TRUTH.
К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1617 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101
102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 112 113 114 115 117 118
119 120 121 122 123 124 125 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135
138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148
Logical truth, therefore, is an attribute not of things in
the absolute, or of objects of thought, but of judgments, i.e. of
relations between objects of thought. The formal object of the
act of judgment is a relation of identity or diversity between two
formally distinct objective concepts or aspects of reality : i.e.
what the mind apprehends, through the act of judgment, is a
1 Cf. MGR. SENTROUL, La Verite et le progres du savoir, in the Revue neo-
scolastique, May and August, 191 1 (pp. 212-30, 305-28) : two very instructive
articles, in which, however, the author s definitions apply only to affirmative
judgments. Defining logical truth as " the conformity of a judgment with a real
identity" (p. 177), and the judgment itself as " a real identification" (p. 305), he
illustrates the latter description in the following terms: " The judgment (of the
ideal, or of the existential order) declares that a thing (intrinsically possible or
actually existing, and) signified by the subject (abstract or concrete, respectively) is
identical with the thing that is signified 1 y the predicate. Take, for instance, this
judgment of the ideal order : the triangle is a figure in which a circle can always be
inscribed. To assert that judgment is to assert that once a triangle is realized in
the existing world you have ipso facto a figure which is not only triangular (as the
subject itself already states) but is also endowed with the property signified by the
predicate. Or, take a judgment of the existential order : to assert that " this horse
is young " is to assert that there is here a single being which is both " horse" and
"young". ... It is in this sense that judgment is always a real identification.
We prefer the term real to the term objective which seems to refer to the formal ob
ject of a cognition rather than to the reality signified by the cognition, and which in
any case seems restricted rather to the identification proper to judgments of the ideal
order " (p. 305). " Judgments which are not of the ideal order we prefer to describe
as of the existential order rather than of the real order. The matter of designation
is of minor importance provided we make our meaning clear : that all judgments
ate real identifications, and are either of the ideal or of the existential order " (ibid.,
n. Cf. 10. JEANNIERE, op. cit., p. 310).
2 5 2 THEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
relation of real identity or of real diversity between the reality
signified by the subject, and that signified by the predicate, of
the judgment. Something " actually perceived or imagined re
veals itself to thought as identical with another object already
conceived by the intellect, so that the former must be placed
under the extension of the latter, and the latter applied to the
former. This attribution is the function of the act of judgment."
Such are the terms in which Mercier describes the affirmative
judgment. 1 And after explaining briefly the nature of the
" identity " or " agreement " expressed by the logical copula, 2 he
says that " logical truth characterizes the judgment when the
mind asserts the union or disunion of two terms in conformity
with objective truth : the judgment is true when the mind unites
terms which agree or disjoins terms which disagree ; in the
opposite event the judgment is erroneous ". 3 By the expression
"objective truth" in this statement Mercier means "ontological
truth," i.e. the reality itself as present or presented to the mind
and as having a nature which can be "understood," "known,"
" represented " only by the affirmative and negative judgments,
the real identifications and discriminations, which that nature
demands. 4 When the judgment, therefore, whether affirmative
or negative, the real identification or separation of objective
concepts or aspects of reality, takes place in conformity with the
real exigencies of the datum presented for interpretation, with
what its concrete reality demands as an intelligible representation
of it, then the judgment is true; otherwise it is false. "And if
we are finally asked," he continues, "what are these exigencies
whereby the subject demands from our intellects such or such
attributes, and not others, we would reply that they spring from
the indivisible unity proper to each subject and by virtue of which
it presents itself to the mind with a certain group of attributes,
rather than any other group, and consequently demands such and
1 Op. dt., 13, p. 20. His whole treatment of the subject ( 10-17) marks a
distinct advance from the traditional scholastic treatment which approached the
question from an exclusively dogmatic and synthetic standpoint.
2 Cf. Science of Logic, i., 78-80; 99-109. :! O/>. /., p. 26.
4 The author rightly observes (ibid., p. 24) that the objective or ontological
truth of reality implies a relation of reality to some mind. Apart from such relation
things have ontological truth only fundamentally or potentially, not actually or
formally. As St. Thomas says (De Veritate, Q. i., a. i), " Etiamsi intellectus
humanus non essct, adhuc res dicerentur verae in ordine ad intellectum divinum.
