : the "external ob
ject"). The distinction between what a thing may "look" or "appear"
and what it "is," will be examined below (128, 129). The major of the
second syllogism means " The object (or reality) here and now perceived or
appearing is judged to be (externally) actual " ; the minor means that what
we know otherwise through inferences from other perceptions of external
reality (and we could know nothing of external reality were real externality
not presented, and known to be presented, to sense) enables us to judge
not that the appearing reality (the " perceived object ") has no present exter
nal actuality, and that our present perception is merely of a mental state or
1 Ann. de philos. chret., 1895, t. 130, pp. 449 sqq.; 592 sqq.
"Op. tit., p. 399, n. 3 C/. PRICHARD, op. cit., p. 133.
1 66 THEOR r OF KNO W LEDGE
" appearance," but that the perceived object has not all the external actuality
which we would naturally attribute to it if we interpreted external reality ac
cording to present perceptions and without taking note of the knowledge
gathered from other perceptions, and interpretations and inferences from
these. 1 In the present instance though the star is itself extinct there is real
and external light still travelling from it. The legitimate conclusion from the
premisses is simply that the total actual reality of the external object is not
identical with, or determined solely by, the portion which at any given
moment we can perceive.
As to the Abbe COSTE S assertion, we may merely remark that while the
physiologist can trace the physiological effects of the retinal image on the
optic nerves and on the brain, and while he can say that the concomitant,
or immediate consequent, of the cerebral excitation is a conscious act of
visual perception, no facts brought to light by his order of investigation can
help him in the least to make any assertion whatever on a question con
cerning this wholly new order of phenomenon (i.e. the consciously perceptive
visual act), the question, namely, as to what is the direct object apprehended
through this perceptive act (112, 124).
1 Cf. JEANMERE, op. cit., pp. 413-14 ; supra, p. 162, n. i.
CHAPTER XX.
IDEALISM AND THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN "APPEARANCE"
AND "REALITY".