ASSENT AS A TEST OF TRUTH.
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101
102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 111 112 113 114 115 116 117 118
119 120 121 122 123 124 125 126 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135
138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148
The "general assent " to which
we have just referred, De Lamennais proclaims to be the
ultimate test of truth. We have seen how he regards it as the
infallible index of Divinely revealed truth, and contrasts its
dictates with the " unreliable " and mutually contradictory de
liverances of the individual reason (the " sens prive "}. But this
"universal dictate" cannot possibly be the ultimate test of truth,
nor can it possibly supplant, by its appeal to the individual
reason, the function of intrinsic objective evidence.
If each of two individual disputants, e.g. the atheist and the
believer, insists that his own interpretation of facts judged in the
light of evidence is the right one, they may indeed appeal in the
first place, if they so desire, to the general verdict of mankind
on the matter in dispute. But such appeal will not and cannot
of itself settle the question. For the atheist will not recognize,
and the believer ought not to recognize, this general verdict as
conclusive unless and until its authority is seen by its objective
evidence to be a sure guarantee of truth : a point which can be
1 MERCIER, op. cit., 70.
304 THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE
decided for each only by the exercise of his individual reason
judging the credentials of that authority.
Nor can it be said that those universal dictates of the voice
of human nature, those truths of " common sense," are beyond
dispute, so that their rejection would be an abdication of reason.
For if this general assent be put forward as an authority to
which we are expected to yield unquestioning submission, it
will be easy to point out that its testimony should not be
accepted without reserve. Did not men for ages universally
assent to the solidity of the heavens, and to the view that the
sun moves around the earth ? The most, then, that can be said
is that universal belief creates a presumption in favour of truth,
that we should be slower to believe it to be in the wrong than
to be in the right; but of itself it cannot reasonably demand an
assent of reasoned certitude from the individual.
If, however, the general verdict is put forward rather as a sign
or index of the tendency of man s rational nature to assent to
those generally accepted propositions as true, and this seems
to be what De Lamennais intended, then indeed such common
agreement can be a criterion of truth, though not the ultimate
criterion. It can be a criterion in this indirect way. When in
any particular case of common agreement we can convince our
selves by investigation that this agreement is not due to such
accidental causes of error as prejudice, precipitancy, want of
reflection, mal-observation, etc. ; and when, moreover, we see
that it concerns some matter of grave import to man s nature
and destiny, 1 then we can conclude that the universal dictate
or verdict in question is reached through the uniform and normal
functioning, in each individual, of human nature as intelligent
or rational. And from this, unless we gratuitously conclude,
1 Such are the convictions referred to in vol. i., 15, as "truths of common
sense". Among them might be enumerated, for instance, the conviction that the
human mind is capable of attaining to some true knowledge of things ; that an ex
ternal material universe exists independently of human minds; that the universe is
not chaotic but manifests order and furnishes evidence of design, purpose, intelli
gence ; that there is a moral order and that the distinction between a morally right
and a morally wrong is inseparable from human conduct and rooted in man s
nature ; that man is a free and responsible agent ; that in man s actual experience
of himself and the universe there are evidences which point to the actual existence
of an unseen, suprasensible or spiritual domain of reality, to man s dependence on
Higher Powers, to life after death, to the existence of a Supreme, Intelligent
Author and Ruler of the Universe, to man s religious worship of this Supreme
Being as a duty that is consonant with human nature and dictated by man s
natural reason.
TRADITIONALISM 305
with the universal sceptic (ch. iv.), that men generally, in
attaining to such universal convictions by the normal and natural
functioning of human reason, are blindly yielding to impulses
that are rationally unjustifiable,- we must infer the only other
alternative conclusion, viz. that such examples of the universal
accord of human intelligences as we have in those general
dictates or verdicts must be due to the manifestation of truth
or the presentation of reality to all intelligences alike. And in
making this inference we are asserting rational or intellectual
evidence to be the ultimate basis of truth and certitude. For we
are simply interpreting the " common agreement " as an index
of the presence of intrinsic objective evidence for the dictates or
judgments in which men thus universally agree ; and as being
thus a secondary criterion subordinate to the objective evidence
the presence of which it indicates. In this way the "general
assent" is merely an index that the objective evidence of the
truth of the judgment assented to is really there and is really
apprehended by each individual of the assenting masses. It
must be because the truth of the judgment is borne in upon
each by its intrinsic objective evidence that all agree in assenting
to it. Thus, even in cases in which common assent is a criterion
of truth it is subordinate to objective evidence as the supreme
and ultimate criterion.
