1 66. KANT S MORAL DOGMATISM OF THE PRACTICAL REASON.
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101
102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 111 112 113 114 115 116 117 118
119 120 121 122 123 124 125 126 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135
138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148
The most influential subjectivist theory of certitude is un
doubtedly the "moral dogmatism" of Kant. Hume had in
ferred from Sensism the impossibility of any knowledge of
absolutely universal and necessary truths. Against this con
clusion Kant s Critique of Pure Reason had asserted, and started
from, the undeniable fact of the existence of such knowledge.
So, too, English Sensism had endeavoured to reduce moral ob
ligation or duty to an egoistic, utilitarian dictate of self-interest.
And against this Kant s Critique of Practical Reason asserted,
and started from, the undeniable fact of the existence of a moral
law that is utterly irreducible to any such dictate.
Is not duty often in conflict with the inclinations of self-
interest? To explain duty, therefore, as springing from any
such motive is to attempt the impossible. The English and
Scottish moralists had imagined that a " moral sense," inclining
the human heart to benevolence, sympathy, enlightened self-
interest, could adequately account for the growth and develop
ment in man of the consciousness of duty, the sense of moral
obligation. This Kant regarded as utterly erroneous and de
structive of morality. A person may be sincere and truthful
and honourable from the motive of an enlightened self-interest
in his own good name and reputation. But the moral law
dictates that he be sincere and truthful and honourable even at
the sacrifice of his own personal interest and reputation. Its
dictate is above all personal interests, superior to all individual
considerations, exempt from all particular conditions : it is an
unconditional or categorical imperative.
Moreover, the moral law as such simply dictates that we
Jo tiie right because it is tJie right, without prescribing the objects
RANT S MORAL DOGMATISM 327
or contents of our individual moral acts. In other words it is a
pure form, which says simply : Do your duty because it is your
duty. The theory of the moral act he calls a metaphysic : the
" metaphysic of morals ".
The dictate of the moral law, then, is wholly disinterested :
it does not seek any end ulterior to itself: it commands the right
for sake of the right. It is its own end. Moreover, transcending
as it does all individual interests, it is a universal law, and is
capable of formulation in absolute or universal terms. For
instance : So act that the maxim of your conduct can prevail as a
universal law. Further, the moral law forbids that the will be
subordinate, as a means to an end, by seeking any good beyond
the moral act itself. Hence also : Act always so that human
nature, whether in yourself or in others, be always an end, not a
means. A will that would pursue an ideal of goodness extrinsic
or foreign to itself would be heteronomous, or subject to an alien
law ; but the moral law is autonomous : the practical reason, or
will, finds in itself the true law of its own proper activity. Hence
this final Kantian expression of the moral law as the form of
moral conduct : Consider the idea of the will of every rational
being as the idea of a will dictating universal laws.
Armed with this apparently lofty and stoic conception of the
moral law, Kant asks himself what does it imply. What " pos
tulates of the practical reason " are inseparable from it ? There
are three such postulates.
The first \<$> freedom of the will. If I ought to act morally, it
must be that I can. Thus in the logical order moral responsi
bility implies human freedom as its ratio cognoscendi, while in
the ontological order freedom precedes responsibility as its ratio
essendi.
The second implication of the moral law is the immortality of
the soul. And why or how ? For this reason and in this wise :
The moral law dictates duty for duty s sake and forbids us to
subordinate duty to the attainment of happiness. On the con
trary, duty often demands the sacrifice of personal interest, well-
being, happiness, satisfaction. Nevertheless reason revolts, and
rightly revolts, against the idea that duty and happiness be
for ever separated. Does not the notion of the supreme good
imply all good, and therefore the union of the good which is
righteousness with the good which is happiness ? But such union
cannot be realized in the conditions of man s moral life here on
328 TffEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
earth. There must, therefore, be a future state of existence in
which the soul can attain ever more fully to the moral ideal,
where it can taste and enjoy, without however having sought,
the happiness which must reward its fidelity to duty.