Sed si uterque intellectus, quod est impossibile, intclligeretur auferri, nullomodo
veritatis ratio remaneret ". Cf. Ontology, 41.
TRUTH AND EVIDENCE 253
such predicates to the exclusion of others?- But there reflection
reaches its limit : for, as St. Thomas somewhere remarks, to
demand why a man is a man is to ask an unmeaning question,
quaerere cur homo est homo est nihil quaerere ." 2
Thus, then, the reality with which the mind is conformed by
a true judgment is on the one hand extramental or objective in
the sense that it is something beyond, distinct from, and in
dependent of the judicial, interpretative, representative act itself; 3
but on the other hand it is this something not as standing out
of all cognitive relation to the knowing subject, but as present
or presented to the knowing subject : and, consequently, since
both terms of the truth-relation are consciously apprehended, the
task of justifying our reflex conviction that we know some at
least of our judgments to be true is at least not prima facie an
impossible task.
Nor can it be objected that on this view both terms of the
"truth" or "conformity" relation are subjective, and that there
fore all truth, all knowledge is subjective, which is Idealism.
One term (the subjective or mental term) of the relation is the
mental state produced by the judgment, or interpretation, or
" representation ". The other term is not a mental state, the state
produced by the " presentation " of the reality to consciousness ;
nor is it this "presentation" itself, for this presentation itself is
not an object but a process, just as the " representation " is not
an object but a process : the whole process, both of presenting
and representing, constitutes the esse ideale of the reality, or
gives the reality its esse ideale^ which esse ideale is not an object
1 C/. vol. i., 92.
z lbid., p. 25 (italics ours). The student will recognize in those sentences an
affirmation of the influence of objective "affinities" urged against Kant s formalism
(vol. i., 92, 93) ; and also of the doctrine that the truth of our judgments is de
termined, and our assent to them motived, by the ontological exigency of the pre
sented reality to have certain predicates affirmed or denied of it, in other words, by
" objective evidence ".
3 This holds good even when the realities which we interpret are our own judg
ments, or our other conscious, mental processes. For these processes are also
realities, and by introspective reflection we make them the objects of inquiry, in
vestigation, interpretation, judgment, etc. The distinctive feature of the judicial
act, the feature which characterizes it as a representation or interpretation of reality,
and which has been described as its " objective reference " or its " claim to truth "
(cf. Science of Logic, i., 79, 80) has been emphasized in many modern definitions.
Thus, BRADLEY defines judgment as " the act which refers an ideal content, re
cognized as such, to a reality beyond the act" ; and BOSANQUET, as " the reference
of a significant idea to a subject in reality by means of an identity of content be
tween them " (ibid., % 80).
2 5 4 THE OR V O F KNO 1 VL FDGE
of cognition or objection cognituui at all, but is only the psychic
means, -the medium quo, by which the reality is mentally appre
hended. The other term of the truth or knowledge relation, the
objective or real term, is the extramental reality itself present or
presented to consciousness immediately, i.e. without the inter
vention of any mentally fabricated product or object intervening
as a substitute or tertium quid between the knowing mind and
the known reality. And we have shown already that there is
absolutely no ground for supposing that in the process of pre
sentation or manifestation the reality is transformed or dis
figured by any mental forms of the knowing subject. The
reproach of Idealism against our definition of truth or true
knowledge therefore falls to the ground.
When a judgment is true, the identification or discrimination
which it makes is in conformity with what the intelligible nature
of the presented reality demands : this latter so appears to in
tellect that it reveals subject and predicate as aspects of it and
demands their identification, or as such that it demands the
exclusion of the predicate from the subject which represents it.
Not that the reality itself, apart from its relation or presence to
the intellect, is formally an identity of distinct aspects (subject
and predicate), or a unity which (as subject) formally excludes
some aspect of reality (as predicate) ; for these identities, dis
tinctions, comparisons, affirmations and denials are formally
logical relations, forms or modes of thought, modalities of the
judgment which is itself a form of thought. But that the reality
presented for interpretation has an objective, real, ontological
exigency, as intelligible, for representation by intellect through
the instrumentality of such relations : these have their founda
tion in the presented reality ; they are in it fundamentally,
potentially ; and it is precisely because of this that reality is
intelligible, i.e. capable of being known or understood through our
human modes of thought. We may err in judging, interpreting,
representing the real ; but when our judgments are true it is with
reality that they are in conformity.