There are these other considerations also, which show that
"common assent" cannot be an ultimate test, and must itself
rest on objective evidence. How can the individual know (i)
that any given judgment has the common assent of mankind ? (2)
that this common assent, if forthcoming, is not really due in the
case to some accidental cause of general deception, since many
beliefs that were, morally speaking, universal for centuries have
nevertheless been proved erroneous ? (3) that the common assent,
even when the possibility of accidental deception is satisfactorily
excluded, as it can be in certain classes of assents, by virtue of
the intimate connexion of their subject-matter with the essential
conditions and natural needs of human existence (15), is really
a reliable test of the truth of the judgment assented to ? l It
J That in such cases (15) it is a reliable test, is not self-evident, but requires
proof. And the proof cannot lie merely in the fact that the assent is, morally
speaking, universal ; but in the answer to the question : Why is it universal ? The
universality of the assent merely creates a presumption in favour of the truth of the
judgment assented to. But the individual must look to the nature of the judgment
itself. He must weigh the objective evidential appeal which, in its whole concrete
VOL. II. 20
306 THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE
is clear that until he decides those questions for himself he can
not make rational use of the criterion of " common assent ".
And it is equally clear that he can decide them only by the
exercise of his own individual reason, and that the decision must
be based upon the intrinsic objective evidence furnished by their
subject-matter to his own individual reason.
It might be urged, and it seems to have been thought by
the traditionalists, that there is as it were some special virtue in
human reason taken collectively, in "la raison ge nc rale" which
is not in human reason taken individually, something which makes
the former infallible, or at least safe and reliable, where the
latter is unsafe and unreliable. Such a suggestion gains plausi
bility from the undeniable fact that in the search for truth, in
the progressive discovery and proof of truth, many minds are
better than one ; that individuals learn from their fellow-men
most of what they know ; that mankind is in possession of an
accumulated heritage of truth (not, however, unmixed with error)
of which individuals are in varying degrees the sharers; and so on.
But, nevertheless, the suggestion will not bear analysis, and
cannot achieve the object for which it is made. For the attain
ment of truth and certitude is not the work of an impersonal
human intelligence, conceived after the manner of the Averroists ;
nor of human reason existing as a universal a parte rci, as extreme
realism would have it : nor do traditionalists mean anything like
that by the " raison generate " or " common sense " of the race.
The attainment of truth and certitude is the work of individual
human minds ; knowledge is an attribute only of individual minds.
If, therefore, there is not in human minds, taken individually, any
native power or capacity to attain to a certain knowledge of
truth, neither can such power or capacity be forthcoming in the
collectivity : if each of them is essentially unreliable, no conceiv
able collection of them can be reliable, much less infallible. But
it is the collection that traditionalists denote by "common sense,"
or " la raison generate ". By proclaiming, therefore, the power-
context, it makes to his own individual reason : part of that evidential appeal coming,
of course, from the fact that the judgment is generally accepted by mankind. II
he sees, on reflection, that there is adequate intrinsic evidence for its truth, and that
this is the reason why people generally assent to it, he will have satisfied himself
not only that the judgment in question is true, but that the common assent of man
kind to it, and to other similar judgments, is a reasonably safe and reliable test of
the truth of such judgments. But he must see at the same time that this latter test
does not supplant, but rather presupposes as ultimate, the intrinsic evidential appeal
of the judgment to the individual reason.
TRUTHS OF " COMMON SENSE " 307
lessness of the individual reason, they strike equally at the
universal or collective reason. And in fact they do disfigure it
and deprive it of the essential attributes of intelligence or ration
ality by proclaiming its function to be merely that of an organon
or vehicle for the transmission of a body of Divinely revealed
judgments, while denying to human reason individually, and
therefore also collectively, the right to demand or the power to
find any rational justification for its assents by scrutinizing the
evidence, whether intrinsic or extrinsic, for the truth of the judg
ments assented to. In ultimate analysis it is really an abdication
of reason on the part of the individual to assent to any judgment
merely because he finds everyone else assenting to it. For
each and for all alike the ulterior question must inevitably arise ;
Why do any of them or all of them assent to it ? And the answer
must be, either because they have rational grounds of evidence
for so assenting, or because they choose to assent in the absence
of such grounds, that is, blindly and unreasonably. In other
words, the ultimate choice must always be between a rational
assent based on grounds of objective intellectual evidence, or
a blind, instinctive assent which, in a being endowed with the
reflective faculty of intelligence, must inevitably terminate in
universal doubt and scepticism.