The third postulate of morality is the existence of God. For
when the soul shall enjoy the reward of its virtue, when duty
and happiness coincide, when the bonum supremum will be the
bonum consummatum, such consummation of the universal order
can only be conceived to be the work of an All-Powerful and
All-Holy Will. There must be a God : the author of the
physical order and the moral order, of the world of sense and
the world of intellect, of the domain of appearances or phenomena
and the domain of realities or noumena, Who will unify all in
one universal and indefectible harmony.
Such, then, are the affirmations of the practical reason : the
moral law exists as an absolute dictate, a categorical imperative ;
its conditions are freedom, immortality, and God s existence.
And religion, based upon morality, derives its legitimate sway
over man, its authority and its credentials, from the practical
reason.
But what are those affirmations of the practical reason worth ?
What are their credentials and authority ? They are not based
on knowledge, but on a need or dictate of the will.
Knowledge is the achievement of man s speculative reason
(46). But it is confined to phenomena which occur in space
and time and are subject to the absolute determinism of the law
of universal causation. Man s speculative reason can attain to
no knowledge either of a substantial soul exempt in its acts from
the absolute determinism of physical antecedents and capable
of surviving bodily death, or of an Absolute Being transcending
the phenomenal universe (46, 54). It may, and indeed must,
think them, but only as problematic : it cannot know them to be
real. Neither, however, can it know them to \>& unreal. Know
ledge has simply nothing to say of them. Nevertheless we will,
and cannot help willing, the morally good ; and therefore we
believe, and cannot help believing, what this implies. Conse
quently we will, and have a natural need to will, that there be a
free and immortal soul in man, and that God, the Supreme Good,
exist ; and we believe, and cannot help believing, in the reality
of what the will thus dictates to be real. The foundation, there
fore, of moral or ethical certitude, and of religious faith, is the
KANT S MORAL DOGMATISM 329
need of our nature to give credence to certain ideas. By nature we
are endowed with will or practical reason, the seat or source or
principle of moral conduct. Moral conduct is a fact ; so is its
source or principle. They are of our very nature. In the
dictate of moral conduct we find certain necessary implications :
human freedom and immortality, and the existence of God.
This dictate of our nature as moral beings furnishes each of us
individually with a motive that is subjectively sufficient for
believing in the reality of these implications : though their ob
jective reality falls necessarily beyond the scope of our knowledge ;
their reality cannot possibly be an object of knowledge. Kant
admits this expressly. "All faith," he says, 1 "is an assent that
is subjectively sufficient, but conscious of its objective insuffi
ciency; faith therefore is opposed to knowledge."
Nor can this consciousness that God, freedom and immortal
ity are unknowable, unattainable by the speculative reason,
militate against the personal certitude of our belief in them as
realities : for reflection on the speculative reason shows that such
realities, being suprasensible, cannot possibly be its objects,
cannot belong to the sphere of knowledge or science. The
Critique of Pure Reason established this. Its achievement in
regard to them was to " remove knowledge in order to make
room for belief": 2 and thus "to render a signal service to
humanity by removing morality and religion from the domain
of science and from the consequent corroding influence of
scientific doubt ". 3 The limits of the scientific knowledge attain
able by the speculative reason being thus duly recognized, the
primacy of the practical reason, the supremacy of its influence
in determining the certitude of personal belief in those supra-
sensible realities, is manifest. For the dictate of the practical
reason, the categorical imperative of conscience, implies and
demands belief in God, freedom and immortality, as realities ;
and at the same time this dictate (with all that it involves)
transcends the sensible or phenomenal domain of the speculative
reason and attains by way of belief to the real or noumenal do
main of being. 4 Thus, then, the scepticism or phenomenism
1 Qu est-ce que s orienter dans la pensie. Edited Sn the Melanges de Logique,
apud MERCIER, op. cit., 77, p. 173. Mercier s exposition (ibid.) has been closely
followed in the text above.
* Critique of Pure Reason, Pref. pp. xxx and xxi (tr. MU LLRR, pp. 700-1), quoted
above, vol. i., 46, p. 172, n. i.
3 Vol. i., 46, p. 172 ; cf. 56, pp. 199-200. * Cf. vol. i., 46, p. 172.
330 THEOR Y OF KNO WLRDGE
of the speculative reason is seen to be a condition of, and a pre
paration for, the moral dogmatism of the practical reason.