Now Kant likewise recognizes the distinction between truth
and error in the judgments of our speculative reason (33, 125,
128-9). For him, too, the true judgment is the one that is in con
formity with something, something with which it ought to be in
conformity. He admits, moreover, that this something is the
same for all human minds, that the true judgment is neces-
TR UTH AND E VIDENCE 2 5 5
sarily and universally true because of its determination by,
and conformity with, this something. But the necessity and
universality are, as we have seen, subjective, because the "some
thing" which determines them is subjective. In his view the
" something " which is the standard of the conformity or truth
of our judgments is not reality. For reality itself, in its pre
sentation to the mind in perception and conception, is
" moulded " into " objects " by transcendental, a priori forms
which belong to the mind s own constitution. The true judg
ment, therefore, is the judgment which is in conformity with
these mental products or objects ; and it is in conformity with
these when it expresses what those transcendental , a priori mental
laws demand that the judgment should express. Truth, in the
sense of conformity of our judgments with reality, is unattainable
by the speculative reason, because reality is unknowable. But
truth in the sense of conformity of our judgments with the laws
which constitute our own understanding is attainable, because
these determining principles of reason, which likewise construct
or create the universe of intelligible phenomena or appearances,
are discoverable by a critical investigation of the a priori con
ditions of the possibility of speculative knowledge.
Our criticism of this view is simply that such knowledge is
riot worthy of the name. If the object with which the true judg
ment is conformed, and into which it is supposed to give an
insight, be not reality, then the judgment is not a form of know
ledge at all. Kant s theory that the objects which determine our
knowledge are not realities, but mental constructions, themselves
determined by a priori forms of the mind, we have already seen
to be fundamentally unsound and wholly indefensible. As
Jeanniere observes : x " The mental causality whereby we form
and compare concepts does not consist in constructing reality,
but in apprehending it through inadequate conceptions which
we so co-ordinate with one another, according to ontological
exigencies, that we gradually attain to the genuine knowledge
which we embody in real definitions ".
Logical truth, therefore, is an attribute not of things in
the absolute, or of objects of thought, but of judgments, i.e. of
relations between objects of thought. The formal object of the
act of judgment is a relation of identity or diversity between two
formally distinct objective concepts or aspects of reality : i.e.
what the mind apprehends, through the act of judgment, is a
1 Cf. MGR. SENTROUL, La Verite et le progres du savoir, in the Revue neo-
scolastique, May and August, 191 1 (pp. 212-30, 305-28) : two very instructive
articles, in which, however, the author s definitions apply only to affirmative
judgments. Defining logical truth as " the conformity of a judgment with a real
identity" (p. 177), and the judgment itself as " a real identification" (p. 305), he
illustrates the latter description in the following terms: " The judgment (of the
ideal, or of the existential order) declares that a thing (intrinsically possible or
actually existing, and) signified by the subject (abstract or concrete, respectively) is
identical with the thing that is signified 1 y the predicate. Take, for instance, this
judgment of the ideal order : the triangle is a figure in which a circle can always be
inscribed. To assert that judgment is to assert that once a triangle is realized in
the existing world you have ipso facto a figure which is not only triangular (as the
subject itself already states) but is also endowed with the property signified by the
predicate. Or, take a judgment of the existential order : to assert that " this horse
is young " is to assert that there is here a single being which is both " horse" and
"young". ... It is in this sense that judgment is always a real identification.
We prefer the term real to the term objective which seems to refer to the formal ob
ject of a cognition rather than to the reality signified by the cognition, and which in
any case seems restricted rather to the identification proper to judgments of the ideal
order " (p. 305). " Judgments which are not of the ideal order we prefer to describe
as of the existential order rather than of the real order. The matter of designation
is of minor importance provided we make our meaning clear : that all judgments
ate real identifications, and are either of the ideal or of the existential order " (ibid.,
n. Cf. 10. JEANNIERE, op. cit., p. 310).