The "general assent " to which
we have just referred, De Lamennais proclaims to be the
ultimate test of truth. We have seen how he regards it as the
infallible index of Divinely revealed truth, and contrasts its
dictates with the " unreliable " and mutually contradictory de
liverances of the individual reason (the " sens prive "}. But this
"universal dictate" cannot possibly be the ultimate test of truth,
nor can it possibly supplant, by its appeal to the individual
reason, the function of intrinsic objective evidence.
If each of two individual disputants, e.g. the atheist and the
believer, insists that his own interpretation of facts judged in the
light of evidence is the right one, they may indeed appeal in the
first place, if they so desire, to the general verdict of mankind
on the matter in dispute. But such appeal will not and cannot
of itself settle the question. For the atheist will not recognize,
and the believer ought not to recognize, this general verdict as
conclusive unless and until its authority is seen by its objective
evidence to be a sure guarantee of truth : a point which can be
1 MERCIER, op. cit., 70.
304 THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE
decided for each only by the exercise of his individual reason
judging the credentials of that authority.
Nor can it be said that those universal dictates of the voice
of human nature, those truths of " common sense," are beyond
dispute, so that their rejection would be an abdication of reason.
For if this general assent be put forward as an authority to
which we are expected to yield unquestioning submission, it
will be easy to point out that its testimony should not be
accepted without reserve. Did not men for ages universally
assent to the solidity of the heavens, and to the view that the
sun moves around the earth ? The most, then, that can be said
is that universal belief creates a presumption in favour of truth,
that we should be slower to believe it to be in the wrong than
to be in the right; but of itself it cannot reasonably demand an
assent of reasoned certitude from the individual.
If, however, the general verdict is put forward rather as a sign
or index of the tendency of man s rational nature to assent to
those generally accepted propositions as true, and this seems
to be what De Lamennais intended, then indeed such common
agreement can be a criterion of truth, though not the ultimate
criterion. It can be a criterion in this indirect way. When in
any particular case of common agreement we can convince our
selves by investigation that this agreement is not due to such
accidental causes of error as prejudice, precipitancy, want of
reflection, mal-observation, etc. ; and when, moreover, we see
that it concerns some matter of grave import to man s nature
and destiny, 1 then we can conclude that the universal dictate
or verdict in question is reached through the uniform and normal
functioning, in each individual, of human nature as intelligent
or rational. And from this, unless we gratuitously conclude,
1 Such are the convictions referred to in vol. i., 15, as "truths of common
sense". Among them might be enumerated, for instance, the conviction that the
human mind is capable of attaining to some true knowledge of things ; that an ex
ternal material universe exists independently of human minds; that the universe is
not chaotic but manifests order and furnishes evidence of design, purpose, intelli
gence ; that there is a moral order and that the distinction between a morally right
and a morally wrong is inseparable from human conduct and rooted in man s
nature ; that man is a free and responsible agent ; that in man s actual experience
of himself and the universe there are evidences which point to the actual existence
of an unseen, suprasensible or spiritual domain of reality, to man s dependence on
Higher Powers, to life after death, to the existence of a Supreme, Intelligent
Author and Ruler of the Universe, to man s religious worship of this Supreme
Being as a duty that is consonant with human nature and dictated by man s
natural reason.
TRADITIONALISM 305
with the universal sceptic (ch. iv.), that men generally, in
attaining to such universal convictions by the normal and natural
functioning of human reason, are blindly yielding to impulses
that are rationally unjustifiable,- we must infer the only other
alternative conclusion, viz. that such examples of the universal
accord of human intelligences as we have in those general
dictates or verdicts must be due to the manifestation of truth
or the presentation of reality to all intelligences alike. And in
making this inference we are asserting rational or intellectual
evidence to be the ultimate basis of truth and certitude. For we
are simply interpreting the " common agreement " as an index
of the presence of intrinsic objective evidence for the dictates or
judgments in which men thus universally agree ; and as being
thus a secondary criterion subordinate to the objective evidence
the presence of which it indicates. In this way the "general
assent" is merely an index that the objective evidence of the
truth of the judgment assented to is really there and is really
apprehended by each individual of the assenting masses. It
must be because the truth of the judgment is borne in upon
each by its intrinsic objective evidence that all agree in assenting
to it. Thus, even in cases in which common assent is a criterion
of truth it is subordinate to objective evidence as the supreme
and ultimate criterion.