The most influential subjectivist theory of certitude is un
doubtedly the "moral dogmatism" of Kant. Hume had in
ferred from Sensism the impossibility of any knowledge of
absolutely universal and necessary truths. Against this con
clusion Kant s Critique of Pure Reason had asserted, and started
from, the undeniable fact of the existence of such knowledge.
So, too, English Sensism had endeavoured to reduce moral ob
ligation or duty to an egoistic, utilitarian dictate of self-interest.
And against this Kant s Critique of Practical Reason asserted,
and started from, the undeniable fact of the existence of a moral
law that is utterly irreducible to any such dictate.
Is not duty often in conflict with the inclinations of self-
interest? To explain duty, therefore, as springing from any
such motive is to attempt the impossible. The English and
Scottish moralists had imagined that a " moral sense," inclining
the human heart to benevolence, sympathy, enlightened self-
interest, could adequately account for the growth and develop
ment in man of the consciousness of duty, the sense of moral
obligation. This Kant regarded as utterly erroneous and de
structive of morality. A person may be sincere and truthful
and honourable from the motive of an enlightened self-interest
in his own good name and reputation. But the moral law
dictates that he be sincere and truthful and honourable even at
the sacrifice of his own personal interest and reputation. Its
dictate is above all personal interests, superior to all individual
considerations, exempt from all particular conditions : it is an
unconditional or categorical imperative.
Moreover, the moral law as such simply dictates that we
Jo tiie right because it is tJie right, without prescribing the objects
RANT S MORAL DOGMATISM 327
or contents of our individual moral acts. In other words it is a
pure form, which says simply : Do your duty because it is your
duty. The theory of the moral act he calls a metaphysic : the
" metaphysic of morals ".
The dictate of the moral law, then, is wholly disinterested :
it does not seek any end ulterior to itself: it commands the right
for sake of the right. It is its own end. Moreover, transcending
as it does all individual interests, it is a universal law, and is
capable of formulation in absolute or universal terms. For
instance : So act that the maxim of your conduct can prevail as a
universal law. Further, the moral law forbids that the will be
subordinate, as a means to an end, by seeking any good beyond
the moral act itself. Hence also : Act always so that human
nature, whether in yourself or in others, be always an end, not a
means. A will that would pursue an ideal of goodness extrinsic
or foreign to itself would be heteronomous, or subject to an alien
law ; but the moral law is autonomous : the practical reason, or
will, finds in itself the true law of its own proper activity. Hence
this final Kantian expression of the moral law as the form of
moral conduct : Consider the idea of the will of every rational
being as the idea of a will dictating universal laws.
Armed with this apparently lofty and stoic conception of the
moral law, Kant asks himself what does it imply. What " pos
tulates of the practical reason " are inseparable from it ? There
are three such postulates.
The first \<$> freedom of the will. If I ought to act morally, it
must be that I can. Thus in the logical order moral responsi
bility implies human freedom as its ratio cognoscendi, while in
the ontological order freedom precedes responsibility as its ratio
essendi.
The second implication of the moral law is the immortality of
the soul. And why or how ? For this reason and in this wise :
The moral law dictates duty for duty s sake and forbids us to
subordinate duty to the attainment of happiness. On the con
trary, duty often demands the sacrifice of personal interest, well-
being, happiness, satisfaction. Nevertheless reason revolts, and
rightly revolts, against the idea that duty and happiness be
for ever separated. Does not the notion of the supreme good
imply all good, and therefore the union of the good which is
righteousness with the good which is happiness ? But such union
cannot be realized in the conditions of man s moral life here on
328 TffEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
earth. There must, therefore, be a future state of existence in
which the soul can attain ever more fully to the moral ideal,
where it can taste and enjoy, without however having sought,
the happiness which must reward its fidelity to duty.
The third postulate of morality is the existence of God. For
when the soul shall enjoy the reward of its virtue, when duty
and happiness coincide, when the bonum supremum will be the
bonum consummatum, such consummation of the universal order
can only be conceived to be the work of an All-Powerful and
All-Holy Will. There must be a God : the author of the
physical order and the moral order, of the world of sense and
the world of intellect, of the domain of appearances or phenomena
and the domain of realities or noumena, Who will unify all in
one universal and indefectible harmony.