2 5 2 THEOR Y OF KNO W LEDGE
relation of real identity or of real diversity between the reality
signified by the subject, and that signified by the predicate, of
the judgment. Something " actually perceived or imagined re
veals itself to thought as identical with another object already
conceived by the intellect, so that the former must be placed
under the extension of the latter, and the latter applied to the
former. This attribution is the function of the act of judgment."
Such are the terms in which Mercier describes the affirmative
judgment. 1 And after explaining briefly the nature of the
" identity " or " agreement " expressed by the logical copula, 2 he
says that " logical truth characterizes the judgment when the
mind asserts the union or disunion of two terms in conformity
with objective truth : the judgment is true when the mind unites
terms which agree or disjoins terms which disagree ; in the
opposite event the judgment is erroneous ". 3 By the expression
"objective truth" in this statement Mercier means "ontological
truth," i.e. the reality itself as present or presented to the mind
and as having a nature which can be "understood," "known,"
" represented " only by the affirmative and negative judgments,
the real identifications and discriminations, which that nature
demands. 4 When the judgment, therefore, whether affirmative
or negative, the real identification or separation of objective
concepts or aspects of reality, takes place in conformity with the
real exigencies of the datum presented for interpretation, with
what its concrete reality demands as an intelligible representation
of it, then the judgment is true; otherwise it is false. "And if
we are finally asked," he continues, "what are these exigencies
whereby the subject demands from our intellects such or such
attributes, and not others, we would reply that they spring from
the indivisible unity proper to each subject and by virtue of which
it presents itself to the mind with a certain group of attributes,
rather than any other group, and consequently demands such and
1 Op. dt., 13, p. 20. His whole treatment of the subject ( 10-17) marks a
distinct advance from the traditional scholastic treatment which approached the
question from an exclusively dogmatic and synthetic standpoint.
2 Cf. Science of Logic, i., 78-80; 99-109. :! O/>. /., p. 26.
4 The author rightly observes (ibid., p. 24) that the objective or ontological
truth of reality implies a relation of reality to some mind. Apart from such relation
things have ontological truth only fundamentally or potentially, not actually or
formally. As St. Thomas says (De Veritate, Q. i., a. i), " Etiamsi intellectus
humanus non essct, adhuc res dicerentur verae in ordine ad intellectum divinum.
Sed si uterque intellectus, quod est impossibile, intclligeretur auferri, nullomodo
veritatis ratio remaneret ". Cf. Ontology, 41.
TRUTH AND EVIDENCE 253
such predicates to the exclusion of others?- But there reflection
reaches its limit : for, as St. Thomas somewhere remarks, to
demand why a man is a man is to ask an unmeaning question,
quaerere cur homo est homo est nihil quaerere ." 2
Thus, then, the reality with which the mind is conformed by
a true judgment is on the one hand extramental or objective in
the sense that it is something beyond, distinct from, and in
dependent of the judicial, interpretative, representative act itself; 3
but on the other hand it is this something not as standing out
of all cognitive relation to the knowing subject, but as present
or presented to the knowing subject : and, consequently, since
both terms of the truth-relation are consciously apprehended, the
task of justifying our reflex conviction that we know some at
least of our judgments to be true is at least not prima facie an
impossible task.
Nor can it be objected that on this view both terms of the
"truth" or "conformity" relation are subjective, and that there
fore all truth, all knowledge is subjective, which is Idealism.
One term (the subjective or mental term) of the relation is the
mental state produced by the judgment, or interpretation, or
" representation ". The other term is not a mental state, the state
produced by the " presentation " of the reality to consciousness ;
nor is it this "presentation" itself, for this presentation itself is
not an object but a process, just as the " representation " is not
an object but a process : the whole process, both of presenting
and representing, constitutes the esse ideale of the reality, or
gives the reality its esse ideale^ which esse ideale is not an object
1 C/. vol. i., 92.
z lbid., p. 25 (italics ours). The student will recognize in those sentences an
affirmation of the influence of objective "affinities" urged against Kant s formalism
(vol. i., 92, 93) ; and also of the doctrine that the truth of our judgments is de
termined, and our assent to them motived, by the ontological exigency of the pre
sented reality to have certain predicates affirmed or denied of it, in other words, by
" objective evidence ".
3 This holds good even when the realities which we interpret are our own judg
ments, or our other conscious, mental processes. For these processes are also
realities, and by introspective reflection we make them the objects of inquiry, in
vestigation, interpretation, judgment, etc. The distinctive feature of the judicial
act, the feature which characterizes it as a representation or interpretation of reality,
and which has been described as its " objective reference " or its " claim to truth "
(cf. Science of Logic, i., 79, 80) has been emphasized in many modern definitions.
Thus, BRADLEY defines judgment as " the act which refers an ideal content, re
cognized as such, to a reality beyond the act" ; and BOSANQUET, as " the reference
of a significant idea to a subject in reality by means of an identity of content be
tween them " (ibid., % 80).
2 5 4 THE OR V O F KNO 1 VL FDGE
of cognition or objection cognituui at all, but is only the psychic
means, -the medium quo, by which the reality is mentally appre
hended. The other term of the truth or knowledge relation, the
objective or real term, is the extramental reality itself present or
presented to consciousness immediately, i.e. without the inter
vention of any mentally fabricated product or object intervening
as a substitute or tertium quid between the knowing mind and
the known reality. And we have shown already that there is
absolutely no ground for supposing that in the process of pre
sentation or manifestation the reality is transformed or dis
figured by any mental forms of the knowing subject. The
reproach of Idealism against our definition of truth or true
knowledge therefore falls to the ground.
When a judgment is true, the identification or discrimination
which it makes is in conformity with what the intelligible nature
of the presented reality demands : this latter so appears to in
tellect that it reveals subject and predicate as aspects of it and
demands their identification, or as such that it demands the
exclusion of the predicate from the subject which represents it.
Not that the reality itself, apart from its relation or presence to
the intellect, is formally an identity of distinct aspects (subject
and predicate), or a unity which (as subject) formally excludes
some aspect of reality (as predicate) ; for these identities, dis
tinctions, comparisons, affirmations and denials are formally
logical relations, forms or modes of thought, modalities of the
judgment which is itself a form of thought. But that the reality
presented for interpretation has an objective, real, ontological
exigency, as intelligible, for representation by intellect through
the instrumentality of such relations : these have their founda
tion in the presented reality ; they are in it fundamentally,
potentially ; and it is precisely because of this that reality is
intelligible, i.e. capable of being known or understood through our
human modes of thought. We may err in judging, interpreting,
representing the real ; but when our judgments are true it is with
reality that they are in conformity.
Now Kant likewise recognizes the distinction between truth
and error in the judgments of our speculative reason (33, 125,
128-9). For him, too, the true judgment is the one that is in con
formity with something, something with which it ought to be in
conformity. He admits, moreover, that this something is the
same for all human minds, that the true judgment is neces-
TR UTH AND E VIDENCE 2 5 5
sarily and universally true because of its determination by,
and conformity with, this something. But the necessity and
universality are, as we have seen, subjective, because the "some
thing" which determines them is subjective. In his view the
" something " which is the standard of the conformity or truth
of our judgments is not reality. For reality itself, in its pre
sentation to the mind in perception and conception, is
" moulded " into " objects " by transcendental, a priori forms
which belong to the mind s own constitution. The true judg
ment, therefore, is the judgment which is in conformity with
these mental products or objects ; and it is in conformity with
these when it expresses what those transcendental , a priori mental
laws demand that the judgment should express. Truth, in the
sense of conformity of our judgments with reality, is unattainable
by the speculative reason, because reality is unknowable. But
truth in the sense of conformity of our judgments with the laws
which constitute our own understanding is attainable, because
these determining principles of reason, which likewise construct
or create the universe of intelligible phenomena or appearances,
are discoverable by a critical investigation of the a priori con
ditions of the possibility of speculative knowledge.
Our criticism of this view is simply that such knowledge is
riot worthy of the name. If the object with which the true judg
ment is conformed, and into which it is supposed to give an
insight, be not reality, then the judgment is not a form of know
ledge at all. Kant s theory that the objects which determine our
knowledge are not realities, but mental constructions, themselves
determined by a priori forms of the mind, we have already seen
to be fundamentally unsound and wholly indefensible. As
Jeanniere observes : x " The mental causality whereby we form
and compare concepts does not consist in constructing reality,
but in apprehending it through inadequate conceptions which
we so co-ordinate with one another, according to ontological
exigencies, that we gradually attain to the genuine knowledge
which we embody in real definitions ".