There are these other considerations also, which show that
"common assent" cannot be an ultimate test, and must itself
rest on objective evidence. How can the individual know (i)
that any given judgment has the common assent of mankind ? (2)
that this common assent, if forthcoming, is not really due in the
case to some accidental cause of general deception, since many
beliefs that were, morally speaking, universal for centuries have
nevertheless been proved erroneous ? (3) that the common assent,
even when the possibility of accidental deception is satisfactorily
excluded, as it can be in certain classes of assents, by virtue of
the intimate connexion of their subject-matter with the essential
conditions and natural needs of human existence (15), is really
a reliable test of the truth of the judgment assented to ? l It
J That in such cases (15) it is a reliable test, is not self-evident, but requires
proof. And the proof cannot lie merely in the fact that the assent is, morally
speaking, universal ; but in the answer to the question : Why is it universal ? The
universality of the assent merely creates a presumption in favour of the truth of the
judgment assented to. But the individual must look to the nature of the judgment
itself. He must weigh the objective evidential appeal which, in its whole concrete
VOL. II. 20
306 THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE
is clear that until he decides those questions for himself he can
not make rational use of the criterion of " common assent ".
And it is equally clear that he can decide them only by the
exercise of his own individual reason, and that the decision must
be based upon the intrinsic objective evidence furnished by their
subject-matter to his own individual reason.
It might be urged, and it seems to have been thought by
the traditionalists, that there is as it were some special virtue in
human reason taken collectively, in "la raison ge nc rale" which
is not in human reason taken individually, something which makes
the former infallible, or at least safe and reliable, where the
latter is unsafe and unreliable. Such a suggestion gains plausi
bility from the undeniable fact that in the search for truth, in
the progressive discovery and proof of truth, many minds are
better than one ; that individuals learn from their fellow-men
most of what they know ; that mankind is in possession of an
accumulated heritage of truth (not, however, unmixed with error)
of which individuals are in varying degrees the sharers; and so on.
But, nevertheless, the suggestion will not bear analysis, and
cannot achieve the object for which it is made. For the attain
ment of truth and certitude is not the work of an impersonal
human intelligence, conceived after the manner of the Averroists ;
nor of human reason existing as a universal a parte rci, as extreme
realism would have it : nor do traditionalists mean anything like
that by the " raison generate " or " common sense " of the race.
The attainment of truth and certitude is the work of individual
human minds ; knowledge is an attribute only of individual minds.
If, therefore, there is not in human minds, taken individually, any
native power or capacity to attain to a certain knowledge of
truth, neither can such power or capacity be forthcoming in the
collectivity : if each of them is essentially unreliable, no conceiv
able collection of them can be reliable, much less infallible. But
it is the collection that traditionalists denote by "common sense,"
or " la raison generate ". By proclaiming, therefore, the power-
context, it makes to his own individual reason : part of that evidential appeal coming,
of course, from the fact that the judgment is generally accepted by mankind. II
he sees, on reflection, that there is adequate intrinsic evidence for its truth, and that
this is the reason why people generally assent to it, he will have satisfied himself
not only that the judgment in question is true, but that the common assent of man
kind to it, and to other similar judgments, is a reasonably safe and reliable test of
the truth of such judgments. But he must see at the same time that this latter test
does not supplant, but rather presupposes as ultimate, the intrinsic evidential appeal
of the judgment to the individual reason.
TRUTHS OF " COMMON SENSE " 307
lessness of the individual reason, they strike equally at the
universal or collective reason. And in fact they do disfigure it
and deprive it of the essential attributes of intelligence or ration
ality by proclaiming its function to be merely that of an organon
or vehicle for the transmission of a body of Divinely revealed
judgments, while denying to human reason individually, and
therefore also collectively, the right to demand or the power to
find any rational justification for its assents by scrutinizing the
evidence, whether intrinsic or extrinsic, for the truth of the judg
ments assented to. In ultimate analysis it is really an abdication
of reason on the part of the individual to assent to any judgment
merely because he finds everyone else assenting to it. For
each and for all alike the ulterior question must inevitably arise ;
Why do any of them or all of them assent to it ? And the answer
must be, either because they have rational grounds of evidence
for so assenting, or because they choose to assent in the absence
of such grounds, that is, blindly and unreasonably. In other
words, the ultimate choice must always be between a rational
assent based on grounds of objective intellectual evidence, or
a blind, instinctive assent which, in a being endowed with the
reflective faculty of intelligence, must inevitably terminate in
universal doubt and scepticism.