Such, then, are the affirmations of the practical reason : the
moral law exists as an absolute dictate, a categorical imperative ;
its conditions are freedom, immortality, and God s existence.
And religion, based upon morality, derives its legitimate sway
over man, its authority and its credentials, from the practical
reason.
But what are those affirmations of the practical reason worth ?
What are their credentials and authority ? They are not based
on knowledge, but on a need or dictate of the will.
Knowledge is the achievement of man s speculative reason
(46). But it is confined to phenomena which occur in space
and time and are subject to the absolute determinism of the law
of universal causation. Man s speculative reason can attain to
no knowledge either of a substantial soul exempt in its acts from
the absolute determinism of physical antecedents and capable
of surviving bodily death, or of an Absolute Being transcending
the phenomenal universe (46, 54). It may, and indeed must,
think them, but only as problematic : it cannot know them to be
real. Neither, however, can it know them to \>& unreal. Know
ledge has simply nothing to say of them. Nevertheless we will,
and cannot help willing, the morally good ; and therefore we
believe, and cannot help believing, what this implies. Conse
quently we will, and have a natural need to will, that there be a
free and immortal soul in man, and that God, the Supreme Good,
exist ; and we believe, and cannot help believing, in the reality
of what the will thus dictates to be real. The foundation, there
fore, of moral or ethical certitude, and of religious faith, is the
KANT S MORAL DOGMATISM 329
need of our nature to give credence to certain ideas. By nature we
are endowed with will or practical reason, the seat or source or
principle of moral conduct. Moral conduct is a fact ; so is its
source or principle. They are of our very nature. In the
dictate of moral conduct we find certain necessary implications :
human freedom and immortality, and the existence of God.
This dictate of our nature as moral beings furnishes each of us
individually with a motive that is subjectively sufficient for
believing in the reality of these implications : though their ob
jective reality falls necessarily beyond the scope of our knowledge ;
their reality cannot possibly be an object of knowledge. Kant
admits this expressly. "All faith," he says, 1 "is an assent that
is subjectively sufficient, but conscious of its objective insuffi
ciency; faith therefore is opposed to knowledge."
Nor can this consciousness that God, freedom and immortal
ity are unknowable, unattainable by the speculative reason,
militate against the personal certitude of our belief in them as
realities : for reflection on the speculative reason shows that such
realities, being suprasensible, cannot possibly be its objects,
cannot belong to the sphere of knowledge or science. The
Critique of Pure Reason established this. Its achievement in
regard to them was to " remove knowledge in order to make
room for belief": 2 and thus "to render a signal service to
humanity by removing morality and religion from the domain
of science and from the consequent corroding influence of
scientific doubt ". 3 The limits of the scientific knowledge attain
able by the speculative reason being thus duly recognized, the
primacy of the practical reason, the supremacy of its influence
in determining the certitude of personal belief in those supra-
sensible realities, is manifest. For the dictate of the practical
reason, the categorical imperative of conscience, implies and
demands belief in God, freedom and immortality, as realities ;
and at the same time this dictate (with all that it involves)
transcends the sensible or phenomenal domain of the speculative
reason and attains by way of belief to the real or noumenal do
main of being. 4 Thus, then, the scepticism or phenomenism
1 Qu est-ce que s orienter dans la pensie. Edited Sn the Melanges de Logique,
apud MERCIER, op. cit., 77, p. 173. Mercier s exposition (ibid.) has been closely
followed in the text above.
* Critique of Pure Reason, Pref. pp. xxx and xxi (tr. MU LLRR, pp. 700-1), quoted
above, vol. i., 46, p. 172, n. i.
3 Vol. i., 46, p. 172 ; cf. 56, pp. 199-200. * Cf. vol. i., 46, p. 172.
330 THEOR Y OF KNO WLRDGE
of the speculative reason is seen to be a condition of, and a pre
paration for, the moral dogmatism of the practical reason.