262 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE

К оглавлению1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 
17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 
34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 
51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67 
68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84 
85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101 
102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 111 112 113 114 115 116 117 118 
119 120 121 122 123 124 125 126 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135 
136 137 138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148 149 150 151 152 
153 154 155 156 157 158 159 160 161 162 163 164 165 166 167 168 169 
170 171 172 173 174 175 176 177 178 179  181 182 183 184 185 186 
187 188 189 190 191 192 193 194 195 196 197 198 199 200 201 202 203 
204 205 206 207 208 209 210 211 212 213 214 215 216 217 218 219 220 
221 222 223 224 225 226 227 228 229 230 231 232 233 234 235 236 237 
238 239 240 241 242 243 244 245 246 247 248 249 250 251 252 253 254 
255 256 257 258 259 260 261 262 263 264 265 266 267 268 269 270 271 
272 273 274 275 276 277 278 279 280 281 282 283 284 285 286 287 288 
289 290 291 292 293 294 295 296 297 298 299 300 301 302 303 304 305 
306 307 308 309 310 311 312 313 314 315 316 317 318 319 320 321 322 
323 324 325 326 327 328 329 330 331 332 333 334 335 336 337 338 339 
340 

 

over and above the things which act and react, because it

is invisible as well as intangible. But though our senses

cannot perceive it, our intellect can and does. When we

knock a nail into a board with a hammer, it is simply

nonsense to tell us that because we can only perceive the

nail, the board, and the hammer, we cannot know that we

exert a force which makes the nail go in.

 

But there is one instance in which a man can be aware,

through his actual feelings, not only of an antecedent and

consequent, and the relation of causality between them, but

also the very bond or nexus between them may be not only

distinctly perceived by our intellect, but its inflow actually

felt. This is whenever a man is in doubt about what course

to pursue owing to his being drawn in different directions

by different motives. Then the inflow and force of the con-

flicting motives acting upon his own mind can be distinctly

perceived by him. This instance is substantially the same

as that we before adduced with respect to our perception of

the emission of " force." We can all also perceive force

when anything resists our will. Thus, let us suppose that

the stem of a small tree has been partly sawn through, and

that we then try whether we can pull it down. If the

coherence of the part not sawn through is still very great,

we may have to exert all our force to overcome it. When

at last we have succeeded, and are exhausted with our efforts,

we may feel very vividly that anyone who denied we had

caused the tree to come down must be as great a lunatic as

anyone who denied the real objective existence of the tree

itself.

 

But it may be said (we know it may, because such follies

have actually been printed) that, though we may be conscious

of our own force, we err if we assert efficient causation in

any other instance. In fact, Mr. Herbert Spencer has said

that by such an assertion we make the great mistake of

 

attributing to inanimate things feelings like those we ex-

perience in making such physical efforts. Surely greater

nonsense has rarely been written. Let us suppose the

partly-sawn-through tree to be not even touched by us, but

that a gale has sprung up which, after having swayed it to

and fro, breaks it off, and prostrates it, just as we have

supposed it prostrated by human efforts. Are we not then

to say that the wind has exerted as much force as was ours ?

Can we not say this confidently, without being such idiots as

to attribute " feelings " to the wind ?

 

Truly, then, we have in our observations and experiments

with external things, as well as in the consciousness of our

own efforts and the action of motives on our minds, actual

experience of causation, while, as we have seen, a very

moderate study of the matter suffices to show us that the

law of causation is a necessary and universal truth which

carries with it its own evidence.

 

A clear perception of the law of causation gives efficient

support to a great principle, without which all science would

be absolutely impossible. This is the law of the Uniformity

of Nature* It is true that the ordinary experience of man-

kind makes men perfectly contented that things will take

their normal course, e.g. y that the sun will daily rise and set,

and that any tool dropped from the hand will at once fall

towards the ground unless otherwise upheld. In circum-

stances which seem to recur under, so far as we can see, the

same conditions as those wherein they occurred before, we

naturally expect the same results to ensue as we before

met with ; and such expectations are fulfilled.

 

Nevertheless, mere common sense and human testimony

cannot suffice, any more than the experience of any indi-

vidual can suffice, to show that the uniformity of nature

is, and must always be, positively certain and absolute.

 

* See ante, p. 1 06.

 

 

over and above the things which act and react, because it

is invisible as well as intangible. But though our senses

cannot perceive it, our intellect can and does. When we

knock a nail into a board with a hammer, it is simply

nonsense to tell us that because we can only perceive the

nail, the board, and the hammer, we cannot know that we

exert a force which makes the nail go in.

 

But there is one instance in which a man can be aware,

through his actual feelings, not only of an antecedent and

consequent, and the relation of causality between them, but

also the very bond or nexus between them may be not only

distinctly perceived by our intellect, but its inflow actually

felt. This is whenever a man is in doubt about what course

to pursue owing to his being drawn in different directions

by different motives. Then the inflow and force of the con-

flicting motives acting upon his own mind can be distinctly

perceived by him. This instance is substantially the same

as that we before adduced with respect to our perception of

the emission of " force." We can all also perceive force

when anything resists our will. Thus, let us suppose that

the stem of a small tree has been partly sawn through, and

that we then try whether we can pull it down. If the

coherence of the part not sawn through is still very great,

we may have to exert all our force to overcome it. When

at last we have succeeded, and are exhausted with our efforts,

we may feel very vividly that anyone who denied we had

caused the tree to come down must be as great a lunatic as

anyone who denied the real objective existence of the tree

itself.

 

But it may be said (we know it may, because such follies

have actually been printed) that, though we may be conscious

of our own force, we err if we assert efficient causation in

any other instance. In fact, Mr. Herbert Spencer has said

that by such an assertion we make the great mistake of

 

attributing to inanimate things feelings like those we ex-

perience in making such physical efforts. Surely greater

nonsense has rarely been written. Let us suppose the

partly-sawn-through tree to be not even touched by us, but

that a gale has sprung up which, after having swayed it to

and fro, breaks it off, and prostrates it, just as we have

supposed it prostrated by human efforts. Are we not then

to say that the wind has exerted as much force as was ours ?

Can we not say this confidently, without being such idiots as

to attribute " feelings " to the wind ?

 

Truly, then, we have in our observations and experiments

with external things, as well as in the consciousness of our

own efforts and the action of motives on our minds, actual

experience of causation, while, as we have seen, a very

moderate study of the matter suffices to show us that the

law of causation is a necessary and universal truth which

carries with it its own evidence.

 

A clear perception of the law of causation gives efficient

support to a great principle, without which all science would

be absolutely impossible. This is the law of the Uniformity

of Nature* It is true that the ordinary experience of man-

kind makes men perfectly contented that things will take

their normal course, e.g. y that the sun will daily rise and set,

and that any tool dropped from the hand will at once fall

towards the ground unless otherwise upheld. In circum-

stances which seem to recur under, so far as we can see, the

same conditions as those wherein they occurred before, we

naturally expect the same results to ensue as we before

met with ; and such expectations are fulfilled.

 

Nevertheless, mere common sense and human testimony

cannot suffice, any more than the experience of any indi-

vidual can suffice, to show that the uniformity of nature

is, and must always be, positively certain and absolute.

 

* See ante, p. 1 